. Cr FRAGILE DOES NOT CIRCULATE Carnell University Cibrary Ithaca, New York “Presi cent farrands ss. 2 | The date shows when this volume was taken. AVea*8e50., “id Re HOME USE RULES All books subject to recall Cornefl University Library All borrowers must regis- ter in the library to borrow B945.K66 U5 books for hame use. SESS Naini turned at end of college | 3 year for inspection and olin Pees repairs. = Limited books must be returned within the four weck limit and not renewed. e ji ers 0 FRAGILE DOES NO CIRCULATE t a, t ao Students must return sll kooks before leaving town. Officers should arrange for the return of books wanted during their absence from town. MAY-2-7435S-E-R FRAGILE PAPER Please handle this book Volumes of periodicals and of pamphlets are held in the library as much as possible. For special pur- poses they are given out for 7 a limited time. with care, as the paper is brittle. verifiable - { i | Be b) : a eT 2 att i” “4, IF Cd Pm y ao r 2 and gift books, when the Borrowers should not use their library privileges for the benefit of other persons. Books of special value bi rp r Pa : ; ase i giver wishes it, . fy A Wor Ty 1 OdF Scien o A , me Readers are asked to Wit “ ag 983, f port all cases of soles marked or mutilated. te ell Do AAPPReface books by marks and writing. - Professor of Philosophy, Columbia University MORRIS LLEWELLYN COOKE, Consulting Engineer, Philadelphia This book solves all problems of why, how, what, in science, religion, and philosophy. Or, it gives an intelligible and unified statement of the fundamentals of all things, and applies that to everyday life. It is addressed to the average educated man, but is designed to meet the requirements of experts in various branches. The book is experimentally verifiable. Some of the particular things the book does are:- Shows intelligihly what electricity, light, matter, energy, etc., are. Gives birth, life, death of solar system. Shows how to get energy out of atoms, etc. Establishes a sound logic. The logic used by the ordinary man is right; that used by Aristotle and nearly all books is wrong. Removes the fundamental error from mathematics, and makes mathematics simple; proves Euclid’s ‘‘axiom” about parallels, and intelligibly solves the various problems of non-Euclidian and n-dimension space. Revises and unifies the eqnations of physics. Completes conventional “theories” of physics—about a dozen,—and makes a somewhat new one that is easier: vortex whirls. Shows how gravity works. Shows what is wrong with Newton's law of gravity, and why. Makes Einstein's theory actually intelligible—showing that it is one sort of possible language out of an infinite number of possible valid languages or logics. 'The book shows that everyday language (Enclid’s and Newton's and Christ’s) is valid, and the most economical and practical — and uses it. Extracts from the INTRODUCTIONS:- Dr. JORDAN, one of the leading scientists of the world, says:- “. .unique daring successful ... Mr. Klyce makes no attempt to solve any scientific problem by pure reason, but he would have us make rational use of the knowledge we possess.” Professor DEWEY, by many regarded as the leading living philosopher and logician, says:- “. . .The sincerity and power of the book, and the radical simplicity of its unifying idea give it every claim to a hearing. . I hope what has been said may indicate the extraordinary value of Mr. Klyce’s work for philosophers, and, in connection with the way in which he applies the formal unification outlined to the mathematical, natural and social sciences, to all persons inter- ested in reducing intellectual obfuscation and confusion. . : . . .Mr. Klyce’s book is remarkable, noteworthy. If experts in various lines shall find his special results as fruitful, as illuminating, as his general treatment of knowledge and technical philosophy has been to me, the remark just made will turn out to be altogether too moderate. Any remark of mine about the value of the book in anticipation of this result will seem intemperately extravagant.” That simple and easy physics is used in the last third of the book to solve qualitatively the more complicated human problems—those of age, growth, death, life, birth, sex, medicine, immortality, good and evil, freedom of will, religious experiences and ethics in general, money, taxes, business principles, value, etc. Proves that the Constitution is right, and shows what democracy is, and proves that it ig right and that all other forms of government and ‘legal’ law are wrong. Proves (verifiably, of course) the doctrines of Christ; disproves the essential ones of Paul and theologians. Mr. COOKE, a leading engineer, says:- “The world today needs broad generalizations, but even more it needs counsel as to their application to specific situations. This book fulfils both these requirements in a very special way. For this reason I am recommending it, not as a philosophical treatise, but as a text book with an everyday usefulness for al] those who are trying to bring some measure of reasonableness and order and effectiveness into our turbulent industria] life. . The book as a whole, in spite of its austere mecha- nics, is not hard reading. This does not mean that there are not places—in fact whole sections—which I made no effo1t to get and others which I read superficially. But the author has developed quite a knack of using words in not only a precise but a commonly accepted way, so that over a greater part of the journey, a lack of mathematical and scientitic training is not an insuperable handicap. . . Of course, if one readily understood and as readily agreed with everything in a book like this, it would be too simple a document to merit much attention. .. I will be much surprised if to most men a reading of ‘Universe’ will not make the struggle [of life] a far simpler matter than it usually seems to be.” Set up, printed, and published by S. KLYCE, Winchester, Mass. Publisher’s price, to everybody:- $2 plus postage FOSTAGE: op tou miles from Boston, Te; to 800, lOc; ec; to 1000 1800, 33c; b 20e; to 1400, 26c; to eyond, &8c. Bookstore price, $3 Cornell University Bleed ay) The original of this book Is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www. archive.org/details/cu31924029066343 UNIVERS E BY SCUDDER KLYCE WITH THREE INTRODUCTIONS BY DAVID STARR JORDAN Chancellor Emeritus, Stanford University JOHN DEWEY Professor of Philosophy, Columbia University MORRIS LLEWELLYN COOKE Consulting Engineer, Philadelphia Coryricut, 1921, sy ScuppER Ktiycr Copyright in Great Britam First Epirion. — 1000 copies. — Printed from type and no plates made: plates can be made by photographic processes later if they are needed. Set up, printed, and published by S. KLYCE Winchester, Massachusetts Publisher’s Price to everybody, $2 plus postage (Wt. 3 lbs.) Bookstore price, $3 (see Preface, §F i). 192) f / First Introduction by Joun Dewey. Second Introduction by Davin Srarr JoRDAN. Third Introduction by Morris LurweLtyn Cooke. Preface. —$_=_ InrropucrorY REMARKS. CHAPTER 1 Summary of contents and their character. II Order and relationship of contents. Part One. Formal unification; or Theory of Language. ll] Nature of the general problem and its conventional name; or, what apparent failure in unification requires reconcilement. IV Statement and proof of principles of langnage; ar, logic. V General statement and proof of how to apply language. VI Names for logic, and chief application of valid logic to men. VII Statement and proof of valid logic from additional points of view. VIII Mechanical model of language. 1X Theory of language in terms of physical science; or, general unification of “‘science.”’ CONTENTS + Parr Two. Concrete unification ; or Physical Science. CHAPTER X General principles, and general mechanicai theories, of science. XI General whirl mechanics. XII Astronomy. XIN) Light. XIV Electricity. XV Heat, chemistry, etc.; and summary of Part Two by practical applications. — Parr Turer. Spiritual Unification; or Humanics. XVI Biology. XVII Psychology. XVIII Ethies and economics. XIX Sociology and economics. Appendix A. Abbreviations. Appendix B. Periodic table of elements. Appendix C. Geologic time scale. Index. ERRATA The errors in this following first list are those which the reader can not readily see at once are errors, and see what is correct. The second error in the list was made only in about half the copies. S 42d line 8 Read stayed instead of stated. 74 line 832 Equation should be Density=MT-®. 76e line 14 do c=QmeT. 89b line 21. Read Reeve’s instead of Reeves’s. 9G6c line 2. + Read chapter instead of section. 98n line 34 Read or instead of of. 114d line 3 Read or instead of and. 132a line 9 Read lower instead of slower. 132e line 10 Read 1913 instead of 1903. 136c line 14 Read F instead of the second E. Fovtnote 168h-iii line 37 Read good instead of 2nd_ poor. do -v line 14 Read of instead of in. This second list is a list of paragraphs in which typographical errors occur that the reader can readily correct for himself if he not- ices them. In a number of the listed cases I caught the error myself and corrected it before printing all the 1000. 1 know that there are some more-technical] errors ] haven’t listed; and probably there are numbers of errors I haven’t found. 8S43ct, 44d, 47h. 49d, 50e, 59ne, 6Oi, 6la, 63c, running head p. G1, 72d, 74b, 76e, 78a, 80c, 81h, 83e, 84b, 85b, 86cdh, 90c, footnote 98d, 98g, 99ab, 100g, 101b, 104b, 112a, 113c, 11Gb, 118e, 120ik, 122], 12Gbg, 133e, 136c, 144hi, 145¢ (two), 146k, 147fg, 148b, 149jq, 151a, 158d (two), 155b, 161b, 162fj, footnote 166d, 166nr, 167), 168dmnp, 170k, footnote 172c, running head p. 233, 175c, 176b, foot- note 176d, 176e. lii UNIVERSE Dewey’s Introduction THREE INTRODUCTIONS FIRST INTRODUCTION by Joun Drwry Mr. Klyce has invited me to write some prefatory words for his book. In spite of my technical incompetency in physica] sciences and realizing the handicap that imposes upon me, I have gladly consented. For although the argu- ment of the book as a whole must finally stand or fall with the treatment of topics where my lack of knowledge makes it impossible for me to have a real judgment, the sincerity and power of the book, and the radical simplicity of its unifying idea give it every claim to a hearing. And judging from the parts where it is possible for me to follow intelligently, I have a strong presentiment the other parts do not go far wrong in substance:—-Mr. Klyce himself makes plenty of allowance for deviations in special points. Mr. Klyce says somewhere in effect that every reader of this book will have in the end to rewrite it for himself. My introductory remarks can not take any other form than re- writing that portion of Part One which sets forth the funda- mental logic—or method—of the book. He says that the book “‘unifies or qualitatively solves science, philosophy, and religion.’’ Many cultivated readers will be likely to stop right here. While they tolerate or laud classic philosophers for attempting such unification, they associate, with painfully good reason, contemporary profes- sions of such solutions with pretentious ignorance. To make such a claim is the common sign of the incompetent amateur in philosophy and science. My first rewriting is of this phrase. Mr. Klyce emphasizes qualitattve unification. He ex- pressly points out that concrete problems of science and practical life are solved only in living them intelligently. For the word qualitative, we may write the word formal, and contrast it with material unifications. Then we note that such attempts as are in unenviable repute owe their offensive arrogance to claiming material unification. | Every philoso- pher deals with the problem of formal unification, either positively or negatively. What is significant in this book is not, then, the claim of unification but the way it is worked out. Every reader knows how common are phrases that combine antithetical terms, terms that taken separately oppose each other. Examples of such pairs are:- rest and motion, space and time, matter and energy, potential and actual, analysis and synthesis, one and many, individual and society, common and proper noun, cause and effect, freedom and authority, quantity and quali- ty, prose and poetry, parts and whole, mind and body, flesh and spirit, God and nature, purpose and mechanism, static and dynamic; or upon a slightly more technical plane, dis- crete and continuous, substance and properties, elements and relations, existence and essence. Now the natural mind, the commonsense mind in the best usage of that ambiguous phrase, is not perplexed by those combinations of opposites. They seem natural, complementary; expression is incomplete without both. Philosophic reflection begins with an express noting of the opposition between the terms of such pairs. _‘It sets out to reconcile them, to get a qualitative or formal unification. Or it denies the possibility of any unification, and holds that all knowledge since it goes on in such terms as motion and rest, space and time, is relative.’’ Or, the apparatus of knowing gets between us and the things to be known. Or it gener- alizes the pairing off into a rigid dualism of the separate, in- dependent forces, substances, principles. Or, like Hegel, it takes the bull by the horns and declares that all ‘‘reality,”’ all ‘‘truth’’ is a union of contradictories. Now it is a conceivable hypothesis that commonsense is innocent of these contradictions because it always uses the terms with reference in a context, to mark or point out features in a situation, and with no other intent than calling attention to them, either as memoranda for one’s self or as guides for another. This supposition does not as yet explain the opposed character of the terms, or why they go in pairs. But it raises another interesting hypothesis. What would be the effect if some one else reflecting on the agencies of point- ing and marking forgot their directive use, and took them to convey something otherwise than as pointers to observations? May not this explain why the terms are effective in ordinary usage and stumbling blocks to the philosopher? This last paragraph is one way of rewriting another sen- tence of his Introductory Remarks which will give offense to some readers:- that the author’s method of complete formal solution has to do with a “‘mere trick of words.’’ Unfortu- nately, not all readers, or writers, take words as seriously as Mr. Klyce does. He himself points out that a mere word is but a passing sound or a patch of ink. What he is doing, as he clearly points out in §2de, is to investigate the fact that kuowledge is a statement or expression, and to investigate this fact by the same experimental methods that have hither- to been confined to the things stated or expressed. Now language as a machine of expression or statement is something quite different from a mere trick of words; and in §155 Mr. Klyce vividly depicts the psychology that makes him from time to time resort to such depreciatory phrases. The reader must balance it with the term ““absolute unification of science, philosophy, and religion,’’ as he is used to balancing the terms rest and motion, whole and parts. Let us return then to the hypothesis that in actual use names call attention to features of a situation; that they are tools for directing perception or experimental observations. The first thing to be noted is that the “‘situation’’ is referred to only in the (literally) most general way, as the limiting in- cluding thing within which specific things are pointed out. A gesture calls attention to a dog-fight. It doesn’t call at- tention to the town, to the world or the sun and its light or to the previous history of the animals or to the position and expectations of the observer. And if some special feature within the dog-fight is then pointed out, a broken leg, the fight itself is no longer specified. It takes care of itself. It is now the ‘‘situation’’ as the entire visible scene was form- erly the situation within which the fight was discriminated. The sttuatzon as such in short is taken for granted. IJ is not stated or expressed. It is implicit, not explicit. Yet it sup- plies meaning to all that is stated, pointed out, named. Its presence makes the difference between sanity and insanity. We may say if we will that it is ignored. But the ignoring is not the ignorance of denial. Ignoring means ‘“‘under- stood,’’ assumed as a matter of course as the background and foreground which gives intelligibility and state-ability to what is explicit, expressly pointed out. Now the implicit situation cannot (save arbitrarily; that is, by some agreement for a purpose) be stopped short of Everything. The setting, Dewey’s Introduction the implicit situation, shades off from the explicit, indefin- itely and continuously. **Everything’’ is understood, im- plied, then as the setting, or meaning-giving force, of what we explicitly say or state. Recur now to the actual naming or pointing. It discrimi- nates, distingnishes something; makes it explicit, states or expresses it. That which is pointed to gives the meaning of the word or directive gesture. But the lone thing pointed at has no meaning. We always distinguish one thing from something. Al] explicit names point out then a comparison- contrast of at least two things. A This by itself, as Mr. Klyce points ont, has no meaning. It is not an expression or statement, but merely another thing, a noise or figure. This explicitly implies That; Here explicitly implies There; Now, Then. In short, the simplest possible intelligible state- ment explicitly implies a number-of-things-related-together, while it implicitly implies a sum total, or an ‘Everything’ with which the related plurality of things is continuous. This is a trick’’ of language just as a watch may be called a trick of steel. It is the only way a thing can be done, in one case keeping time, in another case giving direction to observations of existence. Size and complexity in both cases may vary indefinitely; and substitutes may be found for steel, and different signs in language. But the way, the principle, re- mains the same. Here isthe qualitative or formal unification. This is one way in which one basic proposition of Mr. Klyce may be rewritten. This way of writing will probably appeal especially to those habituated to philosophical modes of writing. For it suggests that the problem of statement, or language, is identical with what in philosophical writing is called the epistemological problem, the problem of know- ledge. Science is the expression of experiments with things. It isn’t the things over again, nor is it simply the experi- ments. It is communication of them with their results in consistent form. The simplest and most objective way then to examine knowledge experimentally is to examine consistent expression or statement experimentally—to see what happens when we do or make it. The method as used by Mr. Klyce getsrid of an enormous amount of cumbrous and largely effete psychology. It cuts out an enormous mass of _ historical reminiscence that obstructs the path of one who approaches the subject in the traditional way. To philosophical readers (to those who use that particular dialect) I would point out the freshness and directness of Mr. Klyce’s method of ap- proach to the old problem of the nature of knowledge. This remark applies to his method irrespective of the re- sults he has obtained by its use. Let us now return to an inspection of these results. In any intelligible statement, from a gesture to a complete discourse on science, there are two kinds of implications, one implicit, the other explicit. The explicit implication is that of relations between ele- ments; that is, between distinguished parts. The implicit, understood or taken for granted is, ultimately, as we have seen nothing less than the universe or ‘‘Everything.’’ Now (1) this implicit implication is strictly ineffable. It cannot be stated. For it is required to give meaning to any statement. Yet it is convenient, and for consistent expres- sion of complex matters it is necessary, to have a term to re- fer to it. It is necessary to have a word which reminds us that whatever we explicitly state has this implicit, unstate- able, ineffable implication. Hence the terms which Mr. Klyce calls One words, like all, nothing, only, being, every, infinity, universe, whole, never, always. These words have no (definite) meaning. In philosophical terminology they are transcendental, noumenal, a_ priori. They are religious terms, like God, eternity, perfect rest or peace, complete salvation, An experimental realization of their meaning is UNIVERSE iv had only emotionally, and the emotion may be BOS ie thetic or in some cases mystic. Speaking in Dee terminology, we have here revealed the truth and the eae O the whole brood of absolutistic, transcendental philosop ae They have had a genuine experience of All, which is mee for the meaning of any consistent statement. But , ey ed sert that these Oze terms themselves have a meaning; a at they are terms of statement. Or if they are professional mystics, the ineffable character is recognized, but the experi- ence is regarded as a special, separated, not to say unique, experience, instead of what is implicit, in some degree of intensity, in every experience. (2) The other side of statement is distinctions-in-relations, Many words, and Relationship words. Here the ways of go- ing wrong hy failing to observe what wedo when we state or express or ‘know’ are more numerous. The most general and fundamental one is to turn the ignoring of the Every- thing or Universe (to take Mr. Klyce’s favorite term, tho to some it is too indicative of the starry heavens) which is equivalent to its implicit assertion into its explicit denial. This is the root of all kinds of phenomenalism, relativism, agnosticism. For it amounts to asserting that the very act of making known (expressing) mutilates reality, puts a veil or screen between us and reality, hides things-in-themselves from us, perverts it in bringing it within our grasp. This is the root of all agnosticism and subjectivism—the notion that the process of knowing intervenes between us and the things to be known. And Mr. Klyce’s examination of Statement shows that this notion is due to failure to grasp all that is done when we state; namely, refer to the Whole as the con- text within which what is explicitly stated. falls as constitut- ing its meaning. Every statement (or knowledge) fully realized in its im- port or logical form links us up with the Whole, instead of cutting us off from it. And this is true when the statement is materially wrong-~as every statement in its explicitness is bound to be in some degree. For some of its implicit junc- tions with the Whole may be rendered perceptible in further statements. If the statement is sincerely taken, they not only may but will be. Every intelligible statement contains within itself, in other words, the conditions of its own recti- > fication, provided we carry out the experiments it indicates. 1 think that those who appreciate the force of these remarks and who find them verified in their own experience will agree that Mr. Klyce understates rather than exaggerates the emo- tional relief and expansion that may come with it. Other fallacies which arise from failure to perceive fully what happens when we state or make known (to ourselves or others) are materialism and mechanism—as a wholesale "ism, that is. This arises from observing that parts are discrimi- nated and failing to observe that they are at the same time related. The problem of relations and elements is a familiar one in philosophical writings. Perhaps one need here only call attention to the likeness and unlikeness of Mr. Klyce’s treatment with that of Mr. Bradley. The latter also points out that every statement both analyzes and synthesizes, selects or partializes and also unifies. But he places those functions over against each other. Selection mutilates the living fullness of reality. Unification adds as it were insult to injury; it falsifies, for the selected parts are not as such capable of union. They unite only in the whole. From this property of statement (judgment, in Mr. Bradley’s language) he infers that everything we judge is compelled to take on the form of appearance, because it involves self-contradiction, and this cannot be found in reality. All this is suggestive of Mr. Klyce’s insistence upon iden- tity or “‘circular perception’”’ as the test of statement, and Vv UNIVERSE his pointing out of contradiction hetween the many and the one in every statement. But where Mr. Bradley ends, Mr. Klyce begins. He points out that this contradiction is itself contradicted by the assertion (indication) of the implicit Every- thing. The elements selected are so related in every intelligible statement as to constitute the Whole; or, the situation is so distinguished that it has an infinite number of elements. And infinity is again a reference to the Whole. This is the ‘verbal trick’’ in its simplest form. The infinite regress of relation and element which Mr. Bradley points out in judgment is to Mr. Bradley another sign that our know- ledge does not get beyond Appearance. Mr. Klyce shows that this infinite regress is the method hy which every state- ment indicates or refers to the Whole. It negates the seem- ing arbitrary selection of some parts by calling attention to the fact that the Whole has an infinite number of other parts: that is, is a whole.’ Another fallacy arises from confusing relationship terms with many or one terms. In this case, we get pseudo- idealism, pseudo-intellectualism, abstractionism in the sense which Mr. James so vividly condemned. Mr. Klyce refers as an instance to the fact that many writers dress up the re- lationship word truth in shining armor, and exploit emotions with it. All idealism of the self-conscious, professional type is of this nature; all idealism, that is to say, that opposes the ideal] to the actual, and throws contempt upon the actual and concrete; which sets up ideals as something above and too good for the common man in common experience. It is the aristocratic vice par excellence. The ideal is the Whole implicit (tho not implied in the ordinary logical sense of im- plication) as the meaning of every intelligible experience. Hegel doubtless saw this in a way, but made the typical idealistic error of supposing that the task of philosophy was to derive modes of statement superior in kind to those of commonsense and science in which the implicit whole should be rationally explicated. In fact, the philosopher has the humbler task of pointing to the fact that every consistent statement already refers to an ineffable whole. Realism, especially modern analytic realism, on the other hand, ig- nores entirely the implicit, and insists only upon logical im- plications; that is, relationships which can be made explicit. As a consequence its relations become only another and strange kind of things or parts. An atomism results which taken strictly forbids all statement whatever—as the Greek critics of a similar view long ago pointed out. A word may be added on Mr. Klyce’s elimination of the bugaboo of subjectivism. Mr. Klyce gets rid of it by start- ing with expression or statement as itself an objective fact which can be observed like any other event. His method may be said to assume or imply that expression is a ‘function’ of things just as heat is. But this assumption is, as Mr. Klyce points out, merely formal in both cases. The meaning of the ‘‘assumption’’ that heat or a statement is there (is happening) is not found ix the statement about heat or ex- pression but in the observation of the happening itself. A finger-board on the road does not materially assume anything about the town to which it points. It actually or materially does nothing but point. The only ‘‘assumption’’ is that if you take the road you will find what you will find; that 1In rewriting one part of Mr. Klyce from the standpoint of the traditional! problems of the theory of knowledge, I am doing him an injustice not only from the standpoint of the larger public not con- cerned with technical philosophy but from the standpoint of profes- sional philosophers. For reference to the positive development of implications of space, time, energy, units of science, and the formu- lae for their relations, in which Mr. Klyce makes his formal unifica- tion fruitful is omitted. Jordan’s Introduction which you find is alone the real meaning of the sign-board. The sign may lie; Mr. Klyce may be mistaken. But the only way to find out either thing is to take the path indi- cated. In the case of the book this means to observe, with the guidance of its author, the thing or happening called ex- pression. It takes a considerable amount of skill and a large degree of vision and good will to follow the road, but that is all. I hope what has been said may indicate the extraordinary value of Mr. Klyce’s work for philosophers, and, in connec- tion with the way in which he applies the formal unification outlined to the mathematical, natural and social sciences, to all persons interested in reducing intellectual obfuscation and confusion. Many thinkers have had the laudable ambition of exhibiting the connection of science and philosophy with commonsense. But usually they have taken commonsense to mean a mixture of the operation of sound sense with a body of inherited engrained traditions and sophistications. Mr. Klyce has taken commonsense in its radical and simplest form, the form of stating or making anything known. He has himself pointed out the reason why his thought is not always easy to follow. The most difficult thing in the world to learn to see is the obvious, the familiar, the universally taken for granted. Taken asa sketch ofa certain way of discovering the meaning of knowledge in general and in its typical branches, Mr. Klyce’s book is remarkable, note- worthy. If experts in various lines shall find his special re- sults as fruitful, as illuminating, as his general treatment of knowledge and technical philosophy has been to me, the re- mark just made will turn out to be altogether too moderate. Any remark of mine about the value of the book in anticipa- tion of this result will seem intemperately extravagent. After the result, it will, fortunately, be quite unnecessary. Joun Dewey. SECOND INTRODUCTION by Davin STARR JORDAN The unique treatise for which I have been asked to write a few words in introduction impresses me as a daring and successful effort to aid straight thinking by the accurate use of language. Its centra] purpose is to bring into the realm of Science the philosophical conception that all that exists is in a sense of one piece,—infmite variety embraced within infinite unity. | Thus the Universe may be looked on as a majestic Federation of Energies, an infinite machine in which all parts fit and cooperate. Oneness, however, does not imply tangible sameness, though some apostles of Monism have insisted that underly- ing unity inevitably postulates at least some measure of ob- jective identity—as of matter and force, for example,—or more concretely, of all the chemical elements, one with another. But to be fundamentally “‘at one’’ does not neces- sitate any such sameness. Matter and force must comple- ment each other, in some positive sense, as the key fits the lock. Indeed there are numberless intimate relations which do not necessarily involve identity of origin, form and sub- stance. In a harmonious universe (however we may describe it) there might be (and we can know only by observing) a million definitely distinct chemical elements, not interchange- able and not derived from Haeckel’s fancied *’Protyl,’’ or any other primitive world stuff, whether matter or spirit. As to this and to al] other questions of fact, we shal] never know the answer until we find it out by looking. Moreover, the conception of the unity of the Universe need not ever Jordan’s Introduction reduce it to a single substance, nor even to a single definite purpose. Pluralism (multiplicity in unity) is as true as one- ness, in the meaning given by William James’s assertion :- “‘No one can question that the Universe isin some sense one, but the whole point lies in what that one is.’”’ Science is hnman experience tested and set in order; any belief which neither demands nor permits verification lies outside of Science. All propositions which can be proved by deduction or even proved completely (see §35 of the book), belong to the realm of expression or Logic, not to Science, — conclusions being involved in premises. Pure mathematics, for instance, is the logic of number and space, and its dem- onstrations, however intricate, are derived from its defini- tions. Similarly, a definition of the Universe can be framed in such a way as to make its unity self-evident;—in fact no other definition that is self-consistent is possible: but no scientific conclusion can be deduced from proof thus obtained. Details of reality—matter, force and life—would be nonearer demonstration than before, for these we know only from the coordinated results of hnman dealings with them. Knowledge, never complete, may be relatively exact or inexact according to the sufficiency of our data. Jn no field has Science yet reached completion,—and it is in the nature of things impossible that it ever can. It sees some things very definitely; but the unknown lies as a trackless wilder- ness on every hand. As details accumulate, generalizations are possible—and even prophecy with some degree of cer- tainty. In Physics, Chemistry, Astronomy, relative ex- actness prevails. The simpler the factors involved, the more definite our mastery. Obstacles in the relatively exact sciences are mainly our human limitations. The enormously distant and the extremely small elude precise observations; star and electron baffle alike; the bulk of the Universe is beyond our definite seeing. ‘“‘Time is as long as space is wide,’’ and no one can conceive a limit to either. The sciences concerned with life deal also with the ele- ments of matter and force, but in highly varying relations. In any biological problem, conditions due to the relative po- sition and relation of atoms and molecules, of cells and tis- sues, of organisms and environment, are visibly varied almost to infinity; data of one sort or another everywhere abound, but the more we have, the more we see we need. Untested problems crowd on every solution. In biology, therefore, to a degree greater than in the more exact sciences we cannat know what we know or what we do not know with complete- ness or ultimate precision. The only fina] test of a supposed fact is found in our ability to proveit by trusting our lives to it, or to the method by which it is gained. Simply to demonstrate that a propo- sition will “‘work’’—that is, ““muddle along’”’ after a fashion —is not enough; in all its parts it must stand a supreme test, that of “‘liveableness.’? Such a direct and conclusive proof, however, is not available in all life’s complex and im- mediately pressing situations. The next resource is to test the method behind the conclusion. The aggregate of know- ledge, so tested, constitutes Science, which then becomes the guide to conduct, though never infallible, because never complete. In default of personal experimental knowledge as to matters of fact or ideals of conduct we make the best we can of the conclusions of others, trusting to the strength of the method by which the conclusions are reached. We thus have an acceptable hypothesis on which to act until the returns from personal experience begin to come in. Mr. Klyce makes no attempt to solve any scientific prob- lem by pure reason, but he would have us make rational use of the knowledge we possess. As to the fundamental! co- ordination of all which exists, known or unknown,—any UNIVERSE vi consistent use of the word Universe implicitly asserts it. Man himself is able with fair success to make his way in the Cosmos; obviously then he is not utterly alien. Not only does his continued existence prove him not alien, but further- more, by taking thought, he can make headway against the forces of nature and thus in some degree shape his own ca- reer. A similar line of argument is shown to apply to every concrete thing of which we are cognizant. The burden of disproof of Mr. Klyce’s thesis lies on him who, within the confines of the Universe, can conceive anything—matter, spirit, life, space, or time—which lies outside it. Davip Starr JoRDAN. Stanford University, California, March 20, 1920. THIRD INTRODUCTION by Morris Liurwe_ityn Cooke The world today needs broad generalizations, but even more it needs counsel as to their application to specific situa- tions. This book fulfils both these requirements in a very special way. For this reason I am recommending it, not as a philosophical treatise, but as a text book with an everyday usefulness for all those who are trying to bring some measure of reasonableness and order and effectiveness into our turbu- lent industrial life. Industry is not only still in the making, but it is in its infancy rather than its adolescence. Just as we begin to realize that civilization is dependent on industry for its very ex- istence we have come to see that this same industry is really not related to Life in any vital way. It is a perilous position and no one claims that the path ahead is at all clearly de- fined. The perpetnity of our institutions seems to depend on whether in a generation or two we can come to have a better understanding of this Juggernaut we have created. For it is daily more apparent that all will not be well in the world until each unit of the structure of industry is sympa- thetically related to every other and to industry as a whole, and that industry itself must understand in some measure its relation to Ultimate Reality. Our industry has been very largely a matter of trading. But the barter hasis is disappearing with the advance of science. More and more it is the trained engineer or the man with engineering training who holds the key positions in industry and commerce. But Engineering in the past concerned itself very largely with things. Up to a genera- tion ago engineers were for the most part either designers or constructors of things, i.e., bridges, dams, railroads, power plants, etc. Then the operation of these agencies began to be included within the scope of Engineering. Only quite recently has it come to be considered that in the operation of most industrial enterprises the engineering method is apt to be the most effective. Thus has been developed the engineer- ing of men, sometimes called “human engineering’ in con- trast with what has been the more technical engineering of materials. This book, from the business man’s or engineer’s point of view, undertakes to establish a proved and verifiable scientific basis for this new branch of engineering which some people prefer to call ‘efficiency engineering.’ The book as a whole, in spite of its austere mechanics, is not hard reading. This does not mean that there are not places—in fact whole sections—which I made no effort to get and others which | read superficially. But the author has developed quite a knack of using words in not only a precise but « commonly accepted way, so that over a greater vii UNIVERSE part of the journey, a lack of mathematical and scientific training is not an insuperable handicap. The author advises readers—especially at certain places—not to work too hard to get out al] the meaning. I dare say that the average reader who will approach the book in this spirit will get about all the author expects anyone to get on first reading and will then be tempted to start all over again. The reader should be on guard against being unduly stirred by the author’s mannerisms. In some of his com- ments on “‘theologians and Jawyers’’ for instance it seems to me that he lapses from his general technique of tolerant expres- sion and philosophy. Of course, if one readily understood and as readily agreed with everything in a book like this, it would be too simple a document to merit much attention. It is altogether impossible to epitomize the conclusions of any such book. But among many pithy phrases which Mr. Klyce has coined, ““balanced co-operation’’ stands out as one having special significance in the industrial field. It means something more than doing unto the other fellow what you would have him do to you. It seems to involve a measure of action and reaction as between units and groups, which will in every instance be conducive to well-being and growth all around. During the War it would frequently have sug- gested to organized labor the advantage of restraint in push- ing wage claims, and at the present moment it should give pause to those employers who tend to push their opposition to labor unions beyond the checking of their obviously un- toward tendencies. According to the author, democracy al- lows or requires that each side to any discussion re-act to the other. This is the exact opposite of the “‘We have nothing to disenss’’ or the ““Public be damned’’ attitude. After all, whether you are king or labor leader, business man or priest, your master decision is as to whether you will be—to use the language of the book—a ‘“‘dualist and an autocrat’’ or whether, constantly studying the unity of all modes and expression of life, you will seek through “‘bal- anced co-operation’’ to participate in the execution of pur- poses and a Purpose not your own. Mr. Klyce has shown a ‘‘capacity for infinite pains’’ in carrying his main thesis into so many different scientific realms and there seeking to establish its truth. Too fre- quently we have been asked to take judgments on scientific, religious and philosophical matters from men who having grown up in one group inherit points of view—even prejudices —which would be dissipated by a larger outlook on life. Vernon Kellogg says that while ‘“The biologist does have a certain positive knowledge of some conditions or factors that do help to determine the course of human life,’’ it is also true that ‘‘the course of human life is partly determined by a set of conditions which are, so far, at least, quite out- side the specia] knowledge of the biologist. | He can guess and wonder about them, just as other people do, but he has no right to claim that he knows about them.’’ The same re- mark obviously can profitably be made about any specialist. Also, to any specialist is apt to come the moment—and and it is one of possible, even soul-racking, disillusionment —when the inadequacy of a narrow slant on life becomes Preface §Ab apparent. The more sincere the worker and the more funda- mental his work the deeper the yearning to relate the indi- vidual effort to the totality of things. The surest way to give dignity to a simple act is to relate it to a purposeful life. The surest way to endow our industria] system with vitality is to scheme it out in harmony with all Life—to make the paying of a wage and the doing of the day’s task in some genuine fashion God’s service—to link them up with the Ultimate Purpose. Of course a great industry will only result from the activities of great men. Most industrial leaders impress us as being literally worn out fighting against a flood of isolated facts and ideas. We need the unifying thought of this book. To be effective we need above all to make our lives simple. Men vary in their mental capacity, but it is undoubtedly true that some men with great capacities are not the match for men of ordinary abilities who ““see life steadily and see it whole.’’ I will be much surprised if to most men a read- ing of ““Universe’’ will not make the struggle a far simpler matter than it usually seems to be. The very familiarity which grows ont of usage has af- forded in the past in all too generous measure, the authority which we humans require to make us happy in our work and play. But in so many ways—through education, through a heightened individualism, and more immediately through the shake-up of the Great War—the mass of men are questioning all our procedures in a way heretofore unheard of. In the depths of the mines, in the vast silences where the lumber- jacks toil, on the seas and in our great manufacturing plants near the centers of population, men are counseling together as never before, on the meaning of life and the meaning of industry and the relation of one to the other. The idea that anyone knows in the old particularistic sense is gone. Have we not read only yesterday of Einstein and that theory of relativity that ““upsets’’ one of the surest rocks on which our whole structure of knowledge has been built? We know now as never before perhaps that, to use the language of this book, ‘“There is no exact science.’’ And yet our respect for science deepens and our sense of depend- ence upon it has become altogether profound. This under- standing of the place of science in industry and life is no longer confined to the schools. The nations begin to appre- ciate the hopelessness of preserving their identity except through science. The owners of our industries perhaps feebly —but altogether definitely—are studying in myriad ways the application of science to the production of goods. And now we detect the first beginnings of the same tendency in the organization through which labor expresses its purposes. Herein lies one of the great bopes of the race. When our workers reach the point where they can well abandon force and embrace science, humanity will be in fora new experience. Buta science that is unrelated is even more fearsome than an industry that is detached from life. Hence our obligation to the author for a master generalization in which science is made to seem but another manifestation of that Ultimate Reality to which the human spirit itself is kinsman. Morris Lirweittyn Cooke. PREFACE SA. Subject matter. —- a. This book unifies or qualita- tively solves science, religion, and philosophy—basing every- thing on experimental, verifiable evidence. The explicit meaning of that statement is given in Chapters I and II. No assumption is made (as is shown in §99). b. The book is a condensed, preliminary rough draft of that unification of knowledge. All the qualitative problems set forth by the race—by “‘religion, science, and philosophy’’ ——are herein positively, definitely, and verifiably solved. But the application of those solutions consists of quantitative SAb Preface problems; and it is shown that zo quantitative solution may be accurately expressed or given (§§25, 40-1, 50, etc.); also, such solutions are infinite in “‘number’’ and may not be even roughly expressed in a finite book. Hence, merely general methods of the application of qualitative solutions to the problems of how much? and how many? are given. And only in so far as the reader is able to understand, verify, and ap- ply those methods to his life has the book any value to him. As each person differs from others (§§162i-j, 167m, 168p, 170p), the best book for one reader truistically can not be the best for another. So this book can not possibly be final, or the last word; other men can continually rewrite it bet- ter, wholly or in part. And most emphatically, I propose to no reader any creed, or “‘theory,’’ or ‘‘system’’ of truth, or ritual of any sort. As will be seen (Part One), all such are merely passing conveniences, tricks with words—and each reader may best select his own words. ec. The prime purpose of the book is to substitute posi- tive knowledge for that aggressive ignorance which is named agnosticism—thus eliminating agnosticism, the current pre- vailing ““ism.’’ The accomplishment of that purpose results in raising the standard and content of living—gives “‘life more abundantly’’ (Chapter XVIII, on ethics). SB. To whom addressed. — a. The book is addressed to the general reader who has a fair education. Each sub- ject is treated with the rigor that will, it is hoped, satisfy the experts in that subject. | But because the book includes all branches of knowledge, probably no one of the present day would be competent to read it if it were written in highly technical terms, and gave the minute details of each branch. I certainly should not be. So in order to satisfy all the ex- perts by giving each the complete grasp of his subject which trnistically includes knowledge of its relations with the sub- jects of other experts, it was necessary to avoid all but fairly common technical terms, and to omit unnecessary details. And that is equivalent to addressing the general reader. b. That reader, as will be shown implicitly throughout Parts One and Three, is quite competent to judge the validity of this book. There is nothing esoteric or ‘“hard’’ about the book in general. It is merely a description of things as they are, However, it requires some work to read the book. Some effort of attention will have to be made in places. c. A competent scientist of wide and successful experi- ence in writing for the general reader tells me that people tend to be frightened away from a book that uses mathemati- cal equations. I show that such a distrust and dislike of mathematics is justified, and an evidence of the wisdom of people in general: conventional mathematics contains funda- mental errors (§§30, 43-4). I remove those disabilities of conventional mathematics, and then use a few algebraic equations which even the non-mathematical reader will nearly surely approve, so obviously do they economize his attention. I may add that the publishers I tried seem to disagree with that: the reader may judge whether they underrate him. SC. a. There is no originality in this book in any real or important sense. Possibly some combinations of ideas are partly new. But I myself have definitely found nearly all, ev- en of the wider combinations, previously advanced by others. b. Consequently, the reader need not anticipate being repelled by any novelty or heresy of any importance; even when at first there is some slightly distressing apparent nov- elty, in the end it will turn out to be obviously an old belief. E. g., it is shown that the earth is cold inside (§122i). That does not happen to be the current conventional belief. But it was a common view in the past; and if the reader will ex- amine his views he will probably find that he has no more real love for a hot inside than for a cold inside—but prefers, UNIVERSE Vill as the important thing, the actual facts and the absence of self-contradictory views. The perspicacious reader will soon discover that I am very conservative—avoid being either radical or reactionary. ec. As there is no real originality in the book it follows that I am indebted to others for the ideas set forth. I grate- fully acknowledge that debt; but those creditors are so numerous that I can name none without injustice to many whose names I do not even know. In even greater measure I am indebted, not only for ideas I have used, but for what is more, personal aid and inspiration, to my wife, Laura Kent Klyce, and to Frederick W. Taylor, David Starr Jor- dan, John Dewey, T. W. Richards, Dorothy Canfield Fisher, J. J. Thomson, and Gerald Stanley Lee. SD. a. Some personal remarks may interest the reader, and will give needed information :- b. Inthe early summer of 1914 [ finished a book that contained substantially what this one does. It was too long, and contained literary defects quite too atrocious, for publi- cation. It ran to about 700,000 words. Since then I have written it over in whole or part continually—having much of that competently criticized. | That work is here condensed into a volume of reasonable size—I have struggled to keep it down to 250,000 words (it has expanded in two rewritings and probably will be about 325,000 when J finish setting it up: this page is done in the middle of that job). That al- most violent compression of such an obviously extensive sub- ject was necessary chiefly because a long book in this day of many good books frightens away readers, and because witha subject of such a nature a long book would tend to have “so many trees that it would hide the forest’ from the view of the few who might have braved its length. c. The reader can of course understand that it would have given easier reading if some of the book had been ex- panded into smaller and more familiar detail. | But the al- most imperative need of brevity, which has just been pointed out, has required the sacrifice of such ease. Quite possibly no reader will be satisfied with the actual compromise that has been made between such brevity and such local easy in- telligibility. The most difficult thing about the actual writ- ing of the book was to make that needed compromise in a way that was even tolerable to the reader—to conserve both his effort of attention and of memory. SE. Typographical and similar formalities. — a. Cer- tain arbitrary printing styles, which are not always used, have been followed in this book. An explicit statement of them here, if the reader keeps the statement casually in mind, will save his attention. b. The argument unifies knowledge. Consistently with that idea, often when I have a formally plural subject, in my view it is clearly unified, and I use a singular verb—some- times oddly. Always in that as well as in other grammatical constructions, I try to be conventional and hence inoffensive. But when explicitness and clearness of expression seems to require it, I deliberately sacrifice formal grammar. ce. All names of books, articles, etc., are put in quota- tion marks. d. All algebraic symbols are given in italics. e. All words, used as words, are printed in italics; no quotation marks are placed around them unless the custom for such marks (stated in the next paragraph) also applies to them. Italics are also used for emphasizing a word or words whenever it seems to me to make the text the least bit easier to read. It would of course always be possible, by ingenious literary circumlocutions, surely to indicate the desired em- phasis without that mechanical use of italics. But the keen reader will appreciate the brevity secured by italics, and will ix UNIVERSE readily perceive that I compliment him by taking it that he does not need the literary flattery I could give him by letting him waste energy finding the emphasis. This is not a book for stupid readers, who require even literary flattery. f. Quotations of others are marked thus:- “* ’’, ete.—in the usual way. Quotations of myself are marked thus:- ‘ ’; and such ‘quotation’ usually consists of my use of some word or pbrase in a temporarily unusual sense. The ’’ marks are similarly used at times to emphasize or indicate that I am using a word or phrase quite conventionally. g. This double mark :- is used “‘to introduce something that the previous sentence or clause has definitely prepared for and led up to,’’ so that it just precedes some remarks that are to be expected. The ordinary colon : is reserved for its other ordinary uses. When the :- is followed by a word beginning with a small letter, it introduces merely the remainder of the same sentence—when by a capital not other- wise needed, the remainder of the paragraph, etc. h. Economy of attention requires the conventional me- chanical device of treating a single topic in a ‘‘paragraph.’’ Sometimes in this book such a natural topic needs a lengthy paragraph which of itself contains sub-topics. If the long paragraph were split into paragraphs to indicate its natural subdivisions, it would, mechanically, at first give the reader the erroneous and confusing idea that the chief topic changed. So I split it into ‘little paragraphs’ by a dash : i. Most algebraic ‘symbols’ used in this book are con- ventional initial letters; bnt some are whole words. A list of those symbols, ete., is given as Appendix A. The chemical elements and periodic table are given as App. B. j. The symbol! ... will be reserved for the single mean- ing:- a continuing series, or infinite regress (§36n). An omission in a quotation, which often is indicated by that symbol, is indicated by ***, k. When J needed to state the source of a quotation or idea, or to indicate where fuller or analogous expression or proof is given in this book, I have tried to avoid that distract- ing and chopping up of the reader’s attention which would have resulted from putting the reference in a footnote in the more usual way, by putting it directly in the text in an ab- breviated form, where the eye can recognize it at once for just what it is, and yet inattentively slide over it unless it is to be definitely used. For similar reasons | have tried to get along without footnotes. Only when a needed parentheti- cal statement seemed to make too violent a break if printed in the text, have I put it as a footnote. 1. In preparing to set up this book myself I read several books on typographical rules and practices. Then I followed that practice which I thought would Jeast intrude itself upon the attention of the usual reader, and at the same time would cost him the least money. When there were two ways, ap- parently equally good, I have used both ways—that giving variety which I trust will please the reader as much as it did me, and relief from remembering arbitrary rules, and a trial of different ways to see if some actual preference develops. SF. a. The reader may be interested in remarks on the form of this book and the reasons for printing it myself:- b. I finished what may perhaps be called the present version in the spring of 1919 (it has been twice rewritten since), and started to look for a publisher. I quickly found that publishers were, so far as I could tell, afraid to risk any- thing on their judgment of the soundness of the book. Sol proceeded to get introductions by leading authorities in the three main sorts of knowledge to vouch for its soundness. e. While continuing trying publishers I tried a number of endowed institutions and similar organizations formed for the purpose of advancing knowledge in one way or another, Preface §Ff to see if they would help get the book published. So far as I could judge from their evasive but nsually verbally cordial letters, they believed the book couldn’t be sound—not one would even look at a manuscript. There was one illuminat- ing exception. I began corresponding with R. 8. Woodward, a scientist then president of the Carnegie Institution of Washington, in December, 1919, and continued until he ceased to be president over a year later. Woodward made a speech to the Congress of Arts and Sciences (convened at the St. Louis exposition in 1904 to try to unify knowledge— spending about $137,000 in the attempt), on the first page of which he said in effect that a book like this is practically impossible. He steadily, with a few exceptions in which he tried safely to dodge my introductions by men with reputa- tions of the highest, asserted in effect that he didn’t believe I had a sound book; and steadily refused even to look at it. He repeatedly referred me to his remarks on writers of what he in effect claimed were similar books (in the Year Book, 1917, of his Institution, 21-7), which include these epithets :- cranks, quacks, aliens, charlatans, mountebanks, arrogance, audacity pushed to the extreme of mendacity [that’s a nice phrase]. I began to think, after reading his letters, that if my book was sound it must have extraordinary value. But on second thought I decided that more likely Woodward was a little timid in the presence of an idea. d. I of course went over Woodward’s head to the Trus- tees of his Institution twice. As soon as Merriam took on its presidency the first of this year, | renewed my request to him and he asked for a4 manuscript, and for months examined it and had some of his colleagues examineit. After] found [ would have to wait for a decision | began to print the book myself (see next par.), and asked the Institution to buy 350 copies for distribution to the libraries on its free list. They are still deliberating on the matter. e. I tried 18 publishers, and they were afraid to take the commercial risk. It is a common practice for authors of books to take the money risk. SoI finally had a reliable publisher give me his lowest offer:- it was that I pay $10,000 for an edition of 2500—$4 a copy, to seli for at least $6 and probably more (if I had printed 2500 [ could have sold them for $1.50—and more, still lower). I didn’t have $10,000. So I tried to borrow it on substantially a mortgage on the book, from 25 successful business men, they to have the additional satisfaction of helping advance knowledge. About one quarter of them showed genuine interest; and I am pretty sure that two or three would have advanced the money if I had waited until the present low-speed panic (footnote 168h) is over. Those business men recognized at once that J was honest and probably right (Index, ““Sizing up men’’). But I decided that the book had waited long enough. f. I spent three days reading about a dozen books on printing—they were fascinatingly easy reading,—and then about four more reading catalogs and looking at printing sup- plies and talking to printers, and buying the cheapest second- hand plant (new type), and supplies for an edition of 1000. I have tried my hand a little at being a machinist, a plumb- er, and six or eight other trades, as I had to handle men in those—and at playing golf. And printing is the easiest—and to me more entertaining and gentler exercise than golf. (Of course, my effort was chiefly to print a passable bcok at the lowest cost; e. g., there are two or three pages printed poorly because | deliberately would not use time waiting for the humidity to drop and hadn’t learned how to counteract it satisfactorily; and there are too many typographical errors left in, due to not spending an extra hour on each page.) It took me a week to print the first page (p. 1), although I had picked up a little printing as a boy; the second took three SFf Preface days. The last half of the book was printed about eight pages a week, and once nine. I could have gone faster if I had not taken plenty of time to revise the book—to think it over and rewrite as ] set it up. That revision was the only real work, except I would occasionally use my head a little to overcome obstacles that printers assured me couldn’t be overcome. Printing one’s own book is the best method of revising it I have found; it gives more time to think over each word, and a very gratifying and useful sense of respon- sibility—there being no assumed-omniscient editor to rely on. Anybody with sense enough to write a readable book can learn to do passable printing in a week (of course, printing, or any other trade, can be made a fine art, and a lifetime be profitably spent on it; see §166f). o. These are the costs per copy, estimated fairly close- ly:- Plant and supplies (net, after selling them at the price tentatively offered), 17 cents; paper, 28c; binding (by a commercial binder), 25c; ink, 1}¢; engravings for pictures (they are poor, 1 having made the mistake of getting them from a high-price firm), 5c; transportation, 2ke; selling ex- penses, insurance, etc. (circulars, postage, free copies for publicity purposes), 4c. That makes a total of 83c. Then my work costs:- author’s royalty at 5 per cent, 10c; pub- lisher’s profit, 7¢; my labor, at $25 a week, $1.00—making the total of what I get, $1.17, and the total cost of the book, $2.00. I have charged labor at about half present printer’s pay. Judged by present prices of farm products, that is probably more than a printer is worth. But if a regu- lar publisher had printed the book I would have had to use fully half as much time on it [and five times as much nerve wear and tear] as I did to do the whole work: and by that criterion $25 a week is more than it sounds. And the plant net cost figures out as a depreciation of 70 per cent a year. A regular publisher of course would not have such an extreme depreciation; so be could afford modern machinery, which is supposed to be five or six times faster than the hand methods J had to use. My ‘‘overhead’’ is itemized above, and con- tains every legitimate item except rent, heat, and light— which would have been Jess than 2c if I had included it. The supervision and thinking for the job is included in the dollar for labor; it was less than a millionth of the work of writing the book, so I am getting overpaid at that. Books of about the number of words of this nowadays retail around $10. b. Asthat $2 is the lowest legitimate price, I had to an- noy buyers by adding postage. Few know what zone post- age will amount to, and the buyer is frequently consciously irritated by any price which adds postage. But there is a difference of as much as 600 per cent in the zone postage for this book—which makes it scarcely fair to buyers to average it, as the difference amounts to 16% per cent of the net cost. I doubt if there is in fact any such wide divergence as that 600 per cent in actual cost of postal transportation of small packages; if not, then the present rate is unfair, as well as being a nuisance. i. I find that some readers want to buy their book at a book store. It costs me no more to sell a book to the reader direct than it does to a dealer, and | find it far more inter- UNIVERSE x esting and pleasant to deal direct. I first offered the book *“by subscription’’ at $2 and postage, in that conventional way announcing my intention not to sell at any less. If the reader prefers to buy at a book store, ] am of course pleased to have him suited; but naturally he should pay the dealer. something for his trouble. J am told that usually the dealer adds about 40 per cent of the cost of the book to him, as the price of his services. So as a mere empty form 1 have put the retail bookstore price at $3: J have no legal control over the dealer’s price. At that price the dealer will per- haps get about 40 per cent increase on the cost to him—and incidentally he will get nearly as much for selling the book as 1 do for labor in selling and making it. Perhaps his service is worth that to the buyer: the buyer can judge that better than I can. Of course, if the dealer were doing me any appreciable service in selling this book I would sell it to him lower than to others. But there are only 1000 copies, and J do not want them sold to people who have to be urged in any way to buy; and the slight publicity which dealers could give the book would probably be undesirable. And naturally, if the dealer thinks that what he does for the buyer is worth the price, he will be as anxious to tell himthe cost as ] am, and will be grateful to me for having largely done it for him. And of course, if any dealer really wants the buyer to get satisfactory value for his money, that dealer will be glad to have the buyer accept my price if more satis- factory. So if any dealer objects to anything in this arrange- ment he thereby demonstrates that he is a profiteer, selfishly trying to deceive and grab something for himself without giving equal value in return—and | am glad to have gained his ill will. J make these remarks because my stand in this matter has already been attacked—that giving direct evidence that they are needed. (For theory of middlemen, see §170o. ) SG. a. It is the opinion of those who are probably the best judges that a book is an actual commercial success if it is intrinsically interesting and so is recommended by one person directly to another. I shall spend no money adver- tising this book, and make but a negligible effort to give it publicity. 1 think the book is a useful one and worth read- ing—rather more so than the ordinary book. If the reader concludes that it is worth reading, he would, if he is right, usually be useful to his friends by recommending it to them. And his doing so would be ample compensation to me; for if the book zs useful, thus I shall in due time get paid for the several years I have spent on it (principles of payment are in 8168). If I have an opportunity I shall inclose one or more circulars in the books I send out, for the convenience of those who may want to use them. b. I find by experience with various people that, because there are so many stand-patters who consider a sound book of this sort impossible, it takes unusual courage to recommend it publicly. So judged by that evidenee the men who wrote the introductions have displayed that fundamentally essentia] trait in the degree that is leadership (§8170r, 167b). 5S. Ktrycer. Winchester, Massachusetts, September 17, 1921. 1 UNIVERSE Introductory I §3b INTRODUCTORY REMARKS CHAPTER I. S1. a. This book is a brief description, and rigorous proof of the truth of the description, of the universe and all that appertains to it, both ‘“‘spiritual’’ and ‘“‘material.’’ Hence, the book is religion, science, and philosophy. If those three names of the main ““branches’’ of knowledge are taken in their customary senses, I am unable to determine which name properly designates any given portion of the book. The three are actually unified. b. Butalthough all threebranches of knowledge are thus included, one general method is rigidly and without excep- tion adhered to:- all statements and conclusions are based on experiment, so that the reader may also verify them by his own experiments or experience. When such a method is used, the product nowadays is usually called science; but in that case “‘religion’’ and ““philosophy’’ become identical synonyms of “‘science.’’ Personally, I have no preference in that matter of names; simply for convenience the three terms are hereafter used as applying respectively to the three possible and conventional ways of expressing the same thing (§39). ce. Although everything is to be experimentally verifi- able, the description is not therefore “‘materialistic.’’ In all conventional fundamental senses this book is far more definitely idealistic than are (say) the doctrines of Plato or Berkeley or any orthodox theologian. The leadingscientists of the present day, such as Richards, Jordan, Chamberlin, Patten, Hale, reach conclusions the opposite of materialistic, as we shall see (IX, X). It is at the same time quite true that some of the men who claim to be scientists have been materialistic, and have damaged the prestige of science with intelligent people. Later we shall see explicitly how such men as Ostwald, Clausius, and other Germans have been materialistic, and hence wrong (see especially $147). d. But the argument of this book, although idealistic in the popular sense (§49,etc.), is not sentimental; it hasmore than the conventional mathematical rigor. For conyentional mathematics are defective (§44), and the argument is given with the rigor of a properly corrected mathematics. S2. a. We may first view the book as a whole by not- ing how it compares with conventional *‘seience.’? The brief statement of such a viewing is that we shall find present science to be quite correct essentially, except that it is in- complete—as is of course acknowledged by most scientists. So it is completed, in a qualitative sense. In many cases we shall find that science reaches what are customarily termed religious conclusions. As strict science those conclusions are wrong in the sense that they are mislabeled and misapplied. Thus, the so-called law of conservation of energy is quite true; but it is religion, and not science. Or, to give a more directly concrete example :~ Newton’s law of gravity is cor- rect as pure religion; but it is wrong, both in principle and qualitatively, when applied to any two (‘scientific’) bodies such as the earth and the sun (§§74, 73d, 83f). b. But that statement of the scientific aspect of the book is perhaps too broad to be comprehended at this point. So we may take a more concrete view of science, and note just how it is proposed to complete science. c. Careful mensuration is considered to be the proper basis of present science. Kelvin declares that “nearly all the grandest discoveries’’ of a legitimate, valid science have been ““‘the rewards of accurate measurement and patient, Summary of contents and their character. long-continued labor in the minute sifting of numerical re- sults, I substantially quote this paragraph from Richards (Faraday lecture, 1911; ‘“Science,’? N. S., 878). d. The last paragraph asserts in effect that experiment or experience is the correct method of getting science, and then states the best method of experiment:- careful obser- vation or “‘measuring.’’ (Later I prove that the assertion is true; see especially §§$38-9; also 36-7, 57, 59, 60, 150.) But the use of that method by no means exhausts what sci- ence must do, and actually does do:- it is obvious that what- ever is obtained by those experiments must be expressed, stated, communicated, classified—and is, before it is even known as science. e. So we investigate the expression—the consistent ex- pression, or classification—of experiments, basing that inves- tigation itself and consequent conclusions upon experiments or concrete evidence. (It is a “‘circular’? process.) That investigation permits us to complete science. We promptly find that the fairly well informed average man is already in possession of enough ‘“experimental’’ data to complete sci- ence, 2s soon as we derive a consciously definite and con- sciously consistent method of expression. Hence, it follows that the reader needs no wide acquaintance with “‘scientifie’? or ‘‘technical’’ details in order to judge the general truth of this book. However, some scientific detail is included for the use of those who need it, and to show the general reader the further implications of his present knowledge. f. We shall find that there is a mere verbal trick which enables us to complete and unify all knowledge; to solve, verifiably and_ self-evidently, all qualitative problems—all problems of why, how, what, or all principles. We shall find that we already constantly use that verbal trick, but merely have not definitely noticed it—that it is an absurdly simple trick, the use of which is ordinarily named ‘‘commonsense’? ($491). The application of that easy trick to the thousands of details of daily life sometimes requires the consideration of such a number of things that it is dificult toremember them all, and we say that such application is complex. That is the only actual difficulty we have in ‘“anderstanding’’ anything. A child can “‘understand’’ the “‘argument”’ or “‘reasoning’? of this book. I have tried it on children of six and they did. The reader already knows the argument (§49q). g. Now, Kelvin himself elsewhere clearly implied that the expression of science is defective. We have him com- plaining:- “‘Quaternions came from Hamilton after his really good work was done; and although beautifully ingenious, have been an unmixed evil to those who have touched them in any way, including Clerk Maxwell’’ (“‘Life of Lord Kel- vin,’’ 1188; quoted from Shaw, ‘“Philosophy of Mathemat- ics,’? 98). Maxwell used quaternions to express the theory of electricity that is still substantially used. So it is clear that there is more to science than measurement. §3. a. The last section implies that mathematics is the means of expression used by orthodox science. view our book from a mathematical aspect. b. We noticed Kelvin objecting to a certain sort of mathematics that is explicitly used ina large part of science. Somewhat contradicting Kelvin, it would be easy to quote a number of scientific writers who substantially hold that those without a knowledge of the so-called higher mathematics can not understand many things that are true about the universe. We shall see that those writers are wrong. So we may §8c I Intreductery c. The fact is that mathematics is simply an abbreviated method of expression—a formal shorthand langnage (§30). It is based on precisely the same method or trick that ordi- nary speech uses ($30). Orthodox mathematics itself contains a fundamental inconsistency or selfcontradicticn. pe mathematicians themselves admit that it does. ee (Buer. Brits; oX¥ils 881) shows it, and says it 2277-8) moved in a certain way; but Shaw (‘*Phil. of Mat ‘ Pee. substantially disagrees that Russell removed ee ees, Poincare, one of the most renowned of recent ma So it ’ , irl ici ever agreel as despairing of mathematicians ©™' a is aoe that mathematical authorities themselves imply i r than orthodox mathematics serves to confuse science, rathe j i intelligibility. re it any fundamental in g . . 7 d As erthodcx mathematics are afflicted with such in consistency, I shall as a general rule not use some pianos of them. It will be shown in general how to correct—more accurately :- complete—them. But this is not a book. on mathematical detail, and extended revision of mathematies is omitted. It will be shown how ordinary algebra, when used in 2 consistent way, gives highly abbreviated expressions which we can easily keep in mind: ashort formula will sum- murize the whole verbal trick. So we use that formula, derived in §§33-8. §4. a. The consistent expression of experience is con- ventionally named /ogic. The mathematicians call substan- tially the same thing logistics or symbolic logic. The trick of language, or the theory of language, will therefore be given that conventional name logic. b. That name hesa formidable sound. Orthodox logic is formidable, as it is quite unintelligible if taken at just what itsays. (That means the ordinary textbook logic; there are several valid treatises—§490-q.) But valid logic is excess- ively easy—precisely that:. so easy that such logic was usually taken for granted and overlooked,so that we have had such monstrous books as Kant’s ““Critique of Pure Reason.’’ The fact which we shall find (§49) is that the average man has been using the valid logic right along, and that it is very simple as scon as we are conscious of what it is. We are not going to trouble ourselves with syllogisms, and other such horrors of our school days. In fact, we are going to see that in the conventional senses there are no such things as ‘“logic’’ and ‘‘reasoning.”’ c. We shall readily see that the well advertised “‘mys- tery that shrouds the ultimate nature of the physical [also spiritual] universe’’ is nothing more than our previous more or less unconsciousness of that trick of verbal expression which we continually use. The mystery and the “‘Veil’’— all ‘‘Unknowns,”’ and especially **Unknowables’’—simply turn out to be the things we really know best, as soon as we see just how we have been talking. Valid logie itself hasthe characteristics of a “‘machine’’ (VIII). So the puzzling mechanical’’ aspect which the universe seems sonictimces to take is an aspect of the verbal method used to describe it. Sines eee and the last ely, assert that, mathematics by Bie ae ae De an ve ay. ee seen ae rs ae trick or method of expression 2 qualitative problems. ae " neers a Ree have to solve guanti- as we go through lifes ee I see Ee ee i such problems be solved ce by acneally living’’ them. The qualita- ive solutions given in this book do not take away the need of continually solving such problems of actual living, and it it rigorously proved that never can such problems be other- wise solved (§§25d, 40-1, 50, 167, 178; ef. §66¢). Sono one need fear that this book or any other is ever going tore- ng on it. UNIVERSE 2 effort, by solving all qual- move from man all need of mental but we shall se© ei: itative problems. It sounds paradoxica aot tre simple (111): that it is quite simp ere 85. a. From the point of vie See eee al] :; is to pro . e of this book is ae es 2 Ean thus absolutely destroying agnosticism quail atiyv z for everyday living, the book Bm Bees ae Fee i will be shown that eee the only ‘“cin’’ or source of pain ($164c); and 6 eaith?’ and dogma, by their very definitions, acknowledge some degree of ignorance, and are sins. However, it is to be emphasized that the actual facts, the verifiable truth, dictate that purpose of the book—not any arbitrary fancy of mine. In no instance do I indulge myself in any “‘purposes’’ and ““aims,’’ in the vague conventional sense of inexplicable or truly primary or uncaused desires—for all kinds of absolute ““purpose’’ or ‘First Cause’’ or teleology are proved to be wrong (§$86d, 144h, ete.). In all cases the facts govern: I personally, as the writer, merely record; and the reader ob- serves and discovers for himself. J am not an ‘‘authority’’; the universe as a whole is the realauthority. I donot preach. I ‘‘uree’’ nothing on the reader, and do not so much as *‘in- vite’? him te do anything. I do not dictate in any way. b. In many places hereafter we see that the point of view set forth in the last paragraph agrees with things as they are. Here, I may show in rough physiological terms that agnosticism is damaging:- If the nerves controiling the beating of a man’s heart were to become ‘ignorant’ or agnos- tic of just what they were doing or ‘wanted’ to do, then asa truism they would be vacillating, uncertain, unreliable; and if they were really agnostic or quite ignorant—and not just partly or ‘formally’ ignorant,—they would as a truism stop working, and the man would die. But even the minor vac- illation would be ‘‘heart disease.’’ Obviously, if his “‘high- er’’ nerves become really agnostic, they stop working, and he is partly dead. He would, as a truism, die wholly if he actually were agnostic about everyday living. We shall see that no one is really agnostic: people are ignorant only in a quantitative sense, and not in a qualitative sense (S§25, 49). Also, agnosticism in practice is turning out to be a favorite disguise of the dogmatist, obviously saying this for him:- ‘‘See how very modest I am in admitting igror- ance. You ought therefore both to praise me for being mcd- est, and also unquestioningly to believe what | assert I know, as that modesty proves my reliability. ”’ I shall im- plicitly show in this book that an assertion of ignorance re- quires as much proof as one of knowledge; that it therefore by no means follows that such a dogmatic agnostic is either modest or reliable. c. But because the method of using language rigorously has previously been somewhat unconscious, although the con- clusions got from the method were consciously called —com- monsense,’’ there actually are what we might call quantita- tive agnosticisms—partial qualitative ignorances, sins, pais, cr partly dead nerves. The removal of those defects will truistically give “‘life more abundantly.’’ The reader him- self, by his own efforts in observing things as they are, gains for himself that more abundant life, as explicitly described in Chapter XVIII on ethics. §6. a. It is difficult to give briefiy at this point any easily intelligible snmmary of the religious conclusions which are to be established. That difficulty exists mostly because of the fact that theology is customarily considered to be re- ligion, whereas orthodox theology contradicts religion, so that there is great confusion in customary terms for this subje Another difficulty at this point is that it is not custom : a consider religion as being a definite, verifiable matter eae eD f actual life the idea or 3 UNIVERSE b. Probably the clearest way of summarizing the relig- ious conclusions that will be established is to state that the average American in his everyday life or work, and as the sum total of his thinking about it, has substantially achieved a true religion (§166e). Or, the sum of Christ’s doctrines is valid. On the contrary, the “‘reasonings’’ and exhortations of professional theologians are usually not sound religion. ec. Perhaps the only explicit remark on religion which will be of much service at this point is that the theologians, in so far as they are explicit and not evasive (848b), mostly teach Paulineism and not what Christ taught. It will be shown that Paulineism diametrically opposes the truth, where- as the substance of what Christ probably taught is correct (§8160-3, etc.). Considering them as men, |] think theolo- gians vary as do other men. Some are objectionable to me, while others are personally very fine. But taking them pro- fessionally—and unless otherwise noted my remarks refer to thein professionally,—they are substantially wrong, and Jam opposed to them (§§169d, 177b). 87. a. The foregoing summary of the book from five points of view may unintentionally lead the reader to believe that what follows is perhaps almost exciting. But to most readers it will not prove to be so. It is more likely toseem at first to be rather dull and tedious. I have had some years of experience in giving the proofs and expansion of those summaries to various people—mostly to men with highly trained minds,—and the argument seems usually to depress them at first. However, occasionally it explicitly collides with some pet superstition of a man, and he gets quite excited. Ordinarily, though, this unification of know- ledge is disappointing. It may be useful to the reader to have me point out the general causes of that possible temporary disappointment :- b. (1) Many generations have been inventing pleasing yarns concerning the delights of having absolute knowledge. In the absence of having such knowledge, even now men often assert the existence of it in some future heaven. But apart from such rosy fairy tales, for generations even the re- sponsible thinkers in their speculations have rather overrated the benefits that would immediately accrue from the posses- sion of absolute and complete qualitative knowledge. So naturally the reader wil] be expecting too much. If he could discount those expectations about 95 per cent right now— which will probably be practically impossible,—he will not be disappointed. ce. (2) The next particular source of disappointment will be that the reader already knows the essential conclusions that are reached. As I have reiterated, I do nothing but use a verbal trick consistently. The reader does nothing but discover for himself that he already knows the essential] truth. That will probably disappoint him at first, as it is not likely to be what he expected. For he may have the age-old, re- curring idea that some Messiah, with mighty intellect, and an overpowering command of the disciples’ emotions, would happen along and communicate undreamed-of, beautiful truths and happiness. It will clearly appear that such can never happen. The reader may resent the destruction of those ex- pectations, the commonplaceness of the whole truth, and probably the commonplaceness of me and my ways. d. (3) Because the reader actually knows the substance of our conclusions before he reads them, it follows that I am writing the obvious for him. About the most difficult thing to show is the obvious, as will appear. Peshaps it is even more difficult to see the obvious consciously—to observe defin- itely that we know it. ‘*Philosophy’’ is the simplest subject there is. The difficulty with it is that it is too simple and Introductory I §7j obvious. ‘Those uuexpected things will perhaps exasperate and further disappoint the reader at first. e. (4) The German tyve of materialistic scientist has taken Kelvin’s phrase, ‘‘minute sifting of numerical results,’’ as practically stating the sum total of any sort of valid know- ledge. The German scientists of that sort so vociferously praised that idea that some others confidingly acquired the same delusion. If any such deluded person reads this book he will be disappointed—except that it is shown that in humanies (Part Three) there is probably not yet enough of definite measuring. For in this book there is added what the materialists omit, and what we have seen Kelvin himself sub- stantially saying was needed (§2f). The book does consid- erable ‘‘minute sifting’’; it is necessary, but it is only half the truth (the whole of Part One proves that). f. (5) Finally, the reader is liable to be disappointed because I am too much lacking in skill in presenting the matter to him in the way he requires. g. I know of no way, available in any practical length of time, of saving the reader from one or more of those possible dissapointments, or ] would use it. If he has a youthful, vigorous mind—a condition not closely dependent upon cal- endar age,—it is nearly certain that in a few months, as the discoveries he makes gradually permeate his mind and become familiar, the disappointment will fade and he will find that he is extremely pleased, and really approves of things’ being as they are. If the reader is surprisingly vigorous in spirit he may be at once pleased with the rigorous truth that the book proves. Personally, I am conservative, as was stated ; and it took me a year or two to see the beauty of the truth. h. But to the possible reader who is so unfortunate as to be rather firmly fixed or ossified in the habit of materialis- tic ‘‘science,’’ and who requires—perhaps more or less un- consciously to himself—a long list of dry-as-dust obfuscating statistics, and nothing but such ‘‘facts,’’I can offer no pleas- ing hope. Both he and his mental brother, the persistently sentimental reader who prefers to believe much current theo- logical and ethical dogma, will perhaps to their deaths mourn or resent that their beloved formulas have here been so plaus- ibly questioned, if they rashly read further. i. However, to the general normal reader I may offer another pleasant hope. It will be shown that the world or universe is correctly made. I am not a reformer, nor a grouchy pessimist—nor a Pollyanna glad-gamer. The tacts do not permit me to be, as will be shown. On a basis of definite fact, I judge the present age to be the best age in history to live in, even though | consider people to be stil] very stupid. I do not think that 1 am as stupid as some peo- ple (I shall not ever bother the reader to praise me for hav- ing ‘“modesty,’’ as I have a negligible amount); but I find that J am enough like other people to prefer to associate with them—wouldn’t feel at home among really intelligent peo- ple. So I like the human race very much on the whole, and shall not try to revise it. We are all on the way of acquir- ing more truth and hence more religion or life, or whatever the reader prefers to call the good we get. So the only panacea is experience—or in scientific technicality :- experi- ments. When we consciously get experience, we name it education. j. Although I am thus correctly optimistic about quali- tative affairs (88149e, 161), in practical life I am able to see existing quantitative abnormalities, or unbalances, or undue departures from the average. I shall never bore the reader with any nonsense to the effect that everything in ordinary life is quantitatively good and lovely; for it is a fact that we (in usual language) say we dislike abnormalities in ourselves (usually calling them pains), and dislike to see them in §7j I Introductory others; and such abnormalities sometimes do exist. From a wider point of view those painful things are good, and are needed; but we can definitely attain that wider view only by explicit recognition of that usual practical view of consid- ering them painful ($177). From an immediate, direct point of view it is unpleasant to contemplate an extremely skinny man, and equally so to contemplate an extremely fat one; both departures from the normal or balance or the immedi- ately pleasing are obviously dangerous to life, or limit life. The ‘‘upper ten’’ and the ‘‘submerged tenth’’ are abnormal, and when we come across them I shall not deny that they are. As we are getting a description of the universe, which includes all things, as a detail it will have to be shown that the I. W. W. and the domineering, profiteering employer persistently try to depart—in opposite directions—from the normal balance or the temperate life, from the democratic or religious life; and are truistically offensive. So it is with the materialistic scientist and his counterpart the dogmatic theologian, the militaristic Prussian and the totally nonresist- ant pacifist, the dualist and the technical mystic, the autocrat and the socialist, the aristocrat and the tramp, the closet philosopher and the “‘rough-neck,”’ the “‘pure’’ theoretical man and the blatant “‘practical’? man. Inu brief, we shall see (XVIII, XIX) that a democrat is a balanced, temperate, religious man; and rigorous proof will be given that such a man is the only sort who is happy and can possibly survive. It is proved with mathematical rigor that our Constitution is in agreement with that and with all natural law (XIX). So the book will be pleasant from «a human point of view, pro- vided the reader is none of those unbalanced sorts of persons. In order really to prove anything about humans we have to connect the proof consistently with ““natural’’ law. So I connect it—or unify knowledge. CHAPTER II. §8. a. We have seen roughly the conclusions to be reached. J shal] now state the order in which they are given, as that shows briefly their general relationship. b. The portion of the book following these introductory remarks is divided into three parts. Part One gives a formal or general unification of knowledge, by showing the language trick. Part Two gives a unification in “‘concrete’’ terms of **matter’’——or is physical science. Part Three gives the uni- fication in “‘spiritual’’ or “‘mental’’ terms, and is the science of human beings, or humanics. c. Those three Parts are briefly outlined in the next three sections. Here it may be emphasized that in substance all three are identical. I.e.,each Part is essentially a repe- tition of the other two: the same principles are merely re- peated in terms of different things—the essentials of words in Part One, of matter in Part Two, and of menin Part Three being identical. Al! the different ““sciences’’—the expres- sions of all aspects of the universe, of all modes of living, of all jobs in life—are merely repetitions of the same essential things. They are simply different points of view—quantita- tively different expression—of the same thing, regardless of how widcly different their names may at first secm to be. Obviously, such repetition is a truistic result of unification: for unification means the ultimate identity of all things. §9. PART ONE. — Formal Unification. a. The first form of unification gives the verbal trick. The statement of that trick or method may with about equal accord with con- ventions be named (1) the theery of Janguage, or (2) the theory of mathematics or (3) principles of mathematics, or (4) legic. And as I shal! make a concrete mode] of language Order and relationship of contents. UNIVERSE + (VIII) which is a machine, the statement of that trick could also properly be named (5) mechanics. But as Part One does not explicitly discuss what are ordinarily called **con- crete’’ things, that Part could also rather conventionally be named (6) philosophy. And also, because the language trick is found to be identical with what in theological technicality is called the Trinity, Part One might with verbal conven- tionality be ealled (7) religion. Unification itself means ‘‘consistency’’; and as consistency is simply “‘valid classifi- eation,’’ which is conventionally “‘science,’’? Part One is also (8) science. b. Thus it appears how unessential mere names are. I endeavor to use names in the way that is generally eustomary. But as soon as we begin to get a real understanding of things, names begin to coalesce—sometimes with such persistence that even temporary verbal distinctions become hard to hold. ce. Obviously, so far as formal completeness is coneerned, I might end the book with Part One. For it essentially unifies knowledge. But so far as that goes, knowledge is also completely formally unified im the first few paragraphs of Part One (§12). We need further repetitions of the uni- fication as a proof that actual unification is possible (ef. §35), and in order to get directly applicable conclusions. For centuries there has existed a formal unification in the word God, or in the word wniverse—and neither unification has practically proved to be very applicable, or intelligible. S10. PART TWO. Concrete Ungfication. a. Con- sequently it is proved that mind and matter are identical ($$46, 150), and our unification of knowledge is explicitly shown in Part Two to hold good with respect to ‘‘matter.’’ b. The doing of that constitutes physical science. We shall see that such science is very useful for our purpose be- cause its terms permit us to be definite. And its concepts are simple, and hence easily grasped. So it is excellent as an introduction to the difficult science of humanics—difficult because of the numerousness or ‘‘complexity’’ of its details, which are hard to hold clearly in memory. That physical science is also directly useful of itself, as it is an intelligible description of the ‘‘environment,’’ which we continually use. S11. a. PART THREE. Spiritual Unification. a. The last part is another repetion of consistent knowledge, given in terms of humans. That final repetition is crucial proof that matter is mind——it being the actual consideration and use of matter as such in a way that obviously agrees with the facts. b. Part Three is, practically, the direct application of a unified knowledge to our immediate interests. It is familiar, and can be used by everybody—is used, in fact; for] merely describe how people act. In Part Two we see that every atom, our solar system, our galaxy-—every so-called material thing—is a live personality with actually as many traits or ‘“properties’” as a man. But im physical science we ean not see those traits so well; hence in each sort of “‘materia]’’ structure we explicitly consider only the few outstanding properties. And that “‘simplicity,’’ which is really meager- ness, permits us to work up gradually to a consistent grasp of the numerous perceptible propertics of men. But at the same time, much of Part Two is unfamiliar and ‘‘uninterest- ing’’ to the genera] reader simply because those properties of atoms have not been conventionally named like the same properties in humans, and so atoms are not at once recognized from the very names as being like himself. The general reader will hence necessarily find Part Two to seem some- what “‘abstract’’ at first. There is no need that he try to remember Part Two. But at least a casual acquaintance with physical science is needed for any actual understanding of ourselves, as we shall see at some length. 5 UNIVERSE ec. In writing Part Two I have tried to show that most of it is of immediate interest to us, and to remove its verbal abstraction. Butitis written with all the fundamental rigor I could put in it, as is the rest of the book. Nothing has been ‘‘prettified’’ or sugar-coated for a lazy mind. Through- out I omit many details, the explicit statement of which would serve more to complicate than it would to forward the main thread of thought. Many such details ] know; but I am quite aware that there are enormously more of which 1] One Ill §14b am not explicitly conscious—although the argument, as is proved, implicitly includes them all. But everywhere the book is written “‘up,’’ in an attempt to equal in worth the work of the best experts in each particular subject, and to interest them. However, the normal reader will find that he is quite my equal in most subjects and superior in some, if he will only take his ability for granted, and ignore the super- stition that there is something esoteric and appallingly recondite about ultimate knowledge. PART ONE FORMAL UNIFICATION; CHAPTER III. Nature of the general problem and its conven- tional name; or, what apparent failure in unification requires reconcilement. 812. a. In this section we shall see in a brief, concrete form the whole trick which definitely unlocks all truth. After that I shall prove the need of such an unlocking, and then begin in a more comprehensive and generally applicable fash- ion to express and apply the trick. b. Without stating the proof explicitly, it still will be rather obvious that we may make atypical form of statement or sentence, thus:- ‘Two things plus [or:- and} three things are equal to five things.’ We may abbreviate it, thus:- ‘two and three are five.’ Or we may abbreviate it still more:- ‘2+3=5.’ The only other general form of statement is what is called the truism, in which both sides are explicitly identical, as:- 55, A is-A, A—=A. Later we shall see that all true or-and intelligible statements can be reduced to truisms (§§35-7); we can see at once that our 2-+3=5 is really the same in meaning as 55. Mostof the sentences we use are obviously but slightly removed from be- ing explicit truisms. E. g., John is a boy means that John [cohom I know to be a boy] is a boy, or Boy=Boy. Or, we could call “‘boy’’ a “‘elass,’’ and finally get the truism in the general form, One unit [who is named John] is one unit [in a collection or class named “‘boy’’|; or, 1==1. But we need not go into that here. It was mentioned merely to make it reasonably obvious at this point that, unless we make sen- tences which are explicit truisins, the general form is 2+3 =5. And that sentence is itself only one step from a tru- ism, as noticed:- for the first member, 2-3, is obviously 5, and we have, 5=5. c. So we start with merely the general form of state- ment, in an abbreviated form:- 2+3=5. In the first member of that, we have two parts, “2’ and “3’. I. e., the first member implicitly asserts that there are two collections of things, which collections are at least verbally separate. The last member of it asserts that there is only one part, °5.’ I. e., the last member implicitly asserts that there are not two collections of things, but that there is one collection not ver- bally separate. In short, so far as form or language is con- cerned, the last member formally contradicts the first. Hence, in our typical sentence, we say a thing is so; and then promptly, and as a part of the very same sentence, say it is not so. Pe d. Well; by all conventional views of logic or " reason’ our typical sentence is thus verbally or formally positively and completely illogical and irrational, as it says one thing and then at once says it is not true—as it flatly contradicts itself. But by ordinary commonsense—by direct observation we know that the typical sentence is correct 3 or experience or THEORY OF LANGUAGE or true. In fact,a proverbial symbol for obvious truth is the statement 2+2-—-4; and I should have used that, except we needed to distinguish one 2 from the other 2, and it is hence rhetorically less awkward to use 2+3. e. Therefore, we simply use observation or ““common- sense,’’ and conclude that orthodox logic or reasoning is wrong, because 2-+3—=5 is correct. Then we further con- clude, as being the total essential of a valid logic, that in any sentence—i. e., completely stated and tntelligible sentence— which is not a truism of the form AA, we must have a formal or verbal “‘contradiction,’’ in the respect that parts are asserted both to be parts and alse to be combined into a whole which is not parts. In fact, we may readily see that-to make such a ‘‘contradiction’’ is the whole purpose and use of language :- to combine parts into a whole: to make names of parts coalesce into a formal unit that means the whole. That states the essential of language and the whole verbal trick. We apply that trick, and thus unify know- ledge, by adhering to the simple rule:- make sure that the valid—or “‘rational,’’ or “‘true’’—sentence does contain such a formal contradiction; if it does not, and is not a truism, it is really nonsense. S13. a. That is the sum total of the essentials of valid logic, and it implicitly contains the solutions of all qualita- tive problems. The last three paragraphs express all the real argument of this book, and there is nothing in all of knowledge any more difficult to understand than those sim- ple observations. The reader knows that logic already. He uses it daily, as ‘““commonsense,’’ without even having to *“‘think’’ about it. He is so expert at it that he would find difficulty in saying how he does it, just as he would find (perhaps much less) difficulty in stating precisely what mo- tions he makes in putting on his clothing. Below in this book I merely point out the details of that familiar logic, and the reader verifies them by his own observation and discov- ers that he knows all answers to questions of principle. b. So I now begin to translate that simple argument into the various aspects of it we have become accustomed to use. S14. a. As we proceed we shall see in more and more detail that the formal contradiction occurring in that simple typical sentence is inherent in positively all knowledge or expression. I shall state in this section some of the more general aspects of the contradiction which have been recog- nized, often for centuries (also cf. 5th and 6th paragraphs of Dewey’s Introduction). b. For each one of perhaps a thousand points of view that contradiction already has a definite conventiona] name. The “‘philosophers’’ long ago (they were the scientists of those days) named the formal way of speaking of parts—e. g., $14b III One of our ‘2’ and *3’—the Many; and the formal way of speak- ing of the whole, the One. Or perhaps mostly, they called the parts themselves, the Many; and the whole itself, the One. Usually I shall not need to be explicit about such a distinction between parts and expression of parts, etc. (cf. §36). And when the philosophers had assigned those names, some asserted that the Many was “‘real’’ or the “‘truth,’’ and the One false or ““seeming’’ or ‘‘appearance’’; and others said it was not so—that it was vice versa. And that dispute was and is named the problem of the One and the Many. ce. We shall see in detail that the problem is by no means an academic one, without appreciable effect on actual life (see Index, s. v. “One and Many’’). For identically the same problem is involved in the theological Trinity, and disputes over that plunged peoples into wars for centuries and still produce clashing, expensive sects. Whether a dem- ocracy is right, or an autocracy or other sort of aristocracy, is the same problem (XIX). As the problem has not before been rigorously and with explicit consistency settled, it fun- damentally produced the world war, which was an attempt, perhaps more automatic or instinctive than conscious, to find out how much aristocracy could be imposed on people. d. We have already implicitly seen in our concrete ex- ample 2-+3=5, that the problem of the One (the whole) and Many (parts) was not an actual problem at all, but sim- ply a puzzle of form—of arbitrary use of language, of verbal technique. Man invented a language; and he thereby cre- ated a verbal puzzle which he fancied was a real, world- shaking problem. And he finally got so befuddled that he ealled it the riddle of the universe—or if theologically in- clined, the mystery of God. The human race took words, mere words, far too seriously—made idols of them. ‘The race have been highbrows:- idolaters of words, the last spec- ies of a long line of idolaters of more tangible things. How- ever, we shall see that the normal man actually did not get so befuddled: he merely made no explicit reply to the num- erous varieties of aristocratic exploiters who kept misusing language according to their own mistaken ideas of self- interest until they came to believe their mendacities and evasions. That befuddling, highbrow bunco game is now mild in comparison with the past. But it may be observed still—nearly surely in this morning’s paper, unless like the Boston “‘Transcript’’ it has an editor especially well bal- lasted with fair-play commonsense. This book explicitly shows how the priesthood of that last, most subtle idolatry work their game. e. The sum of the matter is that there exists no riddle of the universe, no mystery—that there exists no real prob- Jem of any sort. The solution we shall get to that pseudo- problem, which we have already seen broadly given by everyday observation or commonsense in 812, is that the One is true, and that the Many is also true in a formal way, even though they are formally contradictory. We shall simply investigate those formal contradictions, and see.how to keep out of any real contradictions, and how to eliminate our vari- ous verbal] puzzles. S15. a. We may go somewhat more into detail! as to the modern forms of the One and Many. b. John Dewey, in the ““Introduction’’ of his ‘“Essays in Experimental Logic,’’ definitely implies continually that this Cne and Many underlies all philosophy or togic. Dewey is accepted by the experts as a Jeading authority (see Riley, ** American Thought’; ““Eney. Brit.,’’ xvi, 918, footnote 8). I think he is one of the best of ali plrilcsophers, logicians, and psychologists—and J muy add that since he wrote the Introduction for me J] naturally think sc more emphatically. And William James, who was finally in his ‘“Radical Empiri- UNIVERSE 6 cism’’ almost as sound as Dewey, says somewhere that he has come to believe that the One and the Many finally un- derlies all problems. c. Russell, one of the leading mathematical authorities, shows in a general way (‘‘Ency. Brit.,’’ xvii, 881) that the One and Many is at the base of mathematics, and points out the contradiction—which he says he obviates. We haveseen ($3c) how the mathematician Shaw disagrees that Russell avoids the contradiction, and states that Poincare was doubt- ful of ever reconciling mathematical differences of opinion over infinity (infinity is one mathematical name for the One— see §§30, 4.3). d. Technical scientists rarely use the ‘‘philosophical’’ name, ‘One and Many.’’ But we may quickly find them asserting the existence of the ‘‘problem’’ in the most ortho- dox of treatises. E. g., Maxwell is quoted in Watson’s ‘*Physics’’ (p. 2):- ““The difference between one event and another does not depend upon the mere differences of the times or places at which they occur, but only in the differ- ences in the nature, configuration, or motion of the bodies eoncerned.’’ In that statement Maxwell is obviously trying to say what really divides the whole or One of things into parts or ‘‘events’’ of the Many (and as he didn’t know, his statement is, as we shall see in time, confused and unintel- ligible—although it is given children to learn). And three times he uses a form of the term ‘‘difference,’’ which is itself a technical philosophical term—the problem of Differences— that is substantially a synonym of “‘One and Many.”’ e. That shows with great brevity that authorities agree that the One and Many is fundamental, even though they name it variously. As we proceed we shall incidentally see all kinds of authorities naming the problem, and puzzling over it. The general statement of the problem obviously is :- we seem to see the universe in two opposite aspects, (1) split into parts as the Many, and (2) connected into a whole as the One, or universe: and the problem is, How reconcile that ap- parent contradiction ?. We are now ready to sce, by our own observation and without any of the explicit support of convention and authority which I have been citing above, that the problem is fundamental, even though we state it in everyday “‘scientific’’ terms:- f. First, we consider broadly the very bottom thing of science, a ‘machine’’ (for details, see §S21, 8ef, 962). When we say a machine works—and obviously it is not a machine in a conventional] sense if it does not work ,—we con- sider the machine as a unit—as a One. Equally obviously, the machine is made up of parts, which are the Many. Everything which we conventionally call a machine has at least two perceptible parts:- e. g., a lever is the bar (or “‘lever’’) and the fulerum; a screw is the thread (the ‘‘serew’’) and the nut; the inclined plane, as a machine, is the plane and the load on it. In each case there is a jfric- tional union of parts which may be “‘separated.’’ We may make a typical sentence for, as, or ““describing’’ a ma- chine:- One part plus |i. e., held on by some degree of’ friction to| at least one more part is a machine. Or, we may abbrevi- ate:- One part + One or more parts = The machine, or the Whole. Or, The Many = The One. There, in z ‘*scientifie’’ ““inachine,’’ we obviously have parts equal to a connected whole—which is formal/y contradictory. But cb- viously, both are true (so far, we see by ordinary common- sense that they are true; later it is erplicitly proved to be truc—IV). So again we have our general *“solution’? :- The Many=The One. And we see at once that the mistake some people have been making as to “‘machines’’ was that they emphasized the parts of the machine, and overlooked the equally true fact that there was a machine only as it was 7 UNIVERSE a connected, consistent, really inseparable whole—related together as a structure, or organism (XI). When a baby takes apart a watch it is no longer to him a watch—it is not a watch except as it works together. When an infant phil- osopher or scientist or theologian takes apart the universe— ‘‘analyzes’’ it, not into a ‘‘machine,’”’ but into machine parts, —he can not put it together, and to him it no longer is the universe or a whole; to him it is a pile of mental junk, vari- ously named agnosticism, dualism, etc. But, the obvious fact is, he never did actually take the universe apart; in his egocentric, anthropocentric way (§$40f, 73h, 100, ete.) he just fancied he did. The universe kept right on working, and his “‘analyses’’ produced no real problem. g. Newton’s first law of motion, which asserts inertia, explicitly states that no body can move unless acted upon by another body (§88). If we agree to say that bodies move (we could construct a valid science, wherein nothing verbally moves—§97), then at once we imply that in some way the universe (the One) is as a whole made up of parts (the Many) which are connected in some way that permits motion (by orthodox logic no such motion can occur—Index, s. v. ‘“Ze- no’’), And as we shall see ($88), the other two laws of motion were Newton’s attempt to assert that there was no logical contradiction in that assertion of inertia. In short, his laws were an attempt, surprisingly successful for that age, to solve the One and the Many. h. The last two paragraphs give two of the thousands of ways in which science names its forms of that so-called philo- sophical problem of the One and Many. I may at this point merely name some other ways that will probably be seen obviously to involve the problem. i. There is now much apparent conflict between ‘‘quan- tum’’ theories, and ‘‘continuous’’ energy theories—such as wave theories. Those quantum theories in effect assert that fundamentally the universe is divided into parts (here, parts of energy—the term energy being the more usual scientific name for universe). The opposing theories assert that there is no such division—that the universe in continuous (XIII). j. That conflict of words begins far back in scientific history, and comes up to the present day. Is heat small, Many motions (and if so, a Many of what?); or is it continu- ous phlogiston? Is electricity continuous energy (the One), or discrete as electrons or corpuscles? Usually now it is taken as discrete; but the question has already come up whether electrons are continuous inside. Is light continuous as waves, or discrete corpuscles—or in modern terms, discrete magnetic disturbances? Or, in more generality, are there exact or eternal or absolutely separate atoms (the Many); or no exact, really separable atoms (the One)? The so-called kinetic theory gives two answers to that which contradict each other (§89, etc.). And the electron theory is in the same contradictory condition:- Thomson and his school hold that electrons have tubes of force, which substantially amounts to continuity; and the other school have discrete electrons in what is substantially the older kinetic theory. 816. a. I think that is enough evidence of the general need of an investigation of the One and Many. It is prob- ably already obvious to the reader that the investigation, even if it does apply only to a verbal confusion, is of funda- mental importance in reaching a conscious understanding of things, regardless of whether we consider those thingsas be- longing to science, philosophy, or religion. So we begin the completely explicit solution. §17. a. ‘“The Encyclopaedia Brittanica’’ (11th edition) seems to me to be the most reliable generally available auth- ority as to what are orthodox doctrines concerning most sub- i One Ill §17d jects. As] am trying to use words in their customary senses, so as to he easily intelligible, I shall frequently cite that encyclopedia as giving such general agreements as to words and facts. Hence, indeveloping the meaning of ““One and Many’’ ] shall show some of the details of the orthodox difficulties by quoting the important parts of that encyclo- pedia’s articles on pluralism and monism:- b. Art. ‘‘Pluralism’’:- ‘“‘Pluralism ***, a term used ** in philosophy for any theory which postulates more than one absolutely distinct being or principle of being [postulates the Many], opposed to monism. Pluralistic systems are based on the difficulty of reconciling with the monistic prin- ciple the principles of variety [or Difference] and freewill. The chief difficulty which besets any such view [that there is an absolute Many, or pluralism] is that if the elements are absolutely independent, the cosmos [universe] disappears and we are left with chaos: if, on the other hand, there is an interrelation ***, the elements [the Many] are not ulti- mate in any intelligible sense.’’ l. e., if the universe is not chaos, then as a truism it is not possible to say (as a concrete example), that there is any actual difference which will permit us to distinguish between a man and a moon. Clearly, if we take language forms as seriously as the writer of that article, we are fundamentally forever barred from knowing anything. ce. Art. “‘Monism’’:- ““Monism, *** the philosophic view of the world which holds that there is but one form of reality, whether that be material or spiritual. The aim of knowledge is explanation, and the dualism or pluralism which acquiesces in recognizing two or more wholly disparate forms of reality has in so far renounced explanation (see Dualism (i. e., the Article quoted in the last paragraph]). To this extent monism is justified [probably the writer means that monism is justified in that it ‘explains’]; but it becomes mischievous if it prompts us to ignore the important differ- ences in facts as they present themselves to our intelligence. All forms of monism from Plotinus downwards tend to ignore personal individuality and volition, and merge all finite ex- istence in the featureless unity of the Absolute; this, indeed, is what inspires the passion of protestagainst monism. Turn- ing to the historical forms of the theory *** [there follows a short statement of philosophical technicalities not needed here; and it may be added that there seems to be evidence of Chinese monists centuries before Plotinus]. Those who maintain that all these forms are hasty and superficial stand by the conviction that the right philosophical attitude is to accept provisionally the main distinctions [differences] of com- monsense [but we saw, in the case of the machine, §15f, that commonsense gave also a One, as well as that Many}, above all the distinction of personal and impersonal; but to press forward to the underlying unity so far as experience and reflection justify.’’ d. We may note that the writer of the second article speaks of “‘a passion of protest.’’ In short, the reason peo- ple have not agreed on the One and the Many is, from one point of view, because they took mere words so seriously as to become violently emotional over the problem. There is current an odd fiction that philosophers are unemotional (for the psychology or **human nature’’ of it, see §155); but we have just seen the staid ‘“Brittanica’’ tacitly agreeing that it is proper for emotions to keep professional philosophers from agreeing. It is sometimes fancied that scientists do not thus let emotions interfere with their consideration of the act- ual facts. But some in real life become violently emotional the minute this problem is mentioned; e. g., one professional astronomer spat out “‘metaphysician’’ at me, as the vilest epithet he could invent, because I incautiously used with him Ce §17d II] One the name “‘One and Many.”’ Those remarks are made to show that there is all the emotion there is, concealed under the apparently harmless and abstract ‘‘philosophical’’ problem of the One and Many. We are going to go cau- tiously with it, so as not to set off any premature emotional explosions. (See Dewey’s recognition in his 8th paragraph of one of my methods of doing that which I agree J have overdone, but‘which I ‘don’t'dare modify.) | But when, we have the solution thoroughly. controlled; it, is to, be. shown that area] grasp of the problem is an ultimate religious ex- perience, or “‘conversion,’’ or **rebirth”’ (S8153f, 162). S18. a. The One is therefore a conventional and useful technical term meaning that the universe with all its phe- nomena is inherently continuous or joined together; or is an absolutely inseparable or indivisible unit. We shall see the proof that the universe is really thus; but at the same time we shall see that it is absolutely impossible to make a pos- tively intelligible statement or cxpression about such a uni- verse. Consequently, to anticipate—perhaps somewhat unintelligibly here,—-the universe will arbitrarily be talked of as a pluralism—explicitly as an ‘infinite pluralism,’ which is a formally self-contradictory name, not before used in that sense so far as I know. | b. The Many, as a conventional technical term, means that the universe is made up of more than one part, each part being, absolutely distinct, separable, and absolutely real in itself; ““the Many’’ is the conventional name for the parts. Obviously, such a ‘collective’ name is essentially sclf-contra- dictory if it is supposed to have a real meaning, if the parts are absolutely separate; for in that case they are truistically absolutely not collectible, even verbally. Hence, in this book we shall not have “‘the Many’’ used with that absolute con- ventional meaning. I shall use it asa term, admittedly form- ally self-contradictory and desirably so, which asserts or implies that we have arbitrarily divided the universe into parts, basing the division upon certain agreements among ' men (§100, ete.). For, to anticipate the proof agaim—and ‘again perhaps somewhat unintelligibly here,—when we are positively intelligible in our language, we have to speak con- ‘eretely of the Many; an actual language is otherwise impos- ‘sible (IV). Also, we may validly hold that the infinite Many is true, or is the One ($49). S19. a. The only other technical philosophical word which the reader need remember is dualism. Instead of using the now unfashionable theological name devil, I say dualist—and there are many professed dualists, although asa matter of fact there can not possibly be a real dualist, as we shall see. Kant, in so far as he was explicit, was a dualist; the Germans took him seriously—and see what happened to them. b. By dualism I mean that nonsense which is dressed up in the orthodox “‘logical’’ form—i. e., all explicit, formal orthodox “‘reasoning’’ is dualistic and nonsensical. J shall describe that conventional form by this quotation in substance from Art. ““Dualism,’’ ““Eney. Brit.’’:- Dualism is a term that is applied to all doctrines which try to explain facts by classifying them all under two coexistent and separate cr distinct forms or ‘“beings.’’ Dualism in technical philosophy postulates—i.e., assumes and then undertakes to prove—~the eternal coexistence of positively separate mind and matter; it is thus opposed to an ‘‘idealistic monism’’ and a “‘materi- alistic monism.’’ [The “‘Encyclopaedia’’ says there are those two sorts of monism, thus obviously making ‘‘monism’’ also finally dualistic; as a fact, the German variety of “*mon- ism’’ does in effect make so-called monism a dualism—§49. | Similarly, there aré two forms la ‘dualism’ | of dualism. One form is that ynind oe matter are absolutely heterogene- i 3 ¢." a ; torical details. UNIVERSE 8 ous {that is the form that has been substantially stated just above]. The other holds that matter in its usual sense does not exist, but that we have an “‘idea of matier,’’ and the dualism then consists of the eternal absolute distinction be- tween (1) the idea of matter, and (2) ideas themselves, or “‘reason.”’ The reader need not worry if he fails to understand all that: it is unintelligible when considered ex- plicitly: I have been simply quoting—translating into my erude, common words. Indirectly and implicitly, that formal ‘dualism contains the basis of truth, so that it will vaguely mean something:- for we saw that dualism at onee formed a dualism of dualistn: that regress actually implicitly goes on indefinitely and gives the truth (SS23-4). But that remark is not intelligible at this point. c. Inthe Article ““Dualism’’ there are given numerous historical facts about the forms of dualism. E. g., according to the encyclopedia the ‘‘Christianity’’ which holds that there is a God and a Devil is substantially dualistic, and the morality that makes Good and Evil absolutely distinct is positively so. In suitable places below I shall soive those puzzles without burdening the reader with the explicit his- But J may mention here, in anticipation of the proof in §24c, that all orthodox pluralism is in final form dualistic, because orthodox logic is explicitly dualistic. In short, all positive expression in past history, previous to the present solution of the verbal trick, was technically a plural- ism which was a dualism, and hence was technically wrong, if we hold it rigorously to a valid logical standard. Asa matter of fact, very few people ever dreamed of interpreting previous expression thus rigcrously: substantially, most past expression was right, and sensible people actually definitely disparaged the orthodox logic, and very great men like Christ practically repudiated it (8162e). | 820. a. We see thus that orthodox philosophical terms are quite self-contradictory. Orthodox scientifie terms are as bad, as we saw in §15, and shall see in more detail from time totime. Those contradictions are obviously the attempts of various men to dodge the formal contradiction that is un- dodgably inherent in the One and Many. So imevitably, those attempts to escape the inescapable simply, for each at- tempt, put the contradiction in a new place; and instead of resulting in a “‘solution’’ where no solution was needed, simply added one more verbal puzzle. (That is the whole qualitative history of ““philosophy.’’) The attempt became more puzzling when the contradiction was made movable with- in a given “‘system,’’ so that it wasn’t ‘‘there’’ just when we thought we “‘had’’ it:- such an elusive state of affairs occurs in technical philosophical mysticism (analogous words are mystify and mysterious), or in Bergson’s ‘“intuition’’ ; or in modern science, relativity is really an example, which by rigorously making the contradiction move infinitely becomes technically sound, as will become intelligible in §66. b. We may here, in further detailed proof of the exist- ence of such contradictions, and ASG useful means of becoming inoculated against taking any ““isms?? —‘‘ 5, ystems’’ —too seriously, casually note some further substantial quotations from the “Eney clopaedia. ’ TI use the Articles ““Realism,’’ ‘‘Ideal- ism,’’ ““Mysticism’’ (and of course what I thus substantially quote is, just of itself, mostly unintelligible—a deliberate but factually correct parody on the human mind as it disports itself in the “higher learning’’) :- c. Realism is a ‘‘philosophical term used in two opposite senses. (1) The oldest of these is the scholastic doctrine, traceable back to neerates, that univer sals have a more ear’ existence than things.’’ A “‘universal’’ of a chair (say) is not real ehairs, but the mental “‘ideal’’ chair. In its extreme form of this first meaning, realism denies the reality of 9 UNIVERSE anything but “‘universals,’’ and is opposed to what is called ‘‘nominalism’’ and “‘conceptualism.’’ [That denial is of course logical nonsense; a ‘‘universal’’ is what we later call a relationship word—see §§57, 49 for the solution of that orthodox nonsense.| (2) The modern application of realism is to the opposite doctrine that there is a reality apart from such universals. There are several forms of that sort of doc- trine:- e. g., ‘natural or naive,’’ ‘‘ideal,’? empirical,’’ “transcendental,” ete. {Obviously from those quo- tations, the two opposite varieties of realism are tacitly both dualisms. But when expression is so vague and conflicting as those quoted definitions, no one can say positively what such expression does mean. | d. Mysticism requires about five of the encyclopedia pages, the size of these, to explicate. The article says, to begin with, that mysticism is a ‘‘phase of thought, or rather perhaps of feeling, which from its very nature is hardly sus- ceptible of exact definition’’—l[as a matter of fact, we have no difficulty in this book in considering it under the name of infinite regress, which in psychology is called by the very common names emotions or feelings—see Index, “Infinite regress,”’ ‘““Emotions’’]. “Most frequently it [mysticism] appears historically *** as a reaction of the spirit against the the letter.’’ In short, orthodox historical mysticism makes an inconsolable contradiction between “‘spirit’’ and “‘letter’’ —and having no “‘letter’’ can not actually express itself. The emotions of mystics are ‘“violent’’; they are said to have ‘‘fervid Godward aspirations. ”’ [T may mention that several notable mystics have been considered by some to be on the border-line of insanity, if not over. Women sufficiently hysterical to be on the verge of insanity, such as St. Theresa, are often mystics in the orthodox sense. | e. The ‘*Encyclopaedia’’ uses six pages to explicate idealism. First, there are two rather opposed meanings :- (1) The popular meaning is substantially :- “‘abstract perfec- tion’’; i. e., ““ideals.’’ In that sense, idealism is a form of monism. As commonly used by the average man, J do not think that idealism is quite so exaggerated, but think that it is merely his name for the valid logic we are to deduce ex- plicitly (cf, 849, etc.). (2) The technical meaning of ideal- ism is:- the doctrine that conceives knowledge or experience as a process in which two factors, subject and object, stand in entire independence of each other. That of course is ad- mittedly dualism. It is distinguished from so-called ‘*commonsense dualism,’’ which regards mind and matter as being in “‘more or less accidental relation’’ with each other, in that it ‘“seeks to realize its own ideas’’—| by which hysteri- cal phrase I suppose is meant that it strives to relate its ideas into a One, and thus stultify itself, and flop over to the op- posite first meaning |. The article states substantially that there is no contradiction between technical, dualistic idealism and James’s pragmatism. But as a fact that is easily verifiable, James, in ‘‘Essays in Radical Empiricism,”’ did explicitly flop from dualism to a monism that was really valid logic (§§49p, 156). §21. a. Viewing that maze of nearly unintelligible con- ventional contradictions, the reader has probably seen for himself that orthodox philosophy is rather indeterminate. It was fairly obvious that the contradiction, which was shifted about from point to point by the various “‘ists’’ in their dif- ferent “‘isms,’’ is the formal one between the One and the Many. _ Of course I took the easy way and madea parody—a slight exaggeration—of that ‘‘higher thought.’’ (Those past experimental efforts to get consistent thought were of course needed, and have actually been my guide in working out this book.) But a proper constructive summary of the whole thought of the race is given by Dewey in his One Ill §21d Introduction. His summary is a masterpiece, and was far be- yond my powers—in fact, the reader needs to know consider- able about the history of thinking to be able to appreciate the excellence of that summary. b. And probably the reader has seen already, in antici- pation of the explicit discussion in the next chapter, that the whole aim of philosophy and religion, in the search of a con- sistent way of stating truth, was to get ‘one part’ related to, or joined in some way with, ‘at least one other part,’ in or- der to have the united, or One, meaning. In fact, as was indicated in considering mysticism (§20d), unless there are at least two such verbally contrasted parts, there can be no positively intelligible expression. So philosophy was always thrown back upon a dualism; and just as inevitably, as we saw under ‘‘idealism’’ (§20e), it then struggled from that really merely verbal dualism—which however it took too seriously, as being “‘real’’—back to a united or One mean- ing. And obviously, dualism is nothing more than an equiva- lent name for ‘“machine’’ (§815f, 86f), or for “‘analysis.’’ Scientists use “‘machines’’ and ‘‘analyses,’’ and most of them, precisely as do philosophers, struggle to get away from that dualism to a popular idealism, or an intelligible “‘rela- tivity,’’ or a ‘“unification,’’ or “‘understanding’’—or really, to an explicit religion. Those who are too weak to struggle much tend first to be ““quitters’’ by asserting agnosticism; when they are sufficiently calloused to that lack of unifica- tion or understanding, they become materialistic—which variety of hardened, indifferent ignorance is, in everyday terms, named cynicism—the dogmatic ignorance of the quit- ter that is temporarily forgivable in the young, who almost invariably assume it fora while as a protection from becoming too fatigued by the flood of impressions rolling in (8155). c. Jt is possible to go on from this point and show that philosophers, poets, and prophets have invented an idea they called God to make that dualism or machine work. When they asserted (as the result of short vision—cf. $47) that there really was a distinct dualism, then they obviously had to have something to make that apparantly totally disas- sembled machine get its parts together, and work together, in order that it be intelligible or do what we plainly see it doing. And they used their ““God’’ to do that. Obviously, if God actually stuck the pieces together, then as a truism, there was not any longer a dualism, or dismantled scientific machine. And, unless the prophet himself actually created that God, then clearly the God existed previously, and there was not the dualism the prophet or scientist began by assert- ing existed. So we see, merely as a truism, that the idealist-dualists who “seek to realize their own ideas,’ and the realist-dualists who make their machine work somehow, both have, like the mystics, ‘‘fervid Godward aspirations’ —which means, in commonsense terms, a desire to see things as they are (§§153f, 162, 166). d. But we shall not spend any more time directly upon such vague orthodox philosophy or theology, even in order to see the interesting historical facts concerning man’s intellect- ual inventions of God in his (man’s) own image ($1 70jm). We shall proceed to make first-hand, rigorous investigations of facts for ourselves, and not rely upon picking out consis- tencies from the maze of conflicting ‘‘authoritative’’ doctrine ~—although the reader may readily do that for himself, if he likes. By having heard those authorities a little we have found some useful conventional words; and the reader is perhaps convinced that it won’t do to take some of such authoritative “*knowledge’’ very seriously. §29a IV One CHAPTER IV. Statement and proof of principles of lang- uage; or, Logic. §22. a. We now begin definitely to observe facts, each for himself. JI simply point out the things the reader may look at, as a means of seeing the truth for himself. What I write is a sort of gnide or sign-board; it is not the truth, but merely a particular expression of the trnth——certain symbols that point to the truth. b. It is an evident truism that if the reader is to use solely experimental evidence, and is not to make the reaily impossible attempt to substitute this present symbolic guid- ance jor the truth, then J can not permissibly make any as- sumption as to a real truth or fact, from which I ean “‘start.’’ If I were to say that ‘In the beginning God created the Heaven and the Earth,’ or “In the beginning was the Word,’ then I] have assumed the truth or reality of everything about those extensive subjects I cared to assert, regardless of whether or not the reader could see and verify it for himself; and the assumption is obviously used as the answer, or abso- lute explanation, of any problem that is proposed. Obviously there always would remain the problems:- Why is the as- sumption true? and What was before the assumption that made it true? and Just what does the assumption mean any- way? What actually is the ““beginning,’’ and the ““Word’’? ce. Therefore, in this book positively no essential or quali- tative assumption is made: everything is based directly on the reader’s seeing for himself. However, it is not possible, in my writing this symbolic expression (or guidance as to which direction the reader may look), to avoid two general arbitrary, quantitative, or formal assumptions. For if I am to write and have the writing actually guide, ] must formally assume:- (1) that both the reader and I can and will use a certain sort of agreed upon symbols or language; (2) that those symbols do point to something for the reader to look at. In this section we examine those ‘assumptions’ in more detail, it being shown that they are arbitrary and not real. d. The first assumption is simply that the reader and | both speak English. Obviously, it is not essential in any absolute sense that we do. It simply is:- that 7f we wish to communicate, then we both must speak English (or any other mutual language; the book can be translated into other langnages for other readers without greatly modifying its present pointings). So obviously, that assumption is not real, but is a mere temporary and mutual agreement. e. But that arbitrary assumption contains one corollary or implication that is important, and which we need to keep in mind. “To speak English’ [or other language] means finally that jf we say A is A, then we must not undertake to say that simultaneously A is not A; for to do that obviously destroys at once what we say—and we then are not speaking any langauge. That implication of the assumption is still obviously arbitrary; for it says that if we agree to use cer- tain words for certain things, then we must keep the agree- ment until we give notice that we shall change it. It is not an assumption in any real sense; for it is an obvious and commonly accepted fact that (1) many people do not speak ‘English’ li. e., any language] (infants, e. g.), and that (2) some who do speak ‘English’ will consciously and delib- erately fail to adhere to such an agreement (are liars, in short), and further that (3) a number who try to keep the agreement have such poor memories or nervous systems that they fail to do so. The agreement is usually referred to bv the phrase, ““having the same definitions.’? But we are go- ing to see, as an immediate implication of the principles of time and space, that two persons can not have quite the same definitions (S§36, DY Ot polio, Ch. 66): and that even after UNIVERSE 10 I carefully make a definition it is impossible that it be accu- rate (Index, s. v. ‘‘Exact’’), so that it is absolutely impos- sible for me to adhere strictly to my own definitions. Our examination into the language trick in this chapter will show those facts abont ‘“definitions’’; we have had here a summary statement of why there has always been so much difficulty over ‘‘definitions’’——the difficulty is a quantitative matter. Therefore, I have put our arbitrary agreement as to language into an explicitly quantitative form, and we shall see repeatedly, in further detail, that it is not a real or qualitative assumption, but merely the base of the in- vented language trick. f. (2) Our second assumption, when we talk together in this book, is that I am talking ‘about something.’ In short, the minute I begin to use these verbal symbols then I have tacitly assumed that the universe exists. | Now, clearly, that assumption is substantially the same, at least in form, as saying that ‘God exists, and his existence explains every- thing’. It requires a little keen observing to see that this second assumption is also formal, and not real. We shall see it in general in the remainder of this section, and more explicitly in §§60, 93, 161 (also, see Dewey’s treatment of it in his Introduction). The assumption may be called the existence assumption; the philosophers discuss it under the names ‘‘being’’ or ‘“Being’’ or “‘substance’’ or ““ontology.’’ In actual effect, this total book is required to show and does show, that it is not a real assumption. ; g. We obviously correctly write the existence assump- tion thus:- ‘Jf we speak English, then at that time we tacitly assume that something exists, goes on, acts, or happens.’ Well; we can see as a truism that if ] had made # real assumption there, then it would follow that if I had not written the book the universe would not exist; or, I really saved the reader’s life by writing this book, as otherwise he would not ““be.’? That conclusion is clearly absurd. So it is obvious that I am merely formally assuming the existence of the universe. What actually happens, stated in a commonsense and ultimately rigorous way (as proved by this whole book), is that I write, ard in writing I describe the formally-assumed universe; and the reader looks at it—what- ever it is,—and 7f he sees it there, for himself, then the uni- verse is experimentally and verifiably demonstrated to him, and my formal or arbitrary assumption for the purposes of this book was merely a tentative—i. e., not generally essential —way or method or trick used in guiding him to see. h. But that commonsense way of showing that I have made no real assumption does not explicitly satisfy various sorts of agnostics and irrationalists (§32c). They often even definitely ask:- ““What is this universe you take for granted you are talking about? and where does it come from and who made it? and how?’’; and assert that unless I answer those questions intelligibly then I have made a real assumption that there zs such a thing as the universe when I start talking about it. Again, the same commonsense way of answering is, that in this book I do give verifiable answers to those questions, and that further I show experimental, verifiable proof that those answers are complete, and that nothing more or further—in a qualitative way——could exist as an answer. Hence, the book as a whole again is proof that my assump- tion is formal. i. But those commonsense answers do not content the technical objectors. As we shall discover (§35ed), act- ually the only final way or real way to prove any thing what- ever is to do it or make a or produce it (‘observe’ it or experience it, all that being merely the ancient wisdom that the proof of the pudding is the eating thereof)—and that actual way is the one we use in this book for all fina] or il UNIVERSE rigorous proof. But those objectors want an explicit technieal statement which rigorously expresses proof that our existence assumption is not real. SoI give it in the next paragraph; but they will have much difficulty in understanding it at this point, as the understanding requires a grasp of the whole book. The actual fact, which causes the difficulty, is that the objectors’ questions do not ask any real question; the questions are wholly meaningless, or self-contradictory. The reader not interested in technieal word juggling might well skip the paragraph, in which I answer those word jugglers. j. I assert the formal assumption that ‘something exists, or goes on, or acts, or happens, about which we speak when we speak English.’ We can arbitrarily consistently use that form, and rigorously and intelligibly describe and prove everything, without really assuming it. Each of the readers using that formal assumption will then get the same meaning as to what the ‘something existing’ is or is not, regardless of how he considers it for himself: i. e., he can say that ‘it’ is everything or nothing, mind, matter, God, consciousness, ideals, real, unreal, trutb, lies, dreams, life, death, Nirvana, heaven, hell, static, dynamic, or any one of millions of pos- sible mere names; and then he will still, obviously to all the other readers who will adhere to AA, mean just the same that each of them does, regardless of the fact that each may actually have used a different name (or ‘‘Being’’). Inshort, J assert that this book, by using that formal assumption, will get for each reader the same meaning, regardless of what he says ‘it? ““really’’ is. That is the explicit assertion of what I formally (and at least, necessarily tacitly) assume by the very act of writing this book (every book tacitly makes the same assumption—and every speaker of a sentence). Now, the explicit proof of it is:- It appears as a tru- ism, from the very agreement as to the primary use of the ‘English’ [any] language, that the ‘existence assumption,’ whatever it is, is absolutely and rigorously wnxexpressible in any positive or actual words, as xo provision for such expression is made by the agreement. (As a further fact, whieh the reader may verify by personal trial, or which is made to appear im- plicitly by this whole book, no such provision for that ex- pression—the expression in words or ‘English’ of a real assumption which has any positive, actual, or intelligible meaning—can possibly be made; see the remarks on the in- effable, §56.) Consequently, as a truism (which truism was asserted to begin with: and the fact that there zs this ob- servable truism, or obvious ‘‘circle of reason,’’ is the absolute verbal proof—ef. §35), in no expressible sense is that assump- tion a real assumption; consequently, it must be merely a forma] one, or an arbitrary, temporary one. And as a part of the same truism, the agnostic questions quoted in par. h also fail to express any real question; or, this is a formal, technical solution of the problem of Being (put in a negative form: as stated above, the whole book is needed to give the positive, really useful form). k. Well; if the reader did not skip, he probably finds that he does not care for those verbal gymnastics. J] do not care for them myself, because they are not very useful; for such formal expression of proof is generally unintelligible to the very objectors and word quibblers who demand it. That proof is the only sucha one given in the book; J put that one in because I have found that it is often demanded by impatient persons who do not know just what they are asking for. Such ““proofs’’? do not convince. That one is rather obviously a sample of the customary uselessness of mere verbal ‘‘argument.’’ It is really a very brilliant ““argu- ment.’’ But there is no room for that sort of stuff in this book. ]. It may be held that if the reader is to observe for One IV §23d himself, then I am tacitly making a real assumption that he is able to observe—or, more generally, that man is conscious ; or, © I think, therefore ] am.’’ But that assumption that the reader can observe is obviously included as a part of the formal assumption that the universe exists (the reader is part of the universe), and hence like that existence assumption is arbitrary. As a matter of actual practical fact, that formal existence assumption includes any assertion which I wish to call to the reader’s attention for his personal verification. Any non-dogmatic book or sentence makes the same assumption, and leaves the verification to the reader or hearer. In prae- tice, I simply refrain from pontifically asserting that anything is so: the book lets the reader assert that anything whatever is so or not so, just as he likes to say; and if he will then stick to that verbal agreement, that 4—=A can not simultane- ously be A is not =A, the book proves that his further con- clusions, verbally consistent with that assertion, give him absolute knowledge, and knowledge that essentially coin- cides with all other persons’ similar knowledge, regardless of how differently they started verbally. It of course sounds odd to ‘start’? without starting from something— without “‘assuming’’ something. But the total book wil] be concrete evidence that it not only can be done and is done, but that ultimately no other sort of ‘‘start’’ is possible (otherwise, how could any baby possibly start learning?). Valid logic or language or expression is circular, and can not have a real “‘start’’ (§58j)—any more than a circle can. S23. a. In order to clear the field of traditional obstruc- tions, so that the reader may look at things as they are and make his own discoveries, ] begin here and destroy the tra- ditional logic—the logic given in the usual texts, which for convenience I frequently refer to as the classic logic. That logic is essentially dualistic (§24c), and J hence also refer to it as dualistic or pluralistic logic. And as doctrines conven- tionally written in texts are ordinarily tacitly claimed to be “‘Jogical,’’ and the logic is wrong, it obviously follows that insofar as such books really are ““logica]’’ or “‘rational’’ they too are wrong. Some books tacitly admit being ‘‘illogical’’ — Alice in Wonderland,’’ ete. And some few (perhaps less than a dozen) rather clearly repudiate classic logic :- Christ’s remarks, Dewey, Richard’s theory, Jordan, etc. ($49o0p, etc.). But by the destruction of orthodox logic we clear the field, formally at least, of most printed doctrines or theories. b. I said that I shall destroy the classic logic. To speak more accurately, J shall complete that logic. But as the completion contains the conclusion that the beginning of the classical logic—its foundation—was not cnly positively wrong and precisely opposite to the real truth, but that the logic was also useless for any directly practical purpose any- way (and actually never has been so used), then perhaps it is permissible to call it “destruction.” However, the reader ought to name that process what he judges best; I shall name it destruction or completion according to the context. ce. We may trust ‘“The Encyclopaedia Brittanica’”’ (xvi, 879) to state orthodoxly the essentials of that classic iogic:- as being ‘‘the science of the processes of inference,’’—‘‘in- ference’ being ‘‘the mental operation which proceeds by combining two premises so as to make a consequent con- clusion.”’ d. ‘The obvious, commonsense replies to two common- sense questions at once destroy—merely destroy—that logic :- (1) If the truth of one or more premises can be observed directly, why can not the truth of the conclusion be ob- served directly? Clearly, if we take a classie example of ‘"reasoning”’ or “‘logic’’—-such as ‘“‘All men are mortal; Socrates isa man; therefore, as a conclusion, Socrates is §23d IV One mortal’’—it is just as easy (actually more so) to observe that Socrates is mortal as it is to observe that all men are mortal. Hence, such “‘logic’’ clearly does nothing which can not be otherwise done. So there is obviously no nced of adding a useless thing like “‘logic’’ to our burdens. (That is an ulti- mate or absolute view. The actual temporary usefulness of orthodox logic was that it was a tentative trial which, though it turned out a failure itself, was needed as showing how not to do it—a bit of experience essential in practically all cases. ) (2) The second question is:- If the two premises are two distinct or separate entities of some scrt, not connected in any way (as is explicitly implied by the encyclopedia), then how can they be combined? and if they are already com- bined, then why say that they are to be combined? Obvi- ously, the crthodox definition of logic substantially asserts that the premises are absolutely separate—are dualistic or pluralistic. In that case the assertion by that logic that it then combines the premises is self-contradictory and self- destructive:- it says A is A (premises are absolutely separ- ate), and that 4 is not A (premises are combined). On the other hand, if the Jogic means that the premises are not sep- arate, then they do not need to be combined, and there tru- istically exists no such thing as the logic which does “‘com- bine’’ them. In point of fact, this second question, which promptly shows the absurdity of any such thing as ““logic’’ or ‘‘reason’’ being said to exist at all, is vaguely in the minds of most thinkers nowadays; and their answers to the question are not the brutal showing of the orthodox contradiction which ] have just given, but an assertion of agnosticism. e. This paragraph is a slight digression:- When the contradiction is thus dodged by asserting agnosticism—by asserting:- ‘“I donot know’’—the same contradiction merely bobs up in the next step. (That is well known; but I may briefly write it ont in this paragraph.) If the agnostic as- serts that the truth of no premise can be observed or known ——that we can not wltimately know whether the universe ex- ists (even though its existence assumption is formally rigor- ously demonstrated for him in §22j),—then as an obvious truism he has no consistent right to assert the first definite premise or assumption of the classic logic:- that two prem- ises can be combined—or even to imply thus that a premise can exist. A man who does not know can not consistently make any assertion: to do so is to contradict himself essen- tially—to say A=A and A is not—=A. He can not even as- sert that he does not know, for then he would be asserting that he knew at least one thing; and it would then immedi- ately become necessary, according to the classic logic, that he prove from that one premise, by using another which he asserts does not exist, that he has no other—knows no other thing. And it is obviously impossible—i. e., essentially self-contradictory—to do that. In short, the customary as- sertion of agnosticism promptly destroys both itself and the classic logic at the very first step. The agnostic by asserting agnosticism thereby asserts that he knows one thing to be true. That promptly makes him in effect agree that he observes—and tacitly adinits the properness of the exist- ence assumption of the last section. I complete the explicit qualitative principles of agnosticism—or rather the showing of the complete lack of any valid principles—by re- ferring to its variation called irrationalism, the technical synonym for cynicism, in §35. But throughout this book it is shown that qualitative ignorance is impossible—the expres- sion of qualitative knowledge and definite consciousness of it is a different matter, which is being explicitly treated in this chapter, and will be finally fully considered in 8150. And any absolute or exact quantitative knowledge is also impossible (Index, s. v. © Exact’’). UNIVERSE 12 S24. a. The last section shows the fundamental self- contradictions in the classic logic, thus merely destroying !t. In this section we examine that logic more explicitly, and see its completion into one form of a valid logic. b. Ifthe two premises actnally be separate, then ob- viously reasoning consists in combining them. I. e., reason- ing consists in creating (out of nothing—as nothing is sup- plied by the classic logic for the purpose, as can be seen by referring to the conventional statement of what that logic is, in §23c)—reasoning consists in absolutely creating a link be- tween two premises, so that the two and the link all join to- gether into one—that creation “‘causing’’ the “‘consequent conclusion’’ or that joined-together one. I am unable to con- ceive anything’s being created ont of nothing—even an idea as being created out of nothing. The assumption of such a creation is saying) Nothing— Nothing, and then at the same time, Nothing—Something, or A=A and A is not—=A. Cer- tainly I never observed any such process as creating some- thing out of nothing, and no one has ever submitted any verifiable evidence that he observed such. But let us verb- ally and formally assume that an idea, or that connecting link just mentioned, zs created by reason or the classic logic; and then let us see what happens, in strict agreement with the orthodox method of that logic:- By the conventional description of that logic we have definitely that the link did not exist before it was created. Hence, it is at once a mere truism that the creation of the link must also create the con- clusion, and that the conclusion did not exist as fact or truth before that actual creation. Therefore, by classic logic, be- fore formal science was ‘‘reasoned’’ out, the universe was chaos and the sun didn’t rise—which is glaring nonsense. What science does is merely to call men’s attention to cer- tain things: they look, and a part of those things actually becomes a perceptible part of their nervous systems or minds (see Chapter XVII, on psychology),—or their minds or ner- vous systems grow asa result of observing, and nothing is created (S898p, 120h, 144, 146, 166). Therefore, we observe that the classical logic will invariably produce anon- sensical conclusion—as shown typically in that conclusion about chaos. And we use that observation as one premise; and following strictly the rules of classic logic, observe and use as a second premise:- that the classic logic is claimed to exist—or to be not self-destructive. Then from the two premises—viz:- (1) the classic logic destroys its conclusions (i. e., gives nonsense), and (2) the classic logic is not self- destructive or does not destroy its conclusions—we deduce (as a truism of our verbal agreement not to contradict our- selves) that there is no such thing as the classic logic or rea- soning. All that—necessarily long-winded in order to be strictly ““‘logical’’—shows nothing more than the un- escapable contradiction in the One and the Many. The classic logic merely shuts its eyes to it. We may readily see Just how it arises and how to dispose of it, by observing the classic logic a bit more in detail :- c. Obviously from the last paragraph, classical logic is a dualism—there being always in its forms one thing (prem- ise) separate and distinct—evactly and sharply apart—from a second thing (premise). _4// doctrines based on that logic (i. €., conventional science, philosophy, and religion) are hence truistically dualisms: or, are technically finite plural- isms——tor the possibility is tacitly indicated by the conven- tional description of classic logic that there may be more than two premises; but obviously by that description there must be a fnite number because that logic requires explicit state- ment of its premises and only a finite number can be ex plic- itly stated—that being atruism (or, for full discussion see Index, s. v. ‘‘Infinity’’). And as a further truism, a vp pluralism may always be reduced to a dualism; and as A 13 UNIVERSE matter of commonsense fact, the classic logic itself takes its final dualisms—whatever they are in the hands of its differ- ent teachers—and always unites the pairs intoa One: an example was given in §20e. However, classical] logic does not explicitly agree to that commonsense fact, but takes one premise and another premise and relates them by what is actually a third thing or entity—that third entity agreeing definitely in character with Descartes’sand Aquinas’s and the Catholics’ God, and less definitely with the God of all other doctrines or philosophies that use the classical logic (i. e., those others are with more or less explicitness beginning to break away from the use of the classic logic and agree with Christ). Or, the third entity constitutes whatever it is that dualistic systems (§§19, 20e) vaguely and_ surreptitiously mention as “‘relating’’ the “opposite two principles.’’ We may note an incidental but somewhat important truism in al} that. We can see already that strictly speaking, even formally or verbally there is no such thing as dualism:- for that third or relating entity is alway put in in some way, and that makes three things at least—and not two. Therefore, all so-called dualisms are actually some sort of attempted finite pluralism which is at least a ‘trinity.’ But in verbal agreement with conventions I shall continue to use ““dual- ism,’’ merely noting here the careless way the classic phil- osophers had of bandying words. d. Obviously, the classical logic has, in its historical *“systems,’” used such a third, connecting link, even if that link was no more than a formal word, such as ‘‘relation- ship.’’ And clearly, as a truism, if the premises are such sharply distinguished, separate things, they cannot be joined —or ‘‘related’’ together in some way—without some link; for if the two things were directly joined together they would lose their essential character of being sharply distinct. But then we immediately see that this link or third entity itself, by the classic logic, needs a link on each side ef it to join it to the first two things. That fact has frequently been ob- served in the past (it is another mere truism of the logic’s original assertion of absolutely separate things); and its ob- servation is definitely the cause of assertions that pluralisms were truth instead of dualisms. But we sawin the last para- graph that those pluralisms were formally finite; also, they were exceedingly vague as to how many things they con- tained— although classic logic demands sharp, distinct things. However, for the pluralists to have been explicit about how many would have destroyed the classical logic. For if we really observe what we are doing, and become explicit about it, we see that, just as the first link needed a link on each side of it to connect it, so those two links in turn need a link on each side, and so on ad infinitum or in absolutely in- finite regress—making thus an infinite number or never-ending number of entities.” Thus by rigorously using the classical logic we derive an infinite pluralism—which is sound or valid (the “‘truth’’), as we shall also see in simpler and more di- rect ways. But ‘infinite pluralism’ means ‘unmeasurable pluralism,’ or ‘unnumbered number-ism’—which phrases or names are explicitly verbally self-contradictory. Clearly, unnumberable or uncountable pluralism means a continuous connection of things: for we kept on multiplying those links in infinite regress until they necessarily became continuously joined—for if we went to absolute infinity those links would necessarily use up everything in the universe and the last ones would become zero, which truistically means that there is a continuous joining. So the classic logic’s rigorous conclu- sion as to what is truth contradicts its base:- that there were separate and distinct things. But this time its conclusion is obviously a verbal or formal self-contradiction :- ‘unnumber- able number-ism,’ or “infinite pluralism.’ That conclusion One IV §25c obviously means either a continuous universe, or else one ab- solutely divisible into an infinite number of parts of zero size—which at least are not “‘parts’’ of any distinct, finite, perceptibly separable size. (That is an odd looking conelu- sion, of course; but later we shall see that it can be readily handled when put into commonsense terms which merely say ‘there is no exact science.’) So when it is actually used rigorously, the classic logic gets the truth by destroying its base. Below we observe that in simpler, sounder ways. $25. a. We may at once see some important facts. The classic logic’s premises are not absolutely separate, in the ordinary sense of the words. Consequently, they are al- ready together, and we can, as a truism, observe conclusions in essentially the same manner that we observe premises. Therefore, there is no such thing as logic or reasoning in the conventional sense. In the end we shall see that reason is simply what is called consciousness (XVII); and is, in more explicit terms, mind or intellect as verbally distinguished from emotions. But emotions are a part even of that sort of actually-existing reason. Man is not at all a ““reasoning’’ animal in the conventional sense. A number of very useful implications are contained in that general fact; we shall see them in detail throughout the book. b. As the classic logic will, and does, come out right if it be definitely taken as far as it will go, it is an obvious tru- ism that in the past the best philosophers and prophets and seers and scientists have been implicitly right. If we see what they meant, even though they did not say it with rig- orously explicit verbal self-consistency, then we see that they were essentially right. As a matter of fact (the de- tailed proof of which will appear from time to time), if we take into account all the causes of anyone’s saying anything, we see that no one can ever make an error: man can not make a real error: to know all is to forgive all. A short rig- orous proof of that is:- to say that someone makes a real er- ror is to say that the universe—of which he is a part,—or natural law, or God, makes a mistake or is inconsistent— which contradicts the tacit agreement that ‘“universe’’ means oneness or consistency. But actually, in practice, we restrict our vision and statements to just a part of the universe (§28c); and in that restricted part of it, aman may obviously get out of agreement, as a man, with his somewhat immediate environment, however right he may be in a wider sense. We can not actually see definitely all the universa] details one by one, especially in the limited time of a human life; and that fact is at least tacitly agreed upon when we say that someone makes a mistake, or is wrong. Conse- quently, when we use that practical or quantitative, re- stricted way of looking at things, and observe the actual historical context of the classic logic and the explicit expres- sion of the doctrines that use it, then it must he said that explicitly they are wrong. ec. But that is only an intellectual or partial conclusion. Implicitly they are correct, and the actual fact is that men have usually correctly understood them in a general way. Often hereafter ] sharply assert that some conclusion is wrong. But IJ show that it is wrong from only a par- tial point of view (usually the everyday one): my sharp condemnation is only intellectual, and I ask always to be un- derstood as meaning that I know that the total of the matter is beautifully consistent and right. Even the classical] logic is right ultimately. And even the late Kaiser’s paranoiac exaltation of his rather trivial, short-sighted self exhibited the strict consistency of natural law and his own right agree- ment with it, provided we go hack centuries and view the accumulating Prussian aristocracy that, so far ashe personally was concerned or responsible in his relatively short life, §25c IV One merely happened to focus in him. But obviously, in daily life if we say something about the former Kaiser we can not stop and go through with all that lengthy prologue. Usually we simply do not think in terms of centuries and of space that includes galaxies. d. The ultimate fact, anyway, as we shall see when we examine the infinite regress we saw the link go into ($§40-2), is that we can not make an erplictt, accurate statement. $26. a. Having thus fundamentally destroyed all ortho- dox teachings in so far as they pretend to be explicitly rational expression, we can now look unprejudicedly at things as they are, and as a child would. And we can discontinue the use of that tiresome, scholastic classic logic. I used its own weapon to destroy the classical ‘‘reason’’; but it is a poor, overweighty, clumsy tool. b. A child sees things joined together—sees them as be- ing continuous. He does not at first understand how to ‘take’ things as being ‘‘apart’’ or separate, so that they may be readily counted one by one. The reader can substantially verify that by watching a child learning to count, noting that at first he fails to distinguish the things he is counting as be- ing “‘apart’’ from each other. I am now beginning to formulate explicitly the verbal trick of language—the trick of saying things,—which is to replace the defective classical logic. That trick is the basis of the discovery of what is positively the whole truth. It will appear that al- though some of this may look like ““philosophy,’’s:it is act- ually experimentally verifiable. In anticipatiod of the detailed showing of that, I may state that I first began to get at the valid language trick by carefully watching a child learn to count, and trying to see what it was that made it such a slow, difficult process for him. The process of counting is the basic form or invention of mathematics; and mathematics is merely generalized or simplified language. We adults know how to count so well—are so skilled in the use of the trick of mathematics—that we have to watch a clumsy learner at it to see the method. ce. If it is not convenient to watch a baby learning to count, or if the reader prefers to observe actually in himself that we naturally, “‘truly,’’ or with “‘commonsense’’ observe things as continuous or joined together, then he may readily do the latter, thus:- If he observes (say) Chinamen, at first they look practically alike to him. After he gets accustomed to looking at them he can distinguish them apart, and see readily that they have as distinctive ‘“different’’ features— ‘‘separate parts’’—as we have. The essence of the experi- ment is that the reader observe something unfamiliar to him: he then sees without the prejudice of preconceived ideas, and he sees better what it actually is, with the details of parts merging continuously into each other. d. And that fundamental observation which we make is one way of noting the fundamental principle of science :- continuity (or unification or relativity). | “‘Conservation of energy’’ is a phrase that means that cnergy ezists continu- ously. Or, scientific continuity means that there has been observed a continuous, unbroken (unseparated) sequence of events—whether that is named cause and effect, or by some other pet phrase. We have actually had to learn to distin- guish things “‘apart.’’ The way that distinguishing is done by us humans is with convenient arbitrariness based on the velocity of the light that perceptibly affects our eyes: wedo not Aave to do it that way, for by using suitable tools we could divide things differently (§877fg, 83, 100, 136; XIII). e. Therefore, when we look at’the universe, at first it seems joined together and not separated into parts. Usually conventional science, as its last conclusion and its formal end, gets the law of continuity. We are here going UNIVERSE 14 in just the opposite direction, and beginning with that, sim- ply as the first, ‘“commonsense’’ observation. _ It is merely a fresh point of view. Valid logic is circular (§58}); hence, we can start backwards and use our eyes then without inter- ference from remembered dictums. f. With practice we learn to separate the universe into parts, as stated in par. d, and as we shall see in **concrete’’ detail in Part Two. Here we are observing words, and not- ing how they are used to refer to or ‘‘express’’ those parts. And we have seen that when we get practiced in separating the universe into parts we forget how it at first was eontinu- ous. We simply get out of the practice or custom of seeing it as joined. So obviously this whole book is essentially re- calling to the reader’s memory something he already knows. He most likely has never put it into words of any sort; so the words that have to be devised for this book may in some places look a little odd at first, especially along here where we are using words to diseuss an investigation of words. g. Consequently, to our sophisticated eyes and un- prompted memory the universe has rather a self-contradict- ory appearanee:- sometimes it seems continuous and some- times it seems separated into parts (the things we are very familiar with seem so emphatically distinct as to be almost ‘‘sharp,”’ ‘‘exact,’’ discrete things). Obviously, the “‘prob- lem’’ of the One and Many arises with the first observations made by a baby. He does not *‘express’’ the problem and its solution—the whole thing being obvious and simple to him, whose mind has not been tinkered with by Aristotle, the theologians, etc. S27. a. And that seeming double aspect of the universe as being the One and as being the Many can be at once ob- served to be shown or reflected both in the meaning of single words, and—more explicitly—in the meaning of sentences. First we consider single words :- ; b. A-single word standing alone is simply a symbol: i. e., the word indicates or points out to us a meaning which we have mutually previously agreed upon. The word, just of itself, has not that meaning; itis itself obviously a visible design or mark or collection of ink, ete.—or if a voeal word, is a combination of condensations and rarefactions of air, ete. ec. A single word does not, just of itself, have what we might term a positive meaning. E. g., the printed word Oh substantially has no meaning, because only by the tone of that word when spoken can we determine any particular meaning: and just the single word bay (no context) might mean a color, or an arm of the sea, or a sound made by an animal, or a part of a building, or the state of having to face an opponent, or might have several more old-fashioned or *‘obsolete’’? meanings and local or slang meanings. There- fore, a single word has a positive meaning only when we tae- itly or otherwise agree that it means a complete sentenee. With the understanding, then, that single words are agreed to imply some explicit sentence, we shall observe them. d. We may note that there are three sorts of words, if we consider them from the pcint of view of their meaning :- (1) There are words which name parts, and henee imply that the universe is separated, or is made up of parts, or is the Many. (2) There are words which name combinations or unifications of those parts (such as the words universe, all), and which hence imply that the universe is continuous and not split up, or is the One. (8) And there is a third class of words which are used to assert in some way the joining or that which relates the Many together, so as to form a One. From the point of view of meaning there is another sort of words, which are named interjections (such ag Oh). Those words formally have no meaning, as noted. When one is used, it obviously means nothing positively and is then 15 UNIVERSE not a word in the usual sense; or else it must imply in its particular given usage one of the three meanings mentioned. e. Grammarians name other sorts of words; they dis- tinguish sorts according to the structural usage of words in a sentence, which usage is not directly dependent upon mean- ing. There are any number of ways of sorting words:- into lists depending on initial letters, which the dictionaries use; into classes depending on the number of letters, or of syl- lables, or by whom used, etc. Those ways, and our way according to meaning, are merely convenient—i. e., arbitrary and not essential. We shall see that no classification of any- thing is in any way absolutely essential; i. e., we can classi- fy or divide the universe or any part of it as we please, depending on convenience (that statement is equivalent to the one about the velocity of light in §26d, and includes the theory of space and time, §§36, 57, etc.). In the grammars one word is sometimes one ‘‘part of speech’’ and sometimes another, and sometimes in a given usage is not positively any certain part. Precisely similarly, we are go- ing to find that when we divide words according to meaning the same word may be used as any one of the three kinds (§§52, 4.41) ; and sometimes in vague speech its sort is not positively determinable. In brief, even after we classify anything, it is, as we shall see, a general principle that the classification is never exact or fixed. In no case do I ever intend to mean that any classification which I make is sharp, absolutely accurate, or fixed in any essentia] way. Much of this paragraph is an anticipatory statement, given here to let the reader know what to be on the lookout for as we further observe words. In the next section we take up the three classes in more detail. f. Although explicitly I have been saying ‘words,’ ob- viously we may include whole phrases or clauses in the same classification into three sorts. E. g., if 1 say ‘this sheet of paper,’ the phrase is clearly a single name for but one thing in the universe. Therefore, it is tobe understood that when I use ‘word’ with reference to the language trick, I mean a symbol that may bea single word, a phrase, a clause, ora sign such as A or L. S28. a. The first class of words mentioned in §27d— words which name parts—consists usually of nouns and pro- nouns or their equivalents. Those words can name (1) just one definite part of the universe, as ‘this sheet of paper’; or they can name (2) a part or ‘‘class’’ which is usually consid- ered to be made up of parts itself, as ‘men.’ But ‘this sheet of paper’ may also be considered as being made up of parts —of atoms, e. g. So there is no real distinction as to the sorts of words in this first class which consists of names of the Many. I shall refer to words in this class as ‘Many’ words, or ‘pluralistic’ words, or ‘scientific’ words. They are scientific words because when scientific is given an explicit meaning it refers to the formal treatment of the uni- verse as made up of arbitrary parts (§85). h. The second class of words—those which name com- binations or wholes—is also usually made up of nouns or pronouns (or equivalents). They name the One, and hence are conventicnally known as “‘absolute’’ words; i. e., they are considered to name all there zs to name, and _ truistically they are absolute, as there remains nothing else to name. Some words that are usually absolute or One words, are:- the One, universe, all, complete, a-perfect-anything, an- absolute -anything, everything, an- -aceurate-anything (mean- ing really accurate or exact), infinity, zero, nothing, none (the last three are negative in form, but are obviously abso- lute). However, practically any one of the words that are usually Many w rords may be formally used asa One word. I. e., at any time we may formally and arbitrarily consider One IV §28¢ that whatever it is we are talking about may be temporarily taken as the whole universe for that conversation, or sentence. Thus, in our equation 2--3==5, the ‘5? is for the time being considered to be, and is, the absolute sum total of what we are talking about, and it obviously is formally a One word. In the past, that way of using what was ordinarily a part in a One sense, without being clearly conscious they were do- ing it, caused men to fancy that they did not know the whole truth. In this book, I simply call attention to that formal device whenever it is importantly used, and it becomes glaringly obvious that there are no qualitative problems. c. Whenever any explicit name is needed for a word which is formally or logically used as a One word, but does not in ordinary meaning refer to the whole universe, I shall call that word a ‘standard universe,’ or state that we are talk- ing about a ‘standard universe.’ It is called a standard uni- verse simply because we are using a word in a One form, as being for the time a formal universe, or a final verbal model or scale for that conversation, or a criterion, or a measure— and that is precisely what a ‘‘standard’’ is Of course, I have not as yet shown the reader enough facts to make it positively intelligible to him that it is very import- ant, if we are to see and think correctly, that we notice the use of One words, and especially the use of standard Ones or universes. It simply is requested that the reader keep these remarks casually in mind until their application is shown. d. We see again that there is a formal contradiction be- tween the One words and the Many words. That formal contradiction is ingrained in language. e. But the language itself promptly—and with a rigor- ous, valid logic that we are now explicitly noticing— corrects’ or eliminates that formal contradiction of the first two sorts of words by ‘making’ and using the third form, relationship words. Those words, in meaning, assert that the Many are really joined together, and as such zs the One. In short, Many words assert a splitting; and relationship words at once assert no-splitting, and thus really cancel any formal contradiction. Language itself is thus really and explicitly consistent, and there is a double contradiction in it which is self-cancelling. We shall see that fact more definitely when we consider sentences (§§31-4, 51). f. There are several sorts of relationship words, and it is often puzzling to decide just how much of the relationship quality is possessed by a word in a given usage. As a rough general rule, conjunctions, prepositions, and verbs are defin- itely relationship words; they are obviously ““copulas,’’ or joining-together words. Intransitive verbs, such as is, assert explicitly the ultimate nature of a relationship:- identity, or absolute unification (see par. h below). Other relationship words merely explicitly imply identity. There is a sort of relationship words, which words are always making puzzles for us, because the implication of relationship is so remote in them. Usually they are what are called abstract nouns, such as fruth. It is obvious that **truth’’ is not what is usually considered a part of the world; nor is it in its con- ventional meaning the whole of it, the One. It can probably be seen at once that ““truth’’ is simply the name of a rela- tionship:- to get the word we name all the Many we like, and explicitly connect them by a relationship which really and obviously exists, and then we verbally ‘‘adstract’’ or take away those concrete Many and give a name to that real re- lationship which we used to connect them, and formally seem to speak of it as either a One or a Many name:- truth. But obviously, the actual content of meaning is still relationship. g. Usually, such abstract or ‘relationship nouns’ have considerable resemblance to One words. Love is a relation- ship noun or name, and we say ‘All is love,’ or “God is love,’ 16 §28e IV One UNIVERSE . Many words formally cop” . 1 ri S. oh = tra~ : rds, and relationship wor ae weee ords in turn cont where ‘is’ verbally asscrts an identity between a One word wo But relationship W ree aga One (with- and a relationship word. But clearly, in such cases we wae that all the parts of the Many are joined together by a reia tionship named Jove, and as such is-are the Cne. e, h A relationship 1s obviously a joining tugete Pie r—really joined or connec e t—or absolutely one, d the table, if book and two things are joined together ae ——they arc, as a truism, a4 Saar rE. on if we say ‘the ae ce ie ‘and’ is a relationship word iat ie, pe positively ascer~ the table merge together without PU see in detail in banat Coed mines aie ieee the case.) Con- Part Two ee dopey ere gocurately. we are unable to sequently, if we speak post Roepe Geening’ hence, if say where the book ese h, we have to include we mention the book accurately as such, ) sais le (and implicitly the rest of the universe). with it the tab eee Aetie The That is to say, the real relation is an identity ase reader possibly does not see a]ll that for himself as yet; “ 1S something that requires a large amount of evidence, and that is given only gradually as we proceed. . But what is -esPce- jally called to the reader’s attention at this point Is that there is really—in the ultimate—no sort of relationship but that of identity. And here is a formal statement of the truth of that point, simply as definite truisms:- Very obviously, if two relationships are named, the two can not be connected by a relationship word, for there is no relationship (or mutual action) between relationships. A relationship of a relation- ship is nonsense: e. g., what is the brotherhood of mother- hood?™* Relationship, by all our implicit definitions above, is an indirect assertion of continuity; and if something is continuous or the One, it obviously, as a truism, can not be more One or less One. And that is exactly identical to say- ing that all relationship is identical ultimately, and hence és an assertion of identity. As we proceed, frequently I shall point out more and more clearly and in detail, that there is but one relationship—that of identity. i. So, to summarize, there are One words, and Many hThe reader is usually puzzled by such a question, and by this whole subject of relationship, because he has been trained into the habit of being puzzled. All his life he has heard various species of intellectual] grafters using relationships trickily to befuddle him (us- ually the grafters have long ago befuddled themselves, so that they are probably no longer conscious of being such intellectual exploit- ers). Many of us have given up in despair and Ict the befuddlement procced, so that it is difficult now to come out of it. The fact is, as we shall see under religious psychology (§$153f, 162, 166), the ob- servation of a universal relationship is a profound emotional exper- tence. If the reader rcally grasps ‘God is love,’ or ‘The Many: is continuous,’ or any other of thousands of general statements, he is much moved. All relationships are really identical and finally uni- versal. Consequently, when some conscious or unconscious deceiver wants to move the reader profoundly he begins to fire relationships at him—abstract words, **high-sounding’’ words, **rhetoric,’’ ‘‘ora- tory’’ which has little more sense than ‘the brotherhood of mother- hood’ when coolly examined. Perhaps the mast exaggerated form of that intellectual trickery is what in the present day is known a futurist literature and imagism, although the same sort of exa er : tions under other names is perennial. If the reader of that Ge ft and flabby minded he is much moved; if he has a normal] it mind, but has not studied out the way such chicanery with aie accomplished, such forms more or less irritate him; if he k pha ae Ps qe eiepene also pains him that some people Shee Be estroy thelr own and their neiglibors’ minds. But all normally tough mi i f. ‘ eae sale ate : POR ONE oy struggle irritat- withaeecnenice ae or ourselves by such fraud _vonsequently, when I here have to take tomary befuddled haze, and also to feel ir towards me. However, the fact that I am sh buneo man’s game is fairly good evide k nce th it; and we shortly shall ha ae owing the intellectual t I do not care to ve old confusions cleared away. er tradict One words. dict Many words, an out 4 relationship W and hence identity W formal nie teoned logic ‘link’), Therefore, ob- or verbal or logical contradiction is in- and unescapable. But there is, in a second—and hitherto not very explic- 1 or verbal contradiction which elimi- d assert their ord’s being u ith the One. viously, the herent in language relationship words, itly mentioned— ‘forma nates all real contradiction. j. Before proceeding to take up with regard to sen- tences that same formal cancellation of verbal contradiction (beginning in §31), we shall notice that precisely the same thing is evident in theology ($29), and in mathematics ($30). We may here observe, as another form of summary of this section, that One words, especially standard Ones, are merely what science calls classes, and attempts continually ina con- scious way to make. In this book we shall see in detail just what classification is: existent texts are vague on that sub- ject (for implicit authoritative agreement with that assertion, see ‘“Ency. Brit.,’’ xvi, 900-1). S29. a. The race for many centuries has tacitly recog- nized the facts stated in the last section, in the guise of the theological Trinity. Because religion is the most important aspect of life (XVIII), men naturally gave those facts a theo- logical name. In my opinion the men who invented the Trinity—it is a verbal form, or “‘invention,’’ as we shall see—substantially solved all knowledge, and got the same solution as this book. And as that was done centuries ago (nobody knows just when), the reader will probably agree that there is essentially nothing novel here. The chief dif- ficulty connected with the Trinity seems to have been that the priestly intellectual aristocrats promptly started confus- ing it with various historical happenings affecting their spec- ial privileges or graft, and the rest of the people stupidly and weakly submitted. b. At this point I merely mention the outline of the Trinity :- (1) God the Father corresponds to the One. He was consistently the summation of all things (apart from the priestly exploiting, of course). (2) God the Son was a sort of emphatic symbol] for Many words. As a truism, there could be no absolutely unique God the Son; there were God the Sons. But we have already noticed briefly the similar difficulty that arises from standard universes (S28be). His- torically it seems that Christ was first made by people rather definitely simply into a standard One—and when that fact was then afterwards overlooked, the Trinity obviously be- came nonsensical. Christ himself seems to have intelligibly and intelligently held that he was one son of God the Sons —a unit of the Many (§§160-2). (3) And then, to unify the God the Sons into or as God the Father, there was the named universal relationship, God the Holy Ghost. ce. We shall take up those Trinity names for the One and Many form or language device as we neeg them. If any reader thinks that these merely formal aspects of our way of talking can be eliminated, he will find an easily read attempt todo it in Wells’s “‘God the Invisible King.’’ Wells there tried to ‘‘abolish’’ the Trinity as being merely a theological and useless term or name. And the observant reader can readily note Wells’s own reconstruction of another eee ’ aye while he was throwing away the con- Christ is a ieee ie ee : ee Cee contradictory ae es . - 'd ae al ecg eee us as we shall further see ($849 iene ay 7 a eens 5 , ‘J; IS precise] posed to what Christ probably taught; and is the 5 ae . . = = 2 the aristocratic exploitation which the priests have Ae a Iced > and LT UNIVERSE for centuries (the same dualistic game under names other than Christ’s was worked by priests and kings long before Christ was born). §30. a. It has been asserted (§28bgh) that the chief puzzles men have had in the use of language were due to a failure to notice definitely the various kinds of words—espec- ially to a failure to observe the character of a standard One, and the character of a certain sort of relationship words (ab- stract nouns). b. Mathematics is an abbreviated language in which markedly different symbols are (usually) used for those three different sorts of words. Consequently, because all that is needed for consistency in using valid logic is (as we shall see more definitely, §§43-5, 58) the proper recognition, or con- sciousness, of the different sorts of words, it follows that mathematics is an easy, useful, safety-first language because that recognition in it is automatically provided for (usually). In short, mathematics is simply a language that is much easier to use consistently than ordinary words, because in using mathematics it is far less necessary to keep our wits about us. Orthodox mathematics has some defects which make it very puzzling. In fact, it is impossible to understand much of it (the calculus, e. g.) as it is orthodoxly explicitly written: I have cited Poincare twice as asserting something which means that (Index, “‘Poincare,’’ ““Calcu- lus’’). So there is full justification for the customary horror of mathematics. I had it myself so strongly that ] investi- gated them” to see why I had it. c. Mathematics was probably consciously first a science of number. 1. e., all Many words were, in mathematics, represented simply by numbers: instead of saying ““two hoys’’ mathematics wrote 2. Afterwards, those formal sym- bols were increased by writing various other brief symbols, usually letters, such as x, y, a, 6, 9, etc. Obviously, it is easy Just to glance at mathematical language and pick out such Many words. d. But orthodox mathematics may be said to be form- ally defective in that it has devised no symbols for One words that are readily and positively distinguishable from the Many variety of symbol. As we go along we shall see that the symbors for zero and infinity (0 and ©) are always symbols for the One—although orthodox mathematics does not definitely recognize that fact (§$43-4, 55-6). But there are no other symbols in mathematics which are definitely distinguishable as being One words (unless various forms of integration signs be taken as indirect One words). Usually mathematical One words are standard universes, as the ‘5’ in 2+3=5, A device is usually unconsciously or intuitively employed by conventional mathematicians to distinguish such One symbols:- putting the symbol all alone as one member 30bJ apologize to the grammatical purists for my inability tocon- sider such words as mathematics, ethics, as being always singular. Sometimes in my view I take them as being made up of various doc- trines or branches, and hence grammatically plural. ln principle, people with minds untrained in some appreciable degree need rather elaborate verbal inflections—glaringly definite grammat- ical signs of just where and how words fit in asentence,—as a means (1) of forcing themselves to think definitely, and (2) of definitely guiding the similarly untrained hearer’s otherwise unreliable com- prehension. In so far as we are mentally keen we may drop such slavish formalities of inflection, and thereby gain fullness of thought coupled with economy in words (the characteristic of the largely uninflected English language which probably helps its continual spread). There must be a balance or compromise between no inflec- tion and fulsome, barbaric inflection. Without further remarks on the subject I shall take it that the reader of this book is mentally not barbaric and hence likes to tolerate an occasional] disregard of inflectional agreements which might be unpleasant tothe more plod- ding purist who in effect considers it unsafe to give up asingle in- flectional crutch. One 1V_ §30f of the equation—as that “5.” We shall consciously employ that device in this book, in the few algebraic equations we need for brevity. But it is obvious that it would be a considerable advance in mathematics if mathematical books would, in some practically effective manner, positively dis- tinguish One words. It would be an advance perhaps as useful as any since the invention of the calculus. We are going to see that our recognition of the fact that 0 and @ are not “‘numbers’’ or Many words is the practical rule or formal guidance we need in using valid logic (§43, ete.). That last sentence states the exceedingly easy and simple fact which all this detailed talk about words reduces to. The details are all so obvious that we know them without being clearly conscious of it, and I have to write at some length to make them conscious. e. But there is in mathematics a definite sort of symbol Ge aie peer ee cca v4, (An integration sign—that long s, meaning summation——is a relationship noun.) Obviously, those symbols are so dis- tinctive that they are ordinarily practically automatically recognized, and hence are not—without almost an effort— confused with Many words or with One words. If a mighty orator with no real thoughts worth mentioning, or if some similar intellectual bunco man, goes into a rhapsody over truth, and dresses it up in shining armor, etc., soft-minded people fancy he is saying something, and are impressed. But if a mathematician were to do identically the same thing, and go into a rhapsody over his ’s, and +’s, and +’s, and dress them up in shining armor, he would be ridiculous even to the soft minded. The mathematician has not been wholly guiltless in the past of getting relationships confused with Many or with One words: those who take a space of anything but three dimensions very seriously are like that orator (§§59-62)—and the relativitists, unless they are defi- nite about the form of logic they are using, are practically like that orator (§66). But obviously, mathematics has a tremendous advantage over ordinary verbal language in that it is not easy to confuse relationship words with other sorts, usually. And there is another automatic advantage of nearly equal importance:- All relationships, as we saw in §28h, are-is ultimately and definitely a relationship of identity; and in mathematics that relationship is the equali- ty sign = (or some logical or formal equivalent of it—often in practice given in a negative form, such as >, <, etc.). And obviously, all mathematics is an effort to use that sign explicitly. All other relationship symbols are evidently a step by step process leading up to that final definite assertion of identity. There is thus a very definite goal towards which a mathematical discussion is headed: everything explicitly goes towards getting some intelligible One on one side of that equality sign. That gives a tremendous advantage over ordinary verbal expression; for & discussion in words, be- cause we are often so vague as to what ultimate relationship is, frequently omits all clear statement of what mental goal is desired, and naturally never arrives at any goal in particular —not even at a statement of Just what good it is anyway to have truth in uncomfortable shining armor. f. But mathematics is slightly defective in this matter of having distinctive relationship symbols, in that sometimes it uses letter symbols for relationships, that are like its Many symbols (also, figures and letters when used for indices or exponents are relationship symbols). Thus, d is usually the differential sign; f, the function—and there are other simi- lar relationship nouns. It is a fact that mathematicians rarely do confuse a relationship letter with a Many letter symbol—except in the cases of LZ [length, or space] and 7 [time]; time and space are abstract or relationship nouns, for relationship words :- etc. §30f IV One and in ordinary equational use are not Msny words, but are continually erthodoxly taken to be such (IX). The fact that there are such formal] samenesses is a rather positive indication that even mathematicians did not recognize just how mathematics had advantages over words. And incident- ally, it may be noted that Newton, whe invented one sort of calculus, seemed to know almost definitely the foregoing facts about mathematics and hence used a dot or dots over differ- entiated Many symbols instead of the confusing dan in- sight which the German Leibnitz seems to have obscured (““Ency. Brit.,’’ xiv, 540-2). (If the reader has forgotten calculus, or never bothered to pretend to learn it, then he has missed nothing appreciable by failing to understand completely that technical remark about a defect of calculus ~—and he is reassured that there are very few such remarks, needed by experts, hereafter. The remark just made is quite simple and intelligible if translated out of that mathematical jargon. But it isn’t of sufficient importance to any but the mathematicians to warrant using the reader’s attention on such asomewhat lengthy translation giving the full meaning. ) g. The disadvantage all mathematics have, compared with ordinary speech, is that they are not nearly so flexible in giving adefinite meaning. ‘That can at once be seen by not- ing that mathematics have but a few symbols for expressing relationship——probably less than a hundred ,—whereas verbal language has thousands of such words—so many that the very profusion is a perplexity sometimes, a]though it always serves to secure an immense brevity iz putting across an ex- plicit meaning (because those thousands of relationship words replace verbal inflections—those inflections being language’s original ‘mathematical’ way of automatically indicating re- lationship, as shown in footnote 30b: in short, mathematics is merely a primitively differentiated form of words). But, mathematics nevertheless achieves greater brevity with re- spect to the amount of space occupied or number of symbols actually used. However, that results because of the paucity of relationship symbols, and each such symbol] therefore means so much that we take it rather mechanically and fail to get the real emotional content of a mathematical equa- tion. The meaning is formally put over; but not with much emotional fullness or convincingness—in short, mathematics is not so flexible, as was stated at first. As we shall implic- itly seein the chapter on psychology (XVII), if a statement fails to arouse some perceptible emotion it is pretty nearly a failure as a statement-—as expression. And mathematical equations—i. e., mathematical sentences—have hitherto failed to arouse very much perceptible emotion even among first class mathematicians—who hence are “‘dry as dust,”’ etc. Some of them go so far wrong as to assert that such absence of emotion is an advantage to mathematics. (Of course, if a man is so soft minded as to get excited, and fly off the handle, and run amuck like an untrained Malay, ora prima donna, because he has an emotion or so, then he had best avoid them; but the more of controlled or balanced emo- tions the better—§$149, 159). But perhaps the most convincing proof that equations are not so flexible as ordinary language is the fact that mathematicians use words to say just what their equations do mean. h. There remains but little more to add to the descrip- tion of methematics, and that will be incidently done, chiefly in §§43-4, 55. The reader has seen in this section the whole of the nature of mathematics, except that possibly there is not yet enough direct evidence of the fact that 0 and 2 are One terms or symbols. Obviously, there is nothing recondite or esoteric in valid mathematics that need frighten us. They are dull and dry and hence unpleasant if their nature is not understood. But ordinary verbal language is a UNIVERSE great deal more difficult and complicated than mathematics: it is much harder to avoid incorrect and confused statement in formulating ordinary verbal language, or to understand it correctly and clearly when it is expressed to us. But the mathematics in the textbocks—especially the so-called higher mathematics—contains much confusion of One words with Many words, and in that degree properly is frighten- . . ef . OF . ° . ing, just as all ‘‘sin’’ or ignorance is repulsive. §31. a. We have briefly seen the general] nature of the valid logic by examining the equation or typical sentence, g+3=5 (§12). We then saw some more of the details of precisely the same thing by observing the meaning of words themselves. In doing that with words, we actually were considering each word to have a meaning that implicitly was a ‘‘sentence,’’ whereas the intended meaning of a word standing alone is frequently indeterminate. We are now go- ing to consider sentences explicitly, and not merely implicitly. b. When we definitely consider sentences we are going to see more precisely the same principles we have already seen several times. There is only one principle:- the uni- verse hangs together, or works together. But there are an indefinite number of ways of stating that principle, and we are now coming to another way. In this new way we are going to bring in “‘time’’ and ‘‘space’’ explicitly—they be- ing only implicit above. And simply because the things we are going to observe are things we all know, and know so well that we apply them all the time, the observations have never in our history so far as | can find been put very defin- itely into words. Hence, some of that description of the obvious looks a bit odd at first. But I do nothing more than show what logic the “‘man in the street’’ uses, and show that it is correct, and that ] use it. Everybody who has ever correctly stated a valid observation has used it. §32. a. A sentence is a collection of words which states a fact, an opinion—which states a meaning. That is the con- ventional meaning of sentence. Obviously, the words them- selves are, as a truism of that definition, a Many which are-is actually joined together into a One called a meaning. We obviously have there our problem of the One and the Many, and an apparent contradiction—at the very beginning of speech or language. As we saw, if we have simply a list or assortment of words not thus collected into a sentence, the words themselves do not explicitly give any meaning or One. Usually the meaning of a sentence isastandard One. b. Some technical philosophers, ordinarily named irra- tionalists, substantially refuse to agree that there is a “‘mean- ing’’ in any sentence or any of the universe; sometimes they merely say they do not know (are agnostic), but in effect they deny that a sentence can be made. Fundamen- tally, the non-technical person who asks ‘‘What’s the use?’’, with the implication that there is none, is an irrationalist or cynic—as will implicitly appear from time to time, as J show what’s the use (see Index, ‘‘Good’’), There- fore the irrationalists assert:- ‘“No actual sentence can be made. For us commonsense mortals it is sufficient to point out that their basic assertion or ““principle’’ is a sentence, even if it is negative in form; and that therefore, truistically, those irrationalists destroy themselves as such by making a sentence to deny sentences. In the same commonsense way the sufficient answer to the person who asks Jhat’s the use? is to say that if he really believed there was no use of some sort, he would kill himself or at least refrain from his efforts to keep alive, and spare us the question. Hence those irrationalists simply prefer to talk negatively; and it is obvious that, if we wished, we could add the symbol not to every sentence in this book and the meaning of the book 19 UNIVERSE would remain identical, even if formally the meaning was ““reversed’’; the symbol not would merely change its present arbitrary meaning. As a historical fact, Zoroaster substan- tially reversed language that way (by giving his devil the name of his neighbors’ God), with no change in real mean- ing. There is a contemporary example of language’s revers- ing in meaning in the slang statement, “I should worry,”’ which I am credibly informed means “‘I should not worry.”’ In general, as we shall see from tine to time, it is possible validly to reverse the way of saying or expressing any theory; the theory, in its reversed condition will con- tinue to mean precisely what it did to start with (cf. Index, s. v. ‘‘Direction,’’ ‘“Ether’’). |The fundamental principle is that language is arbitrary: we can twist it around to say anything whatever verbally, and then if we keep on consist- ently or non-contradictorily expanding what we verbally stated, we shall end with precisely the same meaning that all others get, even though they may have started with a statement verbally the opposite. The general proof of that is quite simple and obvious:- the things themselves (the universe itself) to which the words or symbols point give the meaning to the words: the mere words just of them- selves have no meaning; e. g., what does the word slgkebjf mean? We may say that ‘irrationalists’ of all sorts are the people who take the dictionary too seriously. It is always painful to take any part of the universe too seriously, as only the One deserves complete attention (8163b). ec. The reader who has dipped a little into general science, or into philosophy or the different orthodox theolo- gies, is aware of the historical fact that practically every sort of principle imaginable has been asserted and denied. I do not think I could formulate even the simplest, most harmless looking sentence on any appreciable subject without its being possible to find somebody, at some time or other, asserting in effect that he could observe that the opposite of my sentence was true. Those contradictory assertions are not confined to closet philosophers, and scientists. Just as soon as we make any kind of statement, some average man is likely to bear vehement witness that it is not so. A large number of average persons assert that there is no such thing as whatever it is the dictionaries designate as evil and pain and disease. Therefore, in the last paragraph, at the very beginning of the description of the valid logic, I considered what would be the result if we verbally agreed with the man who denied that there could be any such thing as a sentence —thus in effect denying, according to the ordinary usage of words, the possibility of any language or logic. We immedi- ately saw that we would get precisely the same essential final meaning regardless of whether we started by saying ‘‘a sen- tence is’’ (sentences exist), or ‘‘a sentence is not.”’ d. The general conclusion of that discussion in par. b is that we can take any sort of statement which anyone cares to make, and get the same meaning for it by expanding it fully as I am getting from my present conventional way of expanding things. All I am doing is to take the most con- ventional way of verbally naming things. If somebody wishes me to start a complete and valid description of the universe with his own primary verbal assertion that the moon is made of green cheese, then I am quite able to do it—and get it right, intelligible, consistent. But the result on lang- uage itself would be that what we now customarily name ‘‘sreen cheese’’ would be green cheese of a considerably different history from that which verbally constituted the moon. In brief, it is a scientific fact that any substance is equal to any other substance, 7/ the other substance be given a different age or time factor (including space factor, the two being ‘“‘history’’; see §§36, 57, 59, 60, 165). That is One IV §33d substantially a repetition of what was shown in par. b; the importance of the principle perhaps warrants the restatement in different words. So we have here, with formal rig- or, onee for all taken eare of those who wish to say things in different words from ours. (We shall note the practical effects of such actual variations from time to time as we pro- ceed.) There is no essential objection to their using such different words. It would result merely in changing the present ordinary meaning of words—would result finally in changing time and space implications of words into some- thing different from present ones. The only objection to their making such changes is the inconvenience of them. Most words have a customary, fairly definitely agreed-upon meaning; and insefar as the meanings are self-consistent it is mostly a waste of time to change them—it is a trivial occu- pation pursued by the trivial, of scarcely more value than making an index for the dictionary. There is no essential reason why an apple should not now be named balloon; it merely is a historical fact, dependent upon many now imper- ceptible causes, that it has not in the past been so named. If an appreciable advantage could be shown to accrue from naming an apple balloon, we would, as a physical truism, so name it (proof in §98m). A simpleton could easily devise a new language by merely assigning each word in the dic- tionary to the definition of some other word—and people re- sembling that simpleton often write lengthy books. e. Whenever words are taken so seriously as to be con- sidered essential, then they have become idols—a part (a word) is mistaken for the whole; a unit of the Many for the One. We considered that generally in §14d. Because idolatry of words, directly considered, is so trivial, it is cor- respondingly hard to detect (is ““subtle’’), and hence rather prevalent still—as we shall frequently have to notice, be- cause of the momentous indirect results of that idolatry. §33. a. Hence, we have established the possibility of a sentence, which consists of Many words combined into a One meaning. b. If we were to name any really isolated fact or thing by the word or symbol THIS, that word—which I am going to use frequently as a ‘single’ algebraic symbol—would ob- viously be absolutely unintelligible. The reader can observe the truth of that by various trials; e. g., if all colors were the same, we could and would name no color; for when we say red we mean or imply that something else is not red. Consequently, we must have a put-together or collected Many of words before we can talk and mean anything—for just one word will] not (without at least implying others) say anything. Hence, the THIS (whatever it is to which we refer, or which we name, by that word) must be compared with something else, which I shall name THAT. (Clearly, whenever we say THIS, if it means anything, we have at least implied a THAT with which it is compared.) ec. That last paragraph simply gives explicitly the ob- vious details of the fact that we have several Many words in a typical or explicit sentence—at least two:- formally THIS and THAT. That is precisely the same fact which we saw relative to a machine (8815f, 21b):- there has to be more than one part to a machine. In a real machine the parts actually join znto each other by friction—just as was men- tioned concerning the book and the table (§28h). A mach- ine, with strict explicitness, is what is usually called an “‘organism’”’ or an “organic whole.’’ Similarly, as we see in detail as we proceed, language itself is a machine—is identical with a machine,—and the words themselves insep- arably merge in meaning with each other. d. When we say THIS we mean (at least implicitly) that there are a number of other things with which it may be §33d IV One compared. If we say that THIJS is number one of a scries or assemblage of things, we imply the rest ef an unending series of numbers or names of things with which it may be compared. And that introduces and describes the primary sert of mathematical words, numbers. Number is simply tne most generalized naming, or the most general sort of Many words. Consequently, when we talk intelligibly we by some means indicate that the 7’HJS is compared (which is to say:- related) toa THAT. That means or method of talking intelligibly may be by gestures, by interjections or sounds such as are made by the “‘lower’’ animals, by impli- cation of some sort, or by explicit words. The means must truistically be explicit words when we propose to express something by means of language and with rigor. e. We have seen that the Many words in the mathe- matical variety of speech have that comparison or relationship (with each other—which we saw in the last paragraph was needed in a sentence) expressed by means of symbols such as +, X, = (§30e). We have seen that in a completely expressed sentence Many words are mutually related, giving a combined or One meaning that is the sentence (§32a). That statement of what we have observed is simply a de- tailed description of a complete sentence. And we may roughly express that typical sentence in mathematical sym- bols, thus:- THAT xX THIS=MEANING. Obviously, that “‘equation’’ or mathematical sentence is the same in form as Q9+3=5. I have used the X sign instead of the + sign, because it happens that later on ordinary science usually uses it; > is simply a sort of abbreviation for a number of -+’s. All relationships are ultimately identical (§28h); hence, formally or logically it makes no difference whether we use a X ora, if we consistently keep to the one started with. f. That equation THAT THIS= MEANING is only roughly expressed. J. e., it——and its equivalent sentence in ordinary words—contains numbers of implications which are not yet made explicit. We are now ready to begin making those implications explicit—writing them all explicitly into that as yet considerably abbreviated equation. g. It may be stated here, in anticipation (and the read- er can not understand it fully at this stage), that the omitted implications are in general two:- (1) the THAT obviously implies a series of other things, and so does the THIS; and henece—with all the explicitness we usually need, but not with complete explicitness—we can write them THAT... and THIS...; (2) and the complete implications of those things obviously are that they are explicitly named-—or meas- ured, as it is called by ‘‘science’’—by the conventional or Euclidian ézme and space. Hence if we write only THAT... THIS..., thus omitting that complete explicitness, we may include such explicit time and space in another, or measur- ing, member of the equation; obviously, that additional member is directly a repnetilion in different words, or a truism, of the first member. Hence, we have the general] equation :- THAT... THIS...=A whole Onelor a standard One| measured by the conventional time and space—MEANING, or =Energy (as Energy is the *“scientific’’ One, corresponding to our ‘logical’? or verbal One:- MEANING). That equation (which is logically equivalent to 2+3—=5, but more explicit) is the sum total of the argument of this book. All that a unification of knowledge is, is such a formal expression of a complete sentence. }t is obvious that we may then substitute in it any terms, and have a complete statement of the mean- ing of those terms; or, the **solution’’ of any problem is merely the translation of such a complete statement into the ternis naming the point of view (the time and space) of that problem. The further details of that complete statement or equation consist in noting just how we customarily use time UNIVERSE 20 and space to measure or name things, or concretely to re- place the THAT and THIS. We drop that gen- eral anticipation now, and go back and observe step by step. S34. a. Inthe equation 7HATX THIS=MEANING it may be easily observed that the real meaning——which is whatever we have observed and understood when we compare ‘this’ and ‘that’—is obviously not given by the word orsym- bol MEANING: it is given explicitly or positively by the THIS and THAT, and that observed meaning is simply named MEANING (and that name is set down in what is ob- viously a tautological or repetitional manner, for the Many names of ‘that’ and ‘this’ already gave that meaning once). Or, it can be directly observed that MEANING does not of itself positively mean anything at all. I. e., the last mem- ber of the equation, ef itselfhas no meaning, any more than Oh has, or is not explicit, or is not actualor positive language: for it itself is not verbally separated into parts that can be observably or verifiably compared—and only the naming of such parts tz conjunction can give a verbal expression of a meaning. The fact that a One word does not of it- self positively express an idea is a fact not usually noticed, so thoroughly have we get into the habit of speaking nearly automatically. (The One is, directly considered, absolutely ineffable—856, etc.) The One word merely names and thus formally or logically but not really repeats the idea positively expressed by the Many words (as joined together by the re- lationship words—by X in our equation). In short, we in practice say everything twice—expressing it by Many words, and then tautologically echoing it by a One name. Itisa curious fact—when first noticed. So accustomed are we to that deliberate saying of everything twice (once ‘“‘scientific- ally,’’ and then again “‘religiously’’ or “‘ineffably’’ or mys- tically) that it is a bit difficult to describe it intelligibly. If the reader is still puzzled, in spite of my having stated the proposition in several different ways in the first of this para- graph, he may note that if we use language that is largely composed of One words it is called mysticism—and mysti- cism is of itself unintelligible (820d). b. As the substance of the last paragraph may stil] seem odd, I shall expand it in more detail:- If THIS and THAT be considered positive or explicit language (and, in agreement with custom we do so consider it—it being the opposite of mysticism), then AYEANING is xot language in any positive sense——but simply a convenient ejaculation, which is a sort of signal that we have “‘caught’’ the meaning already given. (It is like the last member of many formal] equations :- ‘“==0.’? Zero is a One word, and means nothing explicitly.) As we see under ethics ($162), MEANING is the milder, verbal or enunciated equivalent to the laugh which is given when we more energetically’ catch the vivid—i. €., very clear—meaning of something. And a laugh is commonly agreed to be not explicitly language. A laugh, and the less energetic cjaculation MEANING, may be intelligibly con- ceived as a finished or whole or One nervous reaction Gaeid: ing emotions axd intellect or meaning), or summing-up echo to something already expressed. Hence, it is glaringly a tiesto: that to accuse a person of having “‘no sense of hum- or is substantially to accuse him of being so stupid that he can not sum up meanings as wholes or asa One. It is the same in principle as telling him he has not enough intelli- ie edema haere ear ba ties Apr tiapnsate cn Ree ac at all of us have a limit Neyond which we can not readily (and hence with a laugh, oe of humor ($149), States-~ men ae Supposed to be grave and solemn because they are handling matters weighty to the limit of human endurance 24 UNIVERSE —a variety of poppycock (XIX) not indulged in by Lincoln. c. We have seen repeatedly that our typical sentence, now in the rough form That < This—Meaning, contains a con- tradiction between the One and the Many which has hither- to in history been considered an actual self-contradiction. We see now with ultimate obviousness that the contradiction is merely logical or forma] :- for we have seen that the mean- ing is not really given by Meaning “* —that being a mere ejaculation (and itself a meaningless word—by either the classic logic or the valid logic). Also, it is obvious that that formal “‘contradiction,’’ improperly called a real one by the classic logic, must inhere, or must appear, in any equation, or in any conclusion or sentence, which sums into a One the Many that is detailed in positive words. Truistically, if we do not use words or symbols, that ‘must’? does not apply: there is no such thing as what is conventionally meant by ‘logical necessity.’’ That ‘must’ is simply the brief way of indicating the implied truism that ‘if we use language, we use language’ —of indicating that we will stick to our agree- ment that if A—A, then we ‘must’ not say that simultane- ously A ts nof—=A (§22). See §35 for further consideration of ‘‘logical necessity.”’ d. This section shows rigorously in perhaps the most obvious way that there is no real contradiction between the One and the Many. It will be shown in other ways as we need them (Index, ““One and Many’’). §35. a. The complete meaning of valid “‘proof,’’ and implicitly of valid “‘logic,’’ and of a rational or actual “‘logi- cal necessity’’ is given in this section. That meaning is needed to enable us to make further steps in expressing our general equation explicitly. b. Jf we say or assert the formal truism A—=A, then (if we honestly and intelligently adhere to that ‘if’ clause) we ‘must? not say that at the same time A is not—=A, unless we agree to change from that original A—A form of speaking with which we started. We can make that change in agree- ment if we like, and explicity say that we now agree that =something that we shall No LONGER name A. ce. It appears generally from the last paragraph—and I proceed to show it in further detail,—that to reduce any- thing to such truisms is the only valid ‘“*proof’’ which can be expressed in language. Such a meaning of valid ‘‘proof’’ ap- plies only to verbal expression of what we observe; and *“logi- cal necessity’’ is merely the “must? which we follow if we wish to be verbally honest and moderately intelligent. (It is a historical fact that ‘‘logical necessity’’ was not in the least considered a necessity, or even a requirement of good breeding or moderate intelligence, by some people who con- sidered themselves quite logical; e. g., the well known remark about a ‘‘scrap of paper.’’) All the ‘valid proof’ which I can print or express here in this book is that verbal 34¢] have abandoned the printing of That and This and Mean- ing in capitals. I find that all-capitals is too glaringly conspicuous on the printed page; the reader does not need so much emphasis on the fact that he is dealing with a symbol—that all words are sym- bols. Also, all-capitals uses up too much space. 1 could of conrse reprint the last two pages, and conceal my bad judgment or taste in starting with capitals—which, althongh they look well and are needed on the written and typewritten page, are out of place on the printed page. I have little patience with amateurs who insist on plundering publicly. Bnt 1 am an amateur printer—or rather a printer perforce. Hence, it may be well not to try to conceal it. lt is an excellent thing, I think, to give the reader a concrete ex- ample of the fact that | am not infallible—that he must verify my doings and sayings for himself. Also, my leaving the pages as printed shows that my mind it still flexible enough to conform to changed circumstances. Also, the undue typographical emphasis of the two pages may be of advantage to readers. Also, it would cost me two days of work and $2 for paper, to reprint them. One IV §35e proof:- reducing or reduction to truisms. All real or abso- lute proof is actual observation or experience or experiment— seeing for ourselves. I can not sce for the reader; hence, he has to get all the actual proof for himself, and make his own discoveries. If there is for him any discovery in this book, ke makes it—not I. Hence, logic, which is the formal technique or trick of consistent expression, can not give any real proof. Logic gives expressional proof only, and such proof is reduction of expression to truisms. d. It is not usually recognized that the only valid ex- pression of proof is to reduce the expression to truisms. Classical logic substantially says that proof is something else —a step by step process from premise to premise. I. e., classic logic says (in its syllogism) that something to this ef- fect constitutes the process:- A—=Something—Something else =Something else still. That logic then considers that the last step is inferred from the premises (let us assume that the inferring it done in accordance with that logic’s rules), and that hence the last step is ““proved.’’ As a matter of glar- ingly obvious fact, it is not in the least proved, even in ex- plicit expression; the actual proof (when that step happens to be true) is obtained by the reader for himself by observing whatever it is the expression vaguely implicitly points to, and the classic logic does not give even au explicit expression of proof, as that requires statement of truisms. (On the contrary, classic logic asserts that such expression of truisms is circular reasoning, and that such reasoning is invalid; see par. f.) Ignoring that parenthesis here, we see that classic logic thus begs the whole question, wholly omitting actual consideration of ‘“‘What is the expression of proof?’’, which is the relevant question. The classic legic in all that, tacitly concerns itself with a much different question:- ‘‘Does the universe exist?’’ But as soon as we begin to talk we verb- ally assume the existence of something about which we are talking—as was seen in §22, where we saw the rigorous formal proof that there was something. The actual saying of all which can be said, and then the observing that it does ap- ply to that ‘something’ is the real proof of the issue which classic logic always irrelevantly raises. | By declining to be thus irrelevant ourselves, we see that logical proof (i. e., ex- pression of proof) is the expressing of a truism. Obviously, if we show that 4 is a number of things, and then fail to assert that those things are A, there is no explicitly com- pleted expression of proof—no logical proof. It sounds silly, doesn’t it? That is because it is so excessively simple. And hbecanse it was so simple, classical logic substituted an irrelevant question for it (thus fundamentally contradicting itself as to what it was about—see Dewey’s Introduction for an explicit technical and historical statement of it), and the result was agnosticism, and finally the recent war. If we can dodge another such war by becoming inteiligent enough to start with things that are so simple and easy as to seem silly, then such things are important. e. If the point of the too-obvious remarks in the last paragraph is not yet quite clear, let us take a concrete illus- tration:- Suppose that a man thought his name was Smith. How would he go about validly expressing the proof of what happened to be the fact that his name was Smith? Thus:- He asserts to begin with:- “If all men having cognizance of me agree that I am named Smith, then Smith is my name.’ Then he produces a number of persons, all of whom say:- ““His name is Smith.’’ Therefore, Q.E. D., his name is Smith. Obviously, it is alla truism:- if he is named Smith, then his name is Smith: he is named Smith by those who do name him, therefore he is named Smith. Now, the classic logic becomes irrelevant right at the start ; it asks What ts his name?, and then promptly goes off on a §35e IV One tangent trying to discover what a name is, anyway. The problem of What is a name? isa different problem, which requires observationa]l proof: it involves the existence as- sumption (§22), and ean be ‘‘solved’’ only by giving a com- plete unified description of the universe and having the reader verify it for himself. (And similar remarks apply to the analogous directly irrelevant questions of number and credi- bility of the witnesses, of the judges, ete.) f. Hence all /ogical proof of a verbal statement consists in reducing that statement to an obvious truism. As we saw with respect to our equation (§§$34a, 33g), we begin with actual tautology in language: J am now showing that we end with such tautology. Consequently, asa truism of the ordinary definition of “‘circular reasoning,’’ all valid logic is circnlar reasoning (see the proof of Smith’s name). That looks heretical, but we may readily see that it is not really so:- (We have to anticipate conclusions rigorously derived later on; for final summing up of proof that valid logic is circular, see §58j.) If we ‘‘reason’’ from the One—i. e., analyze it into the Many,—we derive the Many; and _ to ‘‘orove’’ the reasoning we synthesize that Many back into the One. And that is circular reasoning. Obviously, as we can not get out of the universe, we have to reason ‘around’ in it: that is a truism. Usually, we reason in standard universes. In such cases our conclusions neglect the remain- der of the real universe; and because they do, always in such cases they are quantitatively inaccurate. Classical logic ob- serves that truistic fact about our customary standard uni- verses; and the practical trouble with that orthodox logic is that it then promptly jumps to tbe erroneous whole One, or qualitative, conclusion that a// circular reasoning is wrong, whereas the fact is merely that standard Ones are quantita- tively inaccurate. But the circular reasoning in standard uni- verses is qualitatively or in principle, or essentially, correct; and all reasoning or consistent expression is, so far as total explicitness is concerned, quantitatively inaccurate. g. This section, which anticipates somewhat, has served to introduce the following facts, the detailed proof of which can be observed as we proceed:- We have explicitly begun with a tautology or truism:- That < This Meaning. So we must end by showing that it is a truism, or is tauto- logical. Hence, whenever our expression or language de- parts from being an explicit truism—departs from saying Meaning—Meaning, to saying That This=Meaning,—we truistically must have a formal contradiction. That ‘One and Many’ contradiction is hence essentially inherent in any positive language. Therefore, the whole of a valid logic (just the logic formally considered of itself, and not considering its use in expressing knowledge) is to show or make obvious the existence of such a forme] contradiction, in summing any set of details into a whole or One conclusion. Only the ex- istence of such a formal contradiction allows reduction to a truism; and such reduction is the only proof in a logical sense. $36. a. When we say This and That, we have implied that we move or travel from one to another in some way—even if only ‘‘in thought’’ (for more precise statement of “‘mo- tion,’’ see 897). That ‘travel’ ‘definitely brings in the ideas of space and time—which are at least implied whenever a Many word is used, and never when a One word is used. As we shali see, space and time, in their fundamental usage are relationship words. For, when we split the One into the Many for verbal purposes (that Many being an inherent neccessity in making a positive language—§$35a), we use space and time as a verbal form by which we consider it log- ically done, or name its doing; then, when we want to un- derstand (re-collect) what we have done, we use (express) UNIVERSE 22 that space and time as a relationship (‘travel,’ I arbitrarily called it above), to get the parts verbally together again into an intelligible One. A separated Many is not intelligible— chaos is its conventional name. Most scientists say that a separated Many, or ‘‘action at a distance,’’ is inconceivable. b. In that last paragraph we have a complete summary of the ultimate character and use of tame and space. It prob- ably is too condensed to be obviously true; so we shall have various details as they arise (8857, 59-62, 64, 66, 97, 150, 161, 165, etc.; also, Index, s. v. ‘Light, velocity of’’). There are a number of words that practically mean time and space. But usually al) the scientists and philosophers and theologians agree to condense the verbal puzzles of them into the two words time and space. The reader can probably see from the last paragraph that those puzzles evaporate very simply by noting the obvious. It took me five or six years of steady work to learn to write that last paragraph: so it may take the reader five or six minutes to graspit. The difficulty with the paragraph is that it is too obvicus. It is so obvious that Herbert Spencer wrote a system of philoso- phy or science and suhstantialiy forgot to consider time and space: it (or they) bobbed up however in the guise of his *“Unknown’’—and a considerable addition to the world’s load of deadening agnosticism resulted. ‘ec. We shall consider that travel between This and That. If That be my pencil, and This an egg possessed by you”, if you want to understand (really prove) a statement about the two (get its meaning), you have to go from one to the other and see for yourself; ultimately, you could not take my word for it, and if you had not before experienced (ob- served) a pencil, you would have no idea what unit of the Many that word pencil pointed out, even though you wanted to take my word for it. (I might verbally ‘construct’ a pen- cil—describe it intelligibly—in terms of other units of the Many previously observed, or now readily observable, by you; but the ultimate proof or understanding of my expres- sion is that you see for yourself; you may be ocularly blind, but you still have to use me as a more or less remote tool, and use your own senses and brain for the direct ‘‘seeing.’’) That obvious fact, that in some way you have to go from one thing to the other and look at them—‘‘experiment’’ with them,—explicitly introduces space and time, both being thus at least zmplied when we speak of That and This. d. Hence, if we become more explicit in our language, we must definitely name the space (which we may abbreviate to L, for ““length’’) and time (or T), when we name This and That. We go from This to That, passing over a space L; therefore we shall definitely say so, thus:- (That This)L. (The parenthesis marks, ( ), as thus used in mathe- matics are equivalent to a <—are merely a different way of symbolizing a relationship.) But we require time 7’ to pass over that space: the more space we pass over the directly proportionally less time we need to pass over all the inter- ae oe a , thus:- (That This) L| TY. But when we get to That we are traveling only on a geometrical] line—on the line or one dimension repre- sented by L or length (and completely represented by Li T). To see all of That we have to travel out into the other two a trust that l may be forgiven for addressing the reader di- recily in the second person in this somewhat formal book. At this point the number of facts we must attend to is so large that it helps considerably in achieving rhetorical clearness to use the readily dis- tinguishable and readable second person pronouns. The reader may perhaps consider that the saving of his effort in reading is sufficient warrant for the use of that rhetorical device. 1 noted that in occasional places further along in the book it became rather absurd} stilted to revert to ‘the reader,’ and I did not do so. : 23 UNIVERSE dimensions (if my pencil were several miles long you could not see it all from the line L; even with an ordinary pencil you do not confine your vision to one geometrical line L). So we put in that fact explicitly also (although we still shall not have a completely explicit statement), and have (That < This) L?/T*. e. A logical or expressed proof that there are three di- mensions is required. It is given in §59. We usually say that we observe directly that there are three dimensions. We do not directly observe that: directly we observe that all things are joined together, and from different points of view we give various names to that one identical relationship, one name being space (see §150 for the simultaneous inclusion of a cancelling time). We can observe directly, from the last two paragraphs, that in order to get a That and This from, or out of, a connected universe, we tacitly put in what we called space to ‘“distinguish’’ them apart, or arbitrarily sep- arate them, or make them have a ‘‘Difference.’’ Then, when we came to talk explicitly about That and This we promptly used that same space as a verbal link to connect them. Ob- viously, we thus really used space in two directly opposite ways, and thus absolutely cancelled it out, as being a mere form to begin with. You may thus see in detail (see also par. j), from this present point of view, the truth or consis- tency of the general summary of the nature of space in par. a. There are other points of view which we see from time to time—altogether an infinite number of points of view, all of which show that space and time is-are formal and cancels out, are possible. f. But that much explicit expression—( That X This) L?/T° —= Meaning—does not give us the whole explicit expression :- for the This may have changed while we were going to the That. This was (as an example) your egg; and it might have hatched and the chicken might then have walked off and got lost while we were going over L to That. And in that case our expression (That < This) L?| T°® about the two things would not be quite exact or true, because there was not the explicit This egg with which we began, but now a lost chicken This. You may readily observe a baby lose his ‘egg’ thus in counting (in mathematical naming or talking); he then does just what we are going to do—goes back and finds it, or ‘verifies’? it again,—only we are going to be very explicit and formal in erpressing what we see and do. This learning the truth of all things—which from our point of view in Part One is the verbal trick of expression, or the logical or mathematical or philosophical game—is nothing more than being a little child with a good memory. The words Iam writing here are nothing more than an aid to your memory—they help you concentrate on, or collect to- gether, what you already know. Being myself too sophisti- cated about counting, I got that aid for my memory by watching a child count—as was mentioned. g. So we have to go back to the egg This, to see it again and be sure that our expression That X This is verbally or formally positively correct and accurate before we ““re- lease’’ that expression for publication, and then become chagrined to find that This is a lost chicken instead of the asserted egg. So we go back to the This, But my pencil That might have had something appreciable happen to it while we were going to the egg. So we go back to That, and verify it. And in the same way we obviously must do that ad infinitum, or in infinite regress, if our language is to be perfectly explicit or positive, or is to be accurate. (In this book, when I say accurate or exact or perfect, I mean ab- solutely accurate or exact or perfect—which is merely the conventional meaning. When I mean fairly or roughly ac- curate or exact I say definite, or something that more explic- One IV §36i itly indicates au approximation.) -—-—- We must make that infinite regress if our language is to assert exactly the de- tails which do exist when we speak, and which details are observable by us if we proceed to see them all. We have proposed, as does conventional science and mathematics, to make a completely explicit statement, and it is simple honesty, or intelligent adherence to our agreement to keep on saying A=A, that we do make that explicit statement or else pro- ceed to state just where we fall short of such exactness. Therefore, we write that infinite regress directly, thus:- (That X This)L® | T”?=Meaning. That equation does not yet express explicitly the fact which we observed, that This and That changed: the L*/T” indirectly asserts it of course, but asserts directly and explicitly only the ad infinitum travel. I put in that omitted explicitness in par. 1. h. And in deriving that equation we tacitly assumed that This was some part of the universe, just as when we say ‘2’ we actually mean ‘2 things.’ Just ‘°2,’’ the absolutely abstract ““number’’ 2, without any implication, is utterly meaningless. The most ‘‘abstract’’ way in which we can conceive ‘‘2’” just alone, and not have it utterly meaning- less, is to consider it a relationship word implying that it means, or is the verbal link, joining one thing and another thing into a whole; in such a case any ‘‘number’’ is cor- rectly and validly equal to any other ‘‘number,’’ as they are then all simply equal to links, or relationships, and the only relationship is identity (that way, in which any number is equal to any other number, is explicitly proved by orthodox algebra in $44; it is also one view of “‘number’’ taken by Einstein’s relativity, $66). In orthodox science or in a formal equation the This and That are often given by just the ‘‘abstract’’ number (as by “‘2’’), and then the ‘things’ that also belongs in the expression is frequently .forgotten— with disastrous consequences to the logic, resulting in a final agnosticism (also in the orthodox mathematical nonsense typically shown in §44). Consequently, we are safer if we put the term ‘things’ into our equation, in some form, so that in the equation there will be an explicit assertion that we are talking about “parts’—about actualities, and not about mere words or symbols. The customary scientific symbol for ‘thing,’ when such a symbol is explicitly asserted, is M, the initial of mass—a thing, or in general a part of the universe. So we may stick that AZ into the equation, without meaning that some new ‘‘number’’ is multiplied into Thai and This, but that they explicitly mean the Many. The MM we put in is to be a unit of mass—to be a standard,—-which thus merely names the sort of measurement, and hence will positively pro- vide for the equation’s being used as a standard universe jf we so wish. So, in an algebraic sense, the M zs multiplied ; but so long as That and This are also explicitly retained in the equation, AJ is unity—or, is simply ‘thing’: onze thing. The fact obviously is, that when we have a completely explicit equation (i. e., when the space and time are really taken as infinite), That and This become the total uni- verse, and in that case M is the unit which 7s the universe (as we shall see further iu par. 1). i. An additional fact about the M is that we are forced to be explicit as to a unit of measurement, if we are to ob- serve our agreement 4—=A. Orthodox science sometimes is not, and gets into fearful logical confusions (cf. theory of relativity, 866). For, if That and This are, as we took it, a pencil and an egg, we can not intelligibly multiply them to- gether. Cows Xhorses is nonsense. The M explicitly as- serts that a common unit of measurement is taken and ap- plied (ultimately it means that the egg and pencil are joined and then measured simply as occupying space, as we shall see). Hence, the explicit presence of the M keeps us from 836i IV One starting talking such nonsense as Pencil < Egg, by asserting that a common measure (finally it is ZL and T) is applied to those: names. Therefore, we have the mere explicit equa- tion:- (That This) ML” /T°=Meaning. j. Also, we truistically conclude—as another aspect of the arbitrariness and unreality of space and time,—from our way of naming L and T, that whatever they are, or however we name them, they vary directly proportionally: in fact, that is what I said when they were explicitly introduced into the equation (4th sentence, par. d), and the statement was made to agree with obvious facts which we can verify at any time by watching a baby count (for explicit statement of it from the point of view of T, see §$150-1).. Hence, L and T, so far as either the meaning of our Many expression, or of Meaning, is concerned, actually cancel each other. I.e., space and time, so far as this language we are constructing is concerned, is-are absolutely arbitrary. They are mere ver- bal counters. We saw directly in par. e that space was un- eal and simply a verbal form. Obviously, in precisely the same way as there used for space, we can see that time is unreal—it is implicitly done in §150. And in this paragraph we see further, and asa formally separate observation, that when we consider time and space together, they themselves formally cance! or contradict the reality of each other. In sbort, our language machine is a very close-knit affair. In whatever way we regard it, we may see at once that there is always the formal contradiction (here we observe it be- tween Land T), but that always the very description of the language structure truistically declares the contradiction to be unreal because it at once cancels. These somewhat mi- nute examinations of the language machine—e. g., the one in this paragraph—need not be remembered. They are ex- ceedingly tiresome if yeu try to remembér them; I never remember them, but work them out by direct observation when I need them. But if there is any point of the exten- sive, important conclusions we are shortly to reach which you wish to see for yourself in ultimate detail, then these minute details are here to refer to. k. Perhaps some readers have formerly been puzzled by the idea that time and space are ‘“‘real’’ in the sense of con- crete or objective (although leading scientists objected to the idea on the ground that £ and 7' could not be manipu- lated in a test tube as ceuld HzO); or by the dualists’ messes of time and space, and by views as to ‘‘transcending’’ them, apparently in our Many personality; or by the mathe- maticians’ n-fold space which they themselves blandly admit is sensibly inconceivable (§62). For those readers, as a gcneral means of clearing up those puzzles, I add this para- graph of direct observations as to the nature of space and time. (From time to time additional concrete details, more easily seen than this paragraph, are added.) It is cleer that we have above used space and time, or Land T, simply as verbal copulas. They are a paired name (i. e., L/T) for God the Holy Ghost, which we wnplicitly intro- duce when we first consider This and That as separate (intro- ducing it in order to make them separate), and then have to put in a second time (cancelling the original contradiction) in order to get Zhis and That back together again into the One. Hence, £/T' is simply tautological with the xX. Therefore, in the expression (That This)L/T, the contra- dictions ‘<<’ and ‘Z£/7” mutually cancel—which is another way of showing how close-knit is our language machine. Perhaps the simplest way of seeing the nature of time and space is to try for yourself to see which of the three kinds of words (as in the Trinity) they correspond with when used in the senses above. Of course, space is sometimes used as meaning that which is a part of the universe and UNIVERSE 24 really meaning the matter that fills it, as a cubte foot—which insofar as it is a Many term obviously indicates the human foot. And sometimes it is used to mean the total universe, as all spuce; then it is obviously a One word. And t2me may similarly be used as each of the three sorts of words; but it is not so usual for time to be anything but a relationship word. l. If we had actually done all that traveling which was or is necessary in order to get the absolutely accurate (al- though not yet fully explicit) statement, (That X This) ML” | T *=Meaning, we obviously would have traveled, naming or counting, all over the universe. And obviously, the That ann This would then have finally coincided as being absolutely identical with the universe, or as forming the universe (see last sentence, par. h). Hence we can drop the verbal counters This and That if we like (as they have merged into identity; also because it is often customary in everyday language to do so; and also because we shall still have in the MM an explicit name for concrete things), and we have left the 31L°/7'", which is still the universe, ora One or meaning. Or, we have M [meaning the whole universe] = Meaning= Universe,—which is obviously the truism The One=The One. And we have noted or observed only one fact in the whole process of writing an explicit and accurate sentence or equation—the other observations were merely of word forms or agreements: were arbitrary inventions. That fact is that the This (which merged with the That and hence implied it: and also implied the M and is the M if we drop explicit mention of This), varied in some way while we were engaged in traveling over Zin 7. (The concrete fact was that the egg hatched, or at least changed in some way. The object of cold storage is to prevent as much as possible eggs’ changing—and it is well known that even there they still do change. Part Two shows in detail that all things always are changing. ) Also, the fact that there was change is truistically expressed by the verbal logic or form:- that the That and This changed so as absolutely to merge into each other and hence become identical with the universe (mutu- ally inclusive). But that truism has not been fully verbally expressed in our equation—especially it has not been defin- itely asserted that M, which explicitly names This, does thus vary. Therefore, we will explicitly say what we observed, thus:- M(vurying with) L” | T° =Meaning, or Unwerse. That equation is then simply our truism, The One=The One. But the truism, in that explicit AZ form, asserts that the parts of the universe move or change in some way. And that motion or change is nothing more than a verbal or formal agreement (so far as expression is concerned) with our formal assumption that we go from This to That (or, finally, so far as expres- sion is concerned, motion or ““energy’’ or “‘life’’ is nothing more than that the universe is formally divided—‘ changed’ —into parts, or into This and That: cf. 8850, 97); Therefore, in expression, we have simply a more explicit tru- ism. And if we take it as an observable or existing fact that the parts change, then we accept motion as a fact, as change is motion. But, as we shall see (especially in 897), we do not need to assert that ““motion’’ is a fact, or ‘exists.’ We can assert absolute rest’’ or “eternally static’’ (some peo- ple do do s0) and we would finally get the same meaning. So it errs whether we say ‘rest’ or ‘motion.’ Motion” is more conventional, so I take that word. PP gab eapten app iirla bard ’ completely explicit and ac- curate—logically or verbally. (We as finite individuals can not of course practically use any such expression; we come to that point in §38.) When we say ‘John is a boy,’ we imply that complete equation. ae in ieee en of ere anes Boa rst member of that 95 UNIVERSE equation, depending on the degree of explicitness we wish to achieve, as follows:- That This; (That This)L/T; (That X This)L°/T”; (That This)ML°/T"; = Mvarying with)L”/T”; and M [meaning a whole One]. In the next section we begin to note important conclusions and applica- tions. Here, we shall obtain one more variation in the method of writing it that is of considerable use. n. We have seen that in order to write That and This accurately, we are forced into an infinite regress of compar- ing them more and more carefully, because they change. The changing was a mere truism of introducing space and time at the beginning as a means of getting This and That. Above, I have explicitly expressed that regress by L”/T™. There is another more conventional way of expressing it which we shall find more useful:- We may write it That... * This...3; or, we may express the same thing with a single word or symbol, as That..., or M..., or This.... The dots . are the usual typographical sign indicating a continuing series, or regress, or verbal step-by-step process, when ex- plicit naming of all the members of the series is not gone through with. Or, the dots mean simply ‘‘ete.,’’ or mean that the completion of our ad infinitum process is omitted. (In English the dots ty pographically spread out, thus:- .. .3 but for obvious reasons it is preferable to use the compact French fashion in this book.) We may conceive the meaning of the dots in a much simpler (i. e., more familiar) way than to consider that they replace the M”/T™:- When we say This we imply that there are other This’s and That’s. Hence, we may say that the dots ... mean that in order to state This completely or accurately we have to go on and name an infinity of Zhis’s in comparison. Therefore, explicit typographical expression of any This—of any part of the universe, or of any unit of the Many—is This... . 837. a. By explicitly formally expressing any statement, using general words or symbols to do it, we have derived an equation or sentence which we can put into various forms, depending on how explicit we wish to be. And we have seen that each form reduces to an explicit truism. Thus, the general explicit form was M(varying with)L” | T ”=Mean- ing, or Universe: we may write that, M...—Universe, and obviously (as a truism of our agreement as to what symbols mean) M... is the universe, and we have Universe= Universe. b. But clearly such explicit truisms are not useful in ordinary ‘speech. Also, in ordinary language we can not actually express that infinite regress which is implied when- ever we use a Many word. Therefore, we need (1) to get those various forms into directly useful shape, and (2) then to note, and express very carefully in conventional terms, just what our practical] typical equations or sentences mean. Actually, we are going to see that all the general laws of science, philosophy, and religion are definitely implied—even expresscd—in those type sentences. It will take the whole book to show that. But it is obvious that if truth is consistent or unified, then it is a truism that all of it may be reduced to explicit expression by one typical sentence. ec. The form which is usually implicitly used in every- day speech is That... This...—=Meaning. That equation simply explicitly asserts a comparison of things—a verifica- tion. And it is obvious that when we talk we compare things—describe the less well known in terms of mutually familiar things. Or, all language is metaphor or simile. It is better to know explicitly that trick of talking. Then we are less liable to depart from it, and try to talk of things as being absolutely separate (which of course implies that they are absolutely without comparison); such talk is nonsensical. d. As immediate rough evidence of the fact that that ‘ 6é ree 3 6é 3 everyday equation explains’ things, or solves problems, One IV §37e or gives intelligible talk, we may in the remainder of this section observe some examples of its use. (These samples are here quite roughly stated: the more definite statements —which would not be very intelligible at this point—are in the last chapters. ) Our Constitution makes a broad comparison of (1) That and (2) This by the method or terms of comparing or joining (1) the various state governments and (2) the federal government. The (1) state governments may run into as many explicit dots (State Governments...) as we can write, by naming governors, legislators, etc., on to the individual citizens—and on to the parts of their component atoms. And (2) Federal Government... may have as many dots as we care to name, such as president, congressmen, messenger boys, on to the details ‘federal citizens,’ and on to pins owned by them, etc. The Constitution broadly makes the Federal Government... react as a verba] Many, or as a part of a machine, with State Governments..., thus:- State Governments... < Federal Government...—=Country, or Na- tion. That is a standard universe (unless we consider it in the light of §47, which we need not, here). But we can divide our Nation into reacting pairs in an indefinite num- ber of ways by making a division in those infinite details or dots from other points of view. Thus, we have People... < Officials... (a form of equation which is recognized or indicated by the first ten amendments to the Constitution—the so- called bill of rights). Or, we may have Congress... >< Presi- dent.... In that pair, the dois in President... obviously wil] finally include the people who elect a particular man as presi- dent (which means, for one thing, in ordinary language, that the people are perceptibly a part of the president as such, in that they can have him impeached, etc.). But Congress... also includes with more or less definiteness the same people. So there is an obvious example of That... and This... becom- ing identical when carried out a little in detail. The Constitution explicitly asserts a democracy—a reacting, or interacting, or formally and explicitly (as well as actually) related That... < This..., or machine. And the Constitution in effect states that regardless of how the standard One or Country be considered as thus arbitrarily or ‘logically’ divided into parts, they are compared, or balanced, or are of equal logical or formal importance, but explicitly are not of equal quantitative importance or “‘value.”’ e. Butin an attempted aristocracy or autocracy (there can not possibly bea real or actual one; §174) anattempt is made to depart from the valid equation That... X This... —=Meaning. The people in an aristocracy are mostly called subjects or vassals, meaning that they are expected to be essentially or in principle subordinate, and xot a complementary or re- acting part of the whole. In short, with respect to the gov- ernment (to the autocratic officials) the people are said to be officially or logically nothing or zero, so that we bave the attempted equation Oficials—Nation, or One. 1. e., it is in verbal effect denied that there is any reacting part, or other unit of the Many such as That...; and it is also denied that there can be any dots, which can, by a division from a dif- ferent point of view, give reacting or comparable parts. Obviously that aristocratic or dualistic point of view is arrant nonsense. As soon as we see how we must talk about the Many if we are to talk at all in positive or concrete terms, we see that there must be reacting parts, or a machine. When the autocrat says that he is the state, he asserts:- An individual of the Many==The One—which is obviously equiva- lent to the claim of divine right, or ex officio infallibility, because in conventional terms the One is God. Such logical absurdity is admired and praised by some; by others it is variously named autocracy, aristocracy, egotism, paranoia, megalomania, hysteria, or excessive selfishness. All §87e 1V One of that states a logical or gialitative proposition. | have made no assertion or implication that onc part of the essen- tial machine is quantitatively equal to another part. Asa fact, no two parts can ever be quantitatively equal during a finite time (S$162i, 164, 167-8). The quantitative sizes of That and This become a matter for measurement, by means of L and T, and we are to investigate that matter; but clearly, that difference in size does not affect the principle that there must erplicitly be at least two reacting parts. f. Thus we see that essentially there are no ‘‘superiors’’ or “‘inferiors’? among the parts of the One. On the other hand, quantitatively, or from the arbitrary L and T point of view, the parts of the One are always of different sizes. That double aspect of the application of our equation— (1) the essential or qualitative aspect is the One; (2) the quantitative aspect is the Many—runs throngh every act of our lives. Thus:- no “‘line’’ organization can, as such, pos- sibly work, as it is se]f-contradictory nonsense (§8$174c, 175, 167). Aline organizationis the so-called military one, wherein there are asserted to be essential superiors and in- feriors (so that by virtue of rank an order is correct, ete.— Just as the pope, in the Catholic line organization or ecclesi- astic hierarchy, is nonsensically held officialiy infallible). g. Those conclusions are anticipated here to show that what superficially seems to be arather trivial investigation of words clears up everyday matters that confuse and puzzle many. Continually we are going to be using that form That... X This...—=Meaning. And usually we find that merely to express a point of view in that form throws such an iJluminating light that further explanation is rather need- less. Also, as we all must be able to estimate the different quantitative sizes of men (KXVII1, X1X), we further need to know about the measuring form of that equation—we need to know very definitely about Z and 7, and see how those apparently ‘‘abstract’’ relationships are applied to simple ‘“material’’ parts of the universe—as a means of learning to apply that form to the complicated parts named men. CHAPTER V. General statement and proof of how to apply language. S38. a. Wemay write onr explicit statement thus:- That... X This... = (That This)ML”/T” = Mvarying with) L” /T ”=Universe, or Energy. In practice, an infinite regress or the L”/T'™ is not positively stateable. | Conse- quently, in order to get rid of it explicity, we assume (this is an actual assumption, in that it is not an exact fact, and will always in practice make cur equation inaccurate quantitatively ; but in §42d we get rid of the assumption formally or logic- ally or qualitatively by cancelling it out—doing that by the simple method of asserting the real truth:- that the equa- tion is inexact) ——-we ussume that This does not change enough to make any particular or important inaccuracy in the truth of what we say, during the time we go to That, if we do not return and re-view and re-state This. Or, we assume that we can guess at what change there will be in This, and hence state wiat the parts This and That are simultaneously, without going back to Tis to see that change—and thereby losing the exact change in That, and having to return, and so on ad infinitum. We therefore, (1) drop explicit stating of the dots before they become absolutely infinity (we as fin- ite individuals have to discontinue naming them at some time); and (2) we also drop the infinite Z’s and 7’s that symbolically gave the impractical positive naming, and have :- That... X This... = (ThatXThis)ML3?/T? = M(varying with) L?/T?—=Energy. The dots... of That..., ete., now tional in form as it is validly possible to make it. UNIVERSE 26 mean in practice that we can not positively go on and name each onc to infinity. They also, in practice, explicitly mean that they replace the ML®/T? in the more explicit form, (That X This) ML®/T?; i. e., That... X This... is really an abbreviation which implies always that a definite measure- ment by Z°/7? must be made if we are quite practically ex- plicit. Usually in this book J do not print that full form (That X This) ML? / T°. Hence, always hereafter, unless definitely stated or indicated otherwise (e. g., as in the cases where I am showing what pluralism or the classic logic verb- ally asserts), Tat and This, or any of the numerous analo- gous symbols or synonyms into which they are translated, are to be understood as having dots; i. e., logicaliy every Many term implies the infinite regress (the classic logic verb- ally tries to deny that regress). For various reasons, on a few occasions ] omit printing the dets.*™ b. And conventional science, for reasons of convenience (SS68d, 72-3), changes the L°/T° into L°/T7. We may therefore drop out an L/T in the second member, remem- bering that it is implied (see $72), and we have what I shall call our general equation, or general sentence or statement:- That... < This...=Mvarying with) L* T-?=Energy. c. That equation expresses, formally and in a fairly conventional scientific way, all knowledge. It is as conven- Orthodox science usualiy (in the older textbooks) asserts the equation ML? T-?=Energy,** —making totally illogical and somewhat inaccurate assumptions ($72, etc. ). Our genera] equation closeiy resembles that orthodox one in form; and the fact is that our ‘(varying with)’ is a number or ‘‘coefficient’’ that in ordinary circumstances quantitatively is equal to approxi- mately 1 (§$72-3, ete.). But in principle, the orthodox equa- tion asserts that the part M is isolated (has no dots); that there is no other body with which that explicitly named Af reacts, but that it just has energy of itself, whatever that mystic statement may mean (of course, all commonsense people, and Newton’s first law in effect, hold that there is energy displayed only when that named M reacts with some other body or M; Iam merely showing what the orthodox equation really asserts, and how it is interpreted). In short, the orthodox equation asserts that M=The One—which we saw in §37ef is nonsense. Our ‘(varying with)’ is ultimately merely an explicit assertion that there are dots—that the part is really M..., ¢mplying an indefinite regress of other M’s with which it reacts or reatiy ultimately joins. §39. a. We begin now to note the rather numerous as we shall see, the above practical nse of L3/T? for L°/7'™ is merely arbitrary, and not essential. When we make that practical assumption, besides (A) making the statement or equation inacen- rate, we also (B) have selected our ordinary everyday Janguage as the language we shall speaix. We did not have to select that par- ticlar language. We could (1) have selected £"/7, and thus obv- iously got any one of the indefinite number of arbitrary languages of a ‘‘space’’ of other than 3 dimensions. Also, we could (2) have taken it that L was not Euclidian or ‘‘flat?’ space, and got any one of an indefinite number of languages—which one we got depending ou the quantitative degree of ‘‘curvature’’ of the s pace which we ar- bitrarily selected. Or, we could (3) have assumed that Land Tdid not vary proportionally—were not mutually steady—and got any one of an indefinite number of languages known collectively as the ‘‘rela- tivity theory’’—which one, depending on the particular quantitative degree of disproportionate variation (of ‘‘jelly-fish’’ shaking of space described in §66) we selected for any given case or statement. We consider those different sorts of languages in VITI. %8¢Usually science writes that equation 4mv*== Knergy, where m is our M; and v is velocity, or L/T, so that v°=JAT-2; and 4 is the numerical result of differentiating or averaging the change of velocity (on the erroneous assumption that there is not our ‘varying with’ —as we shall see). AL T-? is the so-called dimensional form of w%my2 which drops such ‘‘abstract’’? nnmbers (§68). : 27 UNIVERSE conclusions that are directly observable in that general form of a complete sentence. It may first be observed that the reason for using the ‘‘mathematical’’ form is that we have noticed such a considerable number of implications contained in language that we see we need the formality of mathemat- ics to make them explicit in a statement brief enough to be easily remembered—one that is an- aid to memory rather than a burden. If we like, we can put that form which we mostly use into ‘‘words’’:- ‘Thut and this is something.’ But even compared with that form, the ““mathematical’’ way, That... X This...==Meaning, seems to be terser, and more illuminating to the eye. The equation is merely a mne- monic device—-all equations are, and in a sense language is. b. I may repeat somewhat, in summary:- ‘The three members of the general equation are three different forms in which identically the same thing is asserted; i. e., the three are the truism A—=A=—A. The first member, That... X This..., expresses the Many in everyday terms, asserting that the Many is really the One. The second member, M(varying with)L?T-*, expresses the Many explicitly in measuring or quantitative terms (explicitly in terms of time and space)—again asserting that the Many is really con- nected continuously into the One. The third member, Energy (or The One, or Universe, or Meaning), expresses the One as a tautological echo, without being itself positive language. c. We may now see that in so far as it is consistently possible to distinguish apart philosophy, science, and relig- ion, the three members of the equation respectively do it. The meaning or content of philosophy, science, and religion is obviously identical (assuming that each fas a valid mean- ing, as is the case if the names are honestly applied or if we stick to A=A, and if this book proves that knowledge is unified). Hence (unless the book fails to unify knowledge —to show that The Many= The Onc), no valid essential differ- ence can exist between religion, science, and philosophy; they are an inseparable unit, mutually including each other, just as That... ultimately merges identically into This... . Hence, the difference in form (an arbitrary, L and T, or quantitative difference) implied by the general equation is the only valid distinction between the three. d. The That... X This... member is substantially the form in which knowledge or experience has been discussed by philosophy for centuries. And the same form, which speaks of observations in customary terms such as ‘‘this”’ and “‘that,’? and compares such Many terms with each other, is obviously the form used by the average man, in which to express everyday matters. Practically all of hu- manics is expressed in that form: it is used throughout Part Three. Theoretically or technically, it is ““philosophy’’ ; practically, it is the brief commonsense way of expressing what we ordinarily see or think of. ssentially, the foregoing discussion of language (which some critics would nearly surely condemn by their curse-word ‘‘philosophy’’ if they are not hereby discouraged) is obviously equally science, re- ligion, and philosophy——briefly, is commonsense. e. The second member, M(varying with)L*T~", is sub- stantially the scientific member, and its obviously distin- guishing characteristic is that it considers the Many explicitly in terms of Land T. In brief, science definitely and carefully uses space and time, and gets what it calls measurements—so that fundamentally and specifically science is the explicit form of Many expression (summing of course to a One or religion). That agrees with Kelvin and other authoritative scientists (§2c). | But science customarily by no means confines itself to the use of that explicit form. Conventionally it spreads to the other forms, just as This... One V_ §39h merges identically with Thal.... E. g., conservation of en- ergy (i. e., the absoluteness of the One—or briefly, The One=The One) is religion—-even technically mysticism, al- though quite intelligible, —and not formally explicitly science. And science is continually using the first member, the philo- sophical form; as in Force X Length=Energy; Quantity of electricity X Voltage; Volume X Pressure, etc. Further, every one of science’s.‘mathanica] theories’’ is definitely a philo- sophical form ($§88-90, 96, ete.). f. On the other hand, orthodox philosophers and the average man are both frequently engaged in talking of time and space—in explicitly using those words to express meas- ures definitely. In doing so, they are obviously technically scientific. As a matter of commonsense fact (i. e., taking a view of all knowledge, regardless of its forms), there can be no sharp distinction between science, philosophy, and relig- ion, even in the matter of technique or form (for rigorous implicit proof, see §$41, 40, 50). The distinction which | more or less observe in this book is to consider that science treats primarily of the Many—and by implication, is explicit about L and T where need be,—whereas religion is explicit about the One. When I use ‘philosophy’ I am inclined to follow customary usages of the average man, and imply a doctrine of some sort that is rather vaguely stated. I may say in defense of that rather untechnical conduct that to use That... X This... ig more vague than to use M(varying with) L°T-"*, and that with the exception of the few first class philosophers the professional philosopher, or particularly the amateur sort, is pretty vague. So the word philosophy is an uncertain, tricky sort of word to use. | When the scientist means what is strictly technically philosophy—i. e., a That... X This.... sammed into a One,—Ae usually calls it “‘commonsense.’’ And that is just as tricky a word: it ob- viously has been saying ‘‘philosophy’’ for the scientist at the very time he claimed he was abjuring philosophy. Moses and the theologians, when they want to indicate what we see is technical philosophy, thunder ‘“Thus sayeth the Lord’’— which is even more dangerous and uncertain—now so glar- ingly so that the day of noisy dogmatism is rapidly passing. g. Thethird andlastmember, Energy, is the tautological One word, and is the technically religious part of the equa- tion. As a matter of fact, all erpressed religion—when it is not mysticism and of itself unintelligible, ond hence not ex- pression in a positive sense—is necessarily expressed in Many terms that are then summed into the One that is technically religion. So, the erpression of religion is thus truistically a science—or it may be technical philosophy:- a mechanical theory. The science which directly expresses religion is us- ually called ethics (§160). Orthodox theology is funda- mentally dualism, and hence is nonsense when explicitly considered, and actually in practice is neither sciénce, nor philosephy, nor religion (as we shall see in verifiable detail). Theology is practically a spoiled word—so spoiled that in this book I make no perhaps hopeless effort to rehabilitate it, but use it in its customary meanings to indicate a certain dogmatic species of dualism, aristocracy, ete. h. Ishall use the word religion to mean that the pri- mary emphasis of a certain state of consciousness or life or of a certain collection of words is on the validly formal and also intelligible—and hence considerably emotional—sunmmation of the Many into a One. And 1 shall use the term with one special implication:- the summation must be a complete or whole One, and not merely a standard universe. (Words for sum- mations that perhaps usually refer to standard Ones, and hence in such cases are not religion, are education, art, cult- ure, and such; but those words can, and often actually do, indicate whole One meanings and are real religion, as shown §389h V One in S166.) Religion itself as being even more explicitly a conscious meaning, can not be positively expressed: the One words which indicate religion are not positive expression. So when I say religion, I refer to the fact that the definitely used Many words give a meaning of a complete One, and that One is religion—remembering that it or its really grasped meaning gives an appreciable emotional effect. That such a meaning is the One which for centuries has been striven for by orthodox religions, is obvious from the fact that all of them undertake to express definitely a description of the universe which might be summed into a complete God or One. That expression has mostly been dualistic and hence invalid theology; the orthodox reJigion itself, as understood or inarticulately held by vast numbers of past and present people, is obviously real; and the erpression of the great re- ligious teachers themselves (of Christ, Buddha, Confucius, ete.) was usually intelligibly or practically valid, although technically slightly vague at times (Christ, e. ¢., himself repeatedly asserted that he was aware of such technical vagueness in his remarks, by stating that a saying was for those with understanding, or for those who could receive it). When we come to observe the details of religion (SS153f, 162, ete.), we shall find that the more convention- ally recognized characteristic of religion is that the meaning of the complete One must be sufficiently vividly perceived to make it what is called ““emotional.’’ $40. a. Probably the most important conclusion asserted by our general equation is that there is not, and never can be, any exact science. All through the book I sliall be show- ing just what that means, and proof of it. A brief intelli- gible statement of its meaning is that if momentarily we succeeded, by one chance in infinity, in getting the exact dimensions of (say) this sheet of paper, then at the next in- stant those dimensions would be inaccurate. Or, stated in amore technica] way, there is not a single pliysieal or ‘“seientifie’’ ““constant,’’ and can not be. There is no such thing as a constant or eternal atom, cr 2 constant or fixed atomie weight, or ‘‘conservation’’ of a certain mass, ora fixed or eternal ““person’’ or personality—short of the total universe. b. An important, intelligible way of considering the fact that there is no exact science is to state it from the point of view of quantity—of “how much.’ Te put it briefly, it is not possible to express accurately the quantitative solu- tion of any actual problem. That is the same as saying that we can not express all the really ad infinitum dots of actual That...’s and This...’s. ce. Quantity implies that the time and space relationships of a part of the universe are meant: i. €., quantity means measurement. In the first place, measurement implies a standard unit——of time and space. It may be readily ob- served that scientists have never been actually able to desig- nate any such units accurately. The length of a day—which gives the standard time unit:- one second—is observed to have varied in past centuries; and it varies slowly now (XII). There are carefully preserved metal bars representing the standard L (yard and meter): and they have been repeat- edly measured and compared, and always with some slight variation. There simply does not exist any exact standard unit of any sort-—and it is impossible for one to exist, short of the total universe (Part Two). d. However, we are acting—as distinguished from verb- ally expressing—all the time in exact quantitative measure. To turn this page you must exert an exact amount of force. When you turn the page you do exert that foree. If you had turned it a second earlier or a second later, slightly dift ferent amounts would have been needed (e. g,, the sun would have been in relatively different places with reference 28 UNIVERSE to the finite size of the leaf, so that the gravity pulls, or weights, of the leaf would have been slightly changed). This page is a This..., with an infinite regress which must be stated completely in order to achieve verbal quantitative ac- curacy; and it can not be so stated. No man can state ex- actly how much force it needs to turn the page; of course, we can, for practical purposes, readily measure it with fair accuracy. But we are trying now to speak precisely, and by so doing avoid al] the agnosticism and errors due to the vague and indefinite speech of past ages. e. Consequently, we can accurately solve quantitative problems only by doing them—living them. We can, by learning the principles of measurement (principles of L and T), predict pretty accurately the measures. Thus, without an almanac, I can guess to within say ten minutes when the sun will rise tomorrow, and that is elose enough for my pur- poses. The astronomer can anticipate to within about a hundredth of a second what the average of actual measures would be, and the navigator to about a second or so what his measures would be. f. That may be expressed in a different way:- At first mien expressed astronomy geocentrically—i. e., in terms of the earth as a stable or exact base, or scientific ““constant’’ or standard. Then Copernicus found it more eonvenient— i. e., much more accurate and brief, if we use our customary language consistently——to express astronomy heliocentrically —i. e., with the sun as a base or eonstant. At present, with better observing, astronomers find the sun also ‘“mov- ing’’—not exact—(so that it is unfitted to be a ‘‘eenter’’): they tacitly more or less assume a fixed base somewhere, but do not know where or why. This book shows that no such center is possible; there simply is not any (so far I have shown it by an investigation of mere words; but later I give similar proof in terms of all other things). We advance from Copernican astronomy to an astronomy without a cen- tér—without an exact center. Similarly, conventional hu- manics usually takes a man as « base or constant; al] onr everyday talk is anthropecentrie—man creates God in man’s own image. We are going to change from that standard, and see that man is a sample of the universe—is the uni- verse, if we speak absolutely aecurately (§47). That makes the whole universe the center, which is logically and really the same as saying no center (ef. §§43-4), It is actually making a One God the standard or base: most of us have been claiming for many centuries that we are monotheistie, or believe in one God; now we are actually going to be, or do so. It will sound odd at first, although it is merely do- ing what the race has for centuries been claiming it does— and really has been doing in actual living. Ihavea profound respect for the wisdom of what, in the long run, people do —but not much for what they say about it. g. To say that we can not solve quantitative problems accurately, meaning that we can not express oy in any way anticipate the solution of them accurately, is obviously equiv- alent to saying that uever can man anticipate his life exactly and thus be able to quit making an effort to live a better or more successful one, or stop being interested este in actually working it out. It is an obvious truism that if science ever did succeed in doing what some over-enthusiastic second rate scientists fancy is possible—accurately predict some quanti- tative measures,—then in the degree in which. those meas- ures were important it would make a man’s life a bore, take away his incentive to live, and in the same degree kill his nervous system. (Qualitative agnosticism and quantitative ex- act gnosticism both kill—ultimately are death.) To restate that about quantitative exactness in more familiar terins:- Suppose that a fancied-exact science had predicted 29 UNIVERSE accurately the important things that would happen to us to- morrow: obviously, there would be no use living to verify them, as we already absolutely experience them ?f the pre- diction is accurate: so we would simply die, as a truism. It is a fact, perhaps not obvious in detail until the chapters on psychology and ethics (XVII, XVIII), that such accuracy would bore us to death. However, sucha quest for accuracy is obviously a quest for the impossible, It is a waste of tine or life to go after something which in the nature of things does not and can not exist (but we have to be careful that there is rigorous proof of such a condition: they told me that this book was impossible; and then when it was written that I couldn’t find you, to read it; and again that it was impossible for me to print it—not to mention printing it at a reasonable price). Hence, we are, by clear seeing, finding just what knowledge we are after. h. A qualitative problem is one which asks why or how or what. It asks an explanation. And an erplanation con- sists of stating the relationships of things until we find some thing in the series with which we are familiar—fundament- ally, a thing which is directly related to ourselves as a part; is a part of us (cf. Index, s. v. ““Rebirth’’). If an average child asks us to ““explain’’ a cow he is generally satisfied at first if we say it gives milk—is related to milk in the capacity of producer. Not having disturbed himself with the verbal] puzzles of the philosophers, he knows milk, and the cow is explained. Later, he wants himself and milk ‘‘explained.”’ We are doing that in this book by relating all of the Many to each other, in a generally recognizable way. Explana- tion, then, means relating things, and direct observing of the related things as being so related, by the person to whom the explanation explains. That is circular, valid logic. i. Already, in various ways we have observed that the Many parts of the universe are all mutually related. We saw that that principle was the underlying basis of our lang- uage. Consequently, all qualitative ‘“‘problems’’ are ex- plained. We know them al]: it is the fundamental fact or principle upon which we started when we started to talk. Sometimes we may not see immediately the expression of the aspect of desired relationship between (say) cabbages and kings. J] show the general relationship between cabbages and kings and everything else in 847; also, in detail in Part Two: to get the expression of other aspects of any relation- ship is mere verbal] skill easily acquired—and to get fairly accurate measures of those relationships is the whole business of life. But the essential point is that we know absolutely that there is a universal relationship. We know it from merely our investigation, so far, of the typical sentence That... X This...=Meaning. The solution of all qualitative problems is represented or implied by any assertion of the One we may make—and we are continually asserting some One. So, speaking accurately, there are no qualitative problems. j. Consequently,as qualitative so-called ‘“‘problems’’ are the essential ones—the “‘riddle of the universe,’’—we need never worry over any **anknowns.’’ All the theological Veiled Beings, unseen Gods, “‘mysteries,’’ “‘faith,’’ ete., are like the exploiting patent medicine advertisements which in effect fool the dupe into believing he has a disease, and then into paying for an imaginary cure. Before we start doing anything, we can know positively and absolutely that the relationships— ‘causes and effects’’—are going to hold, and that the affair is going to work itself out with quantitative perfection. The Joy of living is to see just how closely we can anticipate and then realize those measures— utilizing them towards what we call our ‘‘wishes’’ or ‘‘will’’ or *“purpose’’ ($§165-8). But we know before we start that there can be no perfect anticipatory guessing. One V_ §4lc That is a very rough anticipation of the solution of the problem of Good and Evil. We are here simply getting a general idea of all things, directly from observing language. k. And we may note that the Oneand Many is directly exhibited or implied by ““qualitative’’ and “quantitative.” Quantitative is the Many, and is not accurately or absolutely expressible or ““soluble,’’ but is positively expressible with as great accuracy as we have time to achieve. Qualitative is the One, and is absolutely known and “‘soluble’’—in con- ventional terms, is so absolutely known that it is not even a ‘‘problem,’’—but is ineffable, and can be expressed only in- directly in terms of the Many. Hence, qualitative and quan- titative are mutually contradictory. But the contradiction is formal, and not real; for it is obvious that there is a sort of double contradiction which cancels. Quantitative problems are often called problems of expediency, and their reasonably aceurate solutions truistically change daily with the change in Many circumstances. And qualitative prob- lems are problems of principle, the valid solutions of which are fixed and unchangeable, and which give the general way of solving the changing quantitative problems. An‘ ‘oppor- tunist’’ is a man who more or less ignores problems of prin- eciple—which obviously must complement and serve as the base of tolerably correct expediency. A theoretical man— one with a “‘single track mind’’—is unbalanced in the op- posite direction, and in actual practice is more dangerous than the opportunist, because he attaches One names—holy names—to his bad Many guesses. S41. a. The phrase ‘no exact science’ is a negative form of statement. It is more easily intelligible in that form. At first a negative statement of anything is always more intelligible. |For there are an indefinite number of things which something is not; and as we are familiar with many of the things which it is not, we can understandingly compare it negatively with those. But there is only one thing which a thing directly is; hence, we have to observe it closely and carefully, and more or less grow some new nerve structures to provide for directly understanding it (XVII). It is hard work to grow a little of new mind; oft- en it is painful. © Hence some people protest against going from the negative form of statement (which though easy to understand, is correspondingly hard to apply), to the definite positive form, b. The first member, That... This..., obviously is an explicitly implicit assestion of no exact science. The second member, M(varying with)L?T~, is an explicitly implicit as- sertion of the positive form of expression of no exact science. That form is:- mass varies with velocity; or, in everyday lang- uage, a thing changes as its speed (‘acis,’ ‘living’) changes. That is the “‘fundamental law’’ of science; i. e., it ex- presses a form of truism to which any scientific statement may be rather readily reduced—which is what is meant by *‘fun- damental law.’’ We shall from time to time—e. g., throughout Part Two—see concrete evidence of its truth. ec. When we say that a body varies with its speed, we definitely mean that what is usually called its weight varies. The best quick, concrete proof of that perhaps is to observe that if a body moves fast it perceptibly rubs off (by friction) some of its substance, and hence has a continuously lesser weight (that technically is a static view; in moving through ether, the dynamic or ‘gravity’ results, in the opposite di- rection, are greater for ordinary bodies at a speed less than that of light—a complicated remark about measures that will require a thorough grasp of Part Two to understand— and only professional scientists have any use for it; the av- erage reader will get the same thing in familiar subjects we discuss). At this point it might be asked how the weight §41e V One could thus change in an absolute vacuum: it will be shown that there is no such thing as an absolute vacuum (§§43-4, 100i, XI, XJI). Scientists are now generally agreed, as the result of direct experimentation, that mass varies with veloc- ity (specifically, that within certain limits clectrons get per- ceptibly heavier as they travel faster; neve Bites xxiv, 401; Millikan, ““The Electron,’’ 185, 251). Weare seeing here, and shall latcr seein more detail, what it means. d. The conventional law of conservation of energy is obviously a statement that energy passes from one part (or MM, or unit of the Many), to another part, without changing the sum total of energy—i. e., without being destroyed and without growing. As we saw (§39e), that is a religious statement; it is the truism Zhe One—The One. The law that mass varies with velocity is the Many statement of that religious truism, and asserts in effect that the parts are en- ergy (i. e., are parts of Energy, or of the whole), and hence merely as a verbal truism, do change or vary when energy changes or ““passes’’ from one part to another—all of which will be proved in detail (XI, ete.). 842, a. The most definite proof of ‘no exact science,’ is the concrete or direct proof which we can get by direct observation of the fact that every unit of the Many changes. It is obviously the same proof as the carefully or ‘‘scientific- ally observed fact that mass varies with velocity (S41c). A more extensive statement of such experimenta! proof of no exact science—no ‘‘constant”’ units of the Many,—in mod- ern scientific terms, is this:- All phenomena are observed to result in (or be) some flow of electrons from atom to atom (conventional science does not know about gravity in that respect, but see Index, ‘‘Gravity’’). All parts of the uni- verse are exhibiting some phenomena continuously—if noth- ing more than a transfer of heat. Electrons have weight. Hence, all things, even atoms, change continucusly—or, are not constant. b. Such observations were made by good observers cen- turies ago. Heraclitus asserted, as fudamental, that all things flow or change. He was called “‘the Obseure.’’ It is a little puzzling at first to talk of things that explicitly are changing (although obviously that is only an infinitely smal] fraction as puzzling as talking of fixed things when it isn’t so); but we are going to derive some very simple and un- derstandable ways of being clear and intelligible in express- ing our observations of that fact. We can’t change the fact. And the modern scientific theory of relativity is the same sort of thing that Heraclitus noticed, and the relativitists have become perhaps more obscure than “‘the Obseure’’; what they substantially do is to say that they will keep a constant M or formally fixed things, and then, in order to agree with obvious facts, will let Land JT vary (866). In our everyday language, as represented by the general equa- tion, L and J are really relationship words, so that thus to vary them is nonsense from an everyday point of view, as we can not really have a relationship of a relationship. How- ever, as we shall see, the relativitists make a new sort of language that in theory is valid; but in it each person has his definitely exclusive language; in it a second of time to you is not one to me, ete. Therefore, in noting that there is no exact science we are not discovering anything new. But we are arranging to keep verbally consistent about our observations, and to avoid both obscurity and un- intelligibility, and also the untruthful assertion that some things are exact, constant’’ standards which do not change. ec. The expression of the proof that there is no exact science has already been made by formulating our general equation. To say that there is no exact science is a mere truism of our way of writing that equation; and hence, so UNIVERSE 30 far as logic or form is concerned ($35d), we have, in agree- ing to use such language, absolutely demonstrated the valid- ity of the law. I need not repeat the details again. Briefly, we used the formal or verbal links L and T' to get the arbi- trary That and This together again—after it (they) was arbi- trarily split by using IL and 7;—and we had to go into an infinite regress of such formal links (just as the classic logic was forced to use an infinite regress of its presumably real links). And that regress is obviously truistic with ‘no exact science.’ Hence, logically I have absolutely proved ‘no exact science.’ d. We therefore see further, that in the equation the This... (or the That... X This...) is by verbal agreement a generalized naming of M, which M is an arbitrary part of the universe (so that, as being the truism which we just saw in the last paragraph, the expression of any such part or en- tity at once demands the infinite regress if accuracy of state- ment is required). And we assumed (38a) that M or This stated the same This pretty well if we stopped the regress with L°7'-3 (or L?T~) instead of going on to L®7”, Therefore, our general equation is not exact. Hence, if we definitely assert that it is not exact—and I do, and we are to understand that it is not exact,—then we formally cancel our previous assumption, and the equation is absolutely rigorous in form, or logically, but quantitatively inaccurate factually. We do not need to know anything about the degree of inaccuracy until we actually begin to measure—begin to try to apply the equation to particular circumstances, either in *“science’’ or in daily life. Insuch cases we are then forced to guess, literally. We can never exactly know what degree, but in every practical problem there is, must jinally rely upon our skill in guessing fairly closely before we act. It is thus absolutely proved that nothing can ever relieve us (or an atom, or a solar system, etc.) of the necessity of having that “‘personal skill’’ (for implications, see Index, ““Teleolo- gy,’’ “*Personality’’). That guessing is conventionally called by the polite name judgment, or by the even more dignified names purpose and teleology. The mildly offensive name guess is sometimes a safer one to use, and I often use ae (Quite probably I over-do the avoidance of all shams and pretentious euphemisms; I have been various sorts of snob and aristocrat in my time, and am probably nowa snob at being no snob. lor the general principles of such over- doing see $155.) It is obvious that this paragraph is a deliberate repetition of the substance of this and the last two sections. Yct a distinctly different logical point was stated in this paragraph—lI explicitly asserted the end (or joining) of the logical circle, which is what makes this para- graph sound a bit too vague. You can at any rate see by the concrete example furnished by the paragraph that all this book is going to be a continual repetition of the solution of the One and Many. But I am going to bother you with these fine logical points only a very little—just enough to indicate that the word-quibblers can split hairs as much as they like, without being able to escape the rigorousness of our argument. S43. a. We may now observe in more detail than in §30¢ the nature of number, and then at once observe that our equation explicitly implies the one single rule for keeping expression or logic consistent and valid—an important prac- tical conclusion. b. Number is directly observable to be the name of the oaeet general way of ae, the units of the Many—of nam- ing the Dhis s and Lhat s. An ordinal number (e. g., 21st) is the specific naine of the last thing or entity considered in ae of Many things containing as many as are named by the cardinal number (21). An ordinal number hence clearly Sl UNIVERSE explicitly involves relationship: it sometimes isa relationship noun. But we shal] not consider those distinctions in this elementary book; we take simply the broad generality that numbers are general Many names, used instead of boy, tree, Jjield; we do not go into details as to classes, etc., and the standard universe number, which is 1. ec. It is obvious that if we begin to name the Many, using numbers as names, then the so-called number, 0 or zero, does not namea Many, but essentially denies that there are any Many entities. | Consequently, it is obvi- ous that 0 is not a number in the usual meaning of number. It is formally or logically a One word. Also, the name for the “‘very last number’’ is © or infinity. But obviously, the concept of number as a general naming does not imply any such end to naming. Therefore, © is is not a number, in the usual sense of number. Infinity or © is the collective name for all numbers, and hence is a One word. Orthodox mathematics asserts (““Ency. Brit.,’’ Art. ““Mathematies’’) that O and © are numbers. They are not. d. Or, we may see in what is formally another way, that 0 and © are not numbers. As a lower limit, outside any actual number or name for a unit of the Many, there is 0. And as an upper limit, autside any actual number or name for a Many, there is ©. Therefore, obviously 0 and © are not numbers, but are /imits of numbers, which logically is an entirely different thing. e. Or, we may see in another way that 0 and @© are not numbers. Obviously, ©, in any intelligible and erplicit sense, means all the Many, and hence means continuous or joined or unified. In that respect, it is clearly a One word. And 0 is a statement of a no-Many, and hence, logically at least, is a One word; with glaring obviousness it is nat a positive Many word in form. In agreement with that and also par. c, we might conventionally say that 0 is a null Many word. Also, 0 does not name the One, in the usual sense of name; hence, it might with perhaps equal agree- ment with conventions be called a null One word. Hence, when I conelude that although zero is a null Many word and also a null One word, it is explicitly a One word, we need to see the definite ‘reason’ or truism for that:- It is said that 0 is a One word because we are taking it that Many words are positive—are explicitly language. (Zero does not actually say anything; it is ineffable—and for that reason a One word.) Consequently, when we have a null word, it posi- tively is not positive language, and hence zs a One word. The mathematicians (““Ency. Brit.,’’ ‘“Mathemat- ics’’) failed to see that distinction, and consequently called 0 a number, and introduced an error that technically vitiates all of orthodox mathematics, as we shall explicitly see in this and the next section. We may see again, in a curious way, that this paragraph is consistent. The custom- ary Occidental conception of Nirvana is that it is a universal nullity, or negation. It isa One, anditis zero. We of the West do not, in holding that, hold precisely the Bud- dha’s view (‘‘Ency. Brit.,’’ iv, 744). But weare practically right in our idea of Nirvana, because Buddhism is a sort of negative language; and if language be reversed (as it may validly be, and as validly is substantially done in Buddhism), then 0 is positively the One (is Nirvana), and © is the null word for the One. And obviously that reversal—which is merely formal—does not at all make 0 a Many word, ora number. Hence, the orthodox mathematical views as to ‘“‘null’’ classes (J. ¢.) are inconsistent. f. Hence, we say that 0 and © are One words, and are logically identical. That means formally identical, of course. 0 and © are ‘opposite’’ ways of speaking of the One, and although at first it may seem odd to speak of them as being One V_ §43i formally identical, such nevertheless they are, as we shal] see clearly in the mechanical model of language given in 8853-8. Also, that fact is the general or ultimate principle of ‘“direction’’ (Index, ‘‘Direction’’). Further, as the One is really ineffable, there obviously is not any really “‘opposite’’ ways of speaking of it, and hence we may use © and 0 in- discriminately for it. But, the Many requires definite, posi- tive words; and if we were to use 0 and © in connection with the Many, even if they correctly meant that the Many was thus summed into a whole, they would mean that the sum- ming was done in opposite directions; and that gives us two languages, logically identical, but in one of which “‘up’’ is named up, and in the other is named down. g. Orthodox mathematics has two other concepts which it is continually confusing as being identical respectively with 0 and ©:- (1) a very small number (an infinitesimal), and (2) a very large number. It is glaringly obvious that a very small number is not 0, and that a very large number is not ©, “A very small number’’ and 0 are qualitatively or in principle absolutely contradictory—and similarly with ‘large number’ and ©. In this book, which as has been stated is much more rigorous than conventional mathematics, when ] mean a large number or a small number J shall say so—generally saying ‘indefinitely’ large or small—except in a few negligible cases where it seems best for merely rhe- torical purposes to follow conventional phraseology. h. Itis already obvious that in practice the only rule that we need follow in being strictly validly logical—i. e., rigorously consistent in expression—is to avoid naming any Many thing 0 or ®, or by any of their numerous synonyms such as no, none, nothing, separate, distinct, all, whole, ab- solute, continuous, total, everything, perfect, God—and, on the contrary, to name a// One summations by such words. Or, from another point of view:- we shall be validly logical simply by being truly scientific and always speaking of the Many as being measurable and the One as unmeasurable— what the measures are numerically being not a matter of log- ic, or general scientific law, but of practical life, experience, skill and good judgment or good guessing. That is the only rule, if it is taken for granted that no one is going to perpetrate the absurdity of making a relationship word— God the Holy Ghost—into a One word or intoa Many word. Even the mathematicians sometimes do that (as shown in the next section). So perhaps we should always be more pre- cise, and say that the only rule to be followed to achieve ab- solute consistency or rationality in expression is to avoid confusing the three sorts of words. Or, we may state that complete rule in terms of our equation:- (1) have no zeros or infinities in the first and second members (Many mem- bers), and always include one or the other in the third or One member; and (2) never confuse the relationship symbols witb the One or with the Many names—never confuse a ‘“process’’ with an “‘entity.”’ Incidentally, the L and T in the equation are relationship symbols. As we saw in §30f, it would have been typographically more consistent to have made them similar to the symbols <, =, ete. When we write JM... for M(varying with) L? T —2 we do become thus typographiecally consistent. And obviously, That... and This..., and especially That... < This..., are thus typo- graphically consistent, the Land T being indicated by the dots, and not explicitly named by the same sort of symbol used for an entity. i. That last paragraph completely states all the rules we need in order to be always consistent. The practical, every- day rule is the one about 0 and ©, Most people (except when they try to talk of something of which they are largely ignorant, or when they try to be oratorical or appear §4i3i V One Wise and important and weighty) by natural commonsense avoid making the confusion of relationship words. Only when they begin to dress up truth, or get off some ponder- ous piffle about the glory of SCIENCE do they become such asses. But when [ put that practical rule in that formal] and rigorous ‘zerc-infinity’ guise it looks strange and hard to apply. So we may note its use and meaning in a little of familiar detail:- | Suppose you are looking at what is actually a chair, and see it. Then, in order to he logical, you will refrain, first, from saying that it is not a chair— i. e., that it is a zero chair. Further, you will refrain from saying that it is a pig—i. e., that it is a zero chair, and that the resulting Ois then multiplied by © to make it something, and that that something, produced by putting in the ™, is a ‘‘pig.’’ And last, you will refrain from saying that the chair is everything, or perfect, or the universe—i. e., vou will refrain from multiplying the actual chair by ©, or call- ingit © or perfect: you can validly say that the chair itself is inseparably related to the total universe, and hence in that sense 7s or becomes the One; _ but that statement uses chair in a One sense different from its common, Many, actual use we started with, and in ordinary honesty that One sense ought to be explicitly distinguished when thus used. j. Obviously, the practical application of the logical rule is simple enough when we have to deal witha chair. It reduces to the rule:- say that a chair isa chair. It is only when we deal with numerous things that we begin to get confused, and to need the explicitly formulated rigorous rule. Obviously, it is essentially no more difficult to speak of numerous things than it is to speak of a chair. But the nuiierousness confuses us because it burdens the memory, and we need the guidance of an explicit rule. We see in the next section how even the mathematicians get confused because of not being conscious of that rule. But asa matter of fact, a large part of the logical errors of the world comes, not from any intellectual difficulty in being logical, but from the lack of courage and honesty to face facts as they are—and those are usually called emotional qualities (§155, ete. ). It takes a strong man to be steadily logical—not necessarily a mathematician. k. The practical rule of logic is so well known and ‘“‘common’”’ that it has, in another form, been taught to children for centuries; every well-bred person is supposed to conform to that rule. The rule is:- do not exaggerate [or if you do formally exaggerate, make it obvious to your hearer that the exaggeration is not really meant—and then, within certain limits, it gives a more vivid understanding, and is one sort of humor]. Exaggeration obviously is simply the making of things too small or too large, with a tendency to multiply them by 0 or ®. One of the Ten Command- ments is simply a partial statement of that everyday form of the logical rule (or is that rule, expressed in ethical terms) :- do not take the name of God in vain. That Commandment clearly is:- do notusea One word asa Many word, or in such a context as to confuse it with Many words. The common- sense view of the matter is that if we have a language, it can be usefully employed as a good tool, and there is no sense in persistently misusing it. However, the human race have indulged in so much confusion of terms—really, in so much ‘“swearing,’’—that it is sometimes said that language is to eonceal thought. E. g., the ““gay and sparkling and _ bril- liant’’ conversation at (say) tea parties, with its tinklings of ‘“wonderful,’’ and “‘perfectly sweet,’’ and “perfectly in- triguing,’’ is swearing, just as much as are the casual ‘“damn’s,’’ etc., of longshoremen. So we can reduce our practical rule to the homely one:- do not swear (except on the occasions you really mean it, and except as humor—and UNIVERSE 32 unless one’s hearer appreciates the humor, it is not humor also humor always ceases to be humor when it be- to him; You see, there is comes too automatic; 8162). nothing esoteric about logic. $44. a. We shall hereafter see numbers of instances of conventional failures to be validly logical—failures to follow the single rule that the three kinds of words must not be confused. The worst source of such logical confusions is the fact that practically every name in our language may be used as each of the three sorts of words. The name God is a conspicuous example. And conventional logical error con- sists in formally confusing the three sorts—just as the con- ventional Trinity has been confused and befogged until the average man feels almost a repulsion towards the very men- tion of it. As was stated, conventional mathematics does not follow the principle that the three sorts must not be con- fused; in fact, it sometimes asserts practically the contrary ; so I am going to follow strictly the conventionally stated principles of mathematics, and “‘prove mathematically’’ in several ways the absurd result that any number is equal to any other number. That will show again that 0 and © are not numbers and that we must not confuse relationship words with either One words or Many words. And it will prove the correctness of our logical] rule, and also show that orthodox mathematics needs it. b. Let ¢ and d be any two different numbers, with differ- ence e, so that c——d=e (A) Multiplying (A) through by e—d, we have c’— 2¢ed-+-d?=ce—de (B) Rearranging (B), c*—cd—ce—cd—d>—de (C) or, c(e—d—e)=d(c—d—e) (D) Dividing (D) through by (e—d—e); or multiplying (D) through by 1/(e—d—e), we have c=d; or, any number equals any other different number, Q. E. D.,—which obviously, or truistically by our agreement 4=A, is non- sense. The mathematicians sometimes, without giving any reasons, say that it is a fallacy to do as I did above, and di- vide (D) through by zero—by (c—d—e), which is equal to 0, —or multiply it through by infinity—by 1/(e—d—e), which is equal to ©. However, J am not able to find an assertion in any of the severa] varieties of mathematical books I hap- pen to have at hand, that such a process is a fallacy; the closest to such an assertion 1] can find is the discussion of “‘indeterminate or illusory forms,’’ such as 0x0, 0X, o-oo, ete., wherein it is merely dogmatically asserted that those forms are, as such, indeterminate—thus implying that logically or mathematically they are permissible. On the other hand, mathematical texts all assert in effect, and usually explicitly if they take up the subject, that 0 and oo are numbers, and hence at least imply that it is just as valid to divide or multiply (D) by 0 or © as by (say) 5— and such a process with 5 gives no absurdity. ““The Eney- clopaedia Brittanica’’ (xi, 303, referring to xiv, 545) clearly implies that there are actual numbers, as values, which are 0 and So tcugh. usually *” means a large number which fee 2 become | = lorthodox mathematics thus clearly Me Wate ee y asserts that 0 and © are ae ee ieee ee eny it, and in effect, although a : s ordinary mathematics just as we are doing here. But all the explicit authoritative assertions eee one of eee are thus shown to be that there is no aeunt that a ie quae ivi Eye een by any number ot} : : ne Pee ere an Eanouah ier than those so-called numbers 0 and and as orthodox mathematics makes no distinction in kind 33 UNIVERSE between Oand ©, and those other ‘‘numbers,”’ it truistically follows that it is rigorously following orthodox principles to divide through by 0 or ™, e—d—e is a null com- plete One—as is asserted implicitly hy (A)—and the valid mathematical principle is that any sort of complete One is not positive language and (according to our primary agree- ment that dA) can not be used as positive language, or as Many words; and when that One is related in any way (as by multiplication) with the Many member, that is equiva- lent to denying that it is a Many, or makes it a One (as all relationship is that of identity). Perhaps the briefest and clearest way to say that is to say that 0 and © arenot num- bers. The absurd conclusion given above is substantially the same as those which are named the paradoxes of Zeno (““Ency. Brit.,’’ ‘“Zeno’’). Only the explicit solution of the One and Many—which is what the rule concerning 0 and © substantially is—will solve those paradoxes. And with that solution, the solution of those centuries-old puzzles is so simple that there is no need to give it explicitly here. ce. A series is orthodoxly (“‘Ency. Brit.,’’ xxiv, 668) ‘a set of quantities *** arranged in order so that each quan- tity is definitely and uniquely determined by its position’’; and it may be infinite—i. e., ‘“the number of [those quanti- ties or] terms may be *** unlimited.’’ | We shall use such series, again to prove that any number is equal to any other :- By algebra, 1/(1-+a)=1—a +-a®—a?+... (A) Let a=1, and we have $=1—1 +1 —1 +... (B) By algebra, (i-a)/(itata)=1—a ta—a 1... (C) Let a=1, and we have =1—1 +1 —1-++... (D) And (1+ate2)/(1 poo eg re ne +... (E) Let a1, and we have =1—1 +1 —1 +... (F) Similarly we may get jy eee Pp eG) ete... etc.etc. The second member of (B), of (D), (F), ete., is a series; and orthodoxly it may be written out to an absolutely unlim- ited number of terms—may have ail the terms there are, as a truism of the orthodox defmition. Consequently, as those various series are, by orthodox mathematics, term for term identical unlimitedly, then obviously they are identical or equal, by our agreement AA. Therefore, as the second members of the equations are equal, the first members are equal (by the same agreement AA: mathematics says that they are equal by the ‘‘axiom’’ that things equal to the same thing are equal to each other), and we have:- 1/2=2/3=3/4—4/5=... (N) By manipulating (N), and similar equations obtained by like methods, by simple algebra, we have:- 1—2—3=—..., or, any number equals any other number. Well; I did not explicitly, or technically by orthodox mathematics, intro- duce any 0 or © into that “‘proof’’—certainly not in the sense of ‘‘multiplying’’ or “‘dividing’’ by one or the other, which is sometimes superficially held by orthodox mathe- matics to be fallacious. But with orthodox mathematical rigorousness I managed to get an absurdity. In a sense (in the commonsense view taken by valid logic), there was an in the “‘proof’’:- the series had orthodoxly absolutely un- limited terms. By commonsense, the fallacy is of course that if the terms are unlimited or infinite in number, then the terms are not ‘‘definitely determined’’ as was asserted by the orthodox definition which I simply took atits word. The simple fact is that there is no such thing as a positively stat- able infinite series (there is no exact science). The _ series above, if they are made definite and expressed definitely, always have a fractional quotient as a Jast term, and evaluate definitely as 44, a4, etc., which are simple identities of standard universes—not of standard universes and absolutely infinite universes, as is orthodoxly asserted. One V §44f d. There are an indefinite number of ways of getting that absurd result by orthodox mathematics, all depending on confusing the One and the Many—in effect, on taking 0 and © to be numbers, or confusing qualitative with quanti- tative. We shall now proceed to “‘prove’’ with orthodox mathematical rigor the same absurdity by confusing relation- ship words with the other two sorts. In this way we donot use 0 or © in any ordinary sence:- By conventional algebra, [—3+-47 (3) B=1 (A) Also, by conventional algebra, 12=1 (B) As the right members are identical, then (—4+47/(—3)P=18 9 (C) (D) Extracting cube-root of both sides of (C), we have ae V8) ) Hence, 41 (—3)=3/2; or, V(—3)=3; or, —3=9 (E) Adding 4 to both sides of that last, 1=138. And proceeding similarly by conventional algebra, any number equals any other number. e. The trouble with those last orthodoxly valid equa- tions is that I used relationship terms (the ““cube,’’ and the ‘‘square-root,’’ and the ‘“—’’ in (—8)) substantially as Many terms (doing it an odd or uncancelled number of times; see next paragraph). It is obvious that there is no explicit principle in orthodox mathematics which says that that is wrong; but it nevertheless produces an absurdity. There are other well known ways of proving our ab- surd proposition by manipulating the ‘“‘second power’’ (which involves a relationship), without introducing the —. The same absurdity is shown in another way (using geome- try) in §50b; and in a general way in §66. We may note briefly that the symbol // is a relationship term, just as defi- nitely as is —. And of course it is as much nonsense to say and mean explicitly ““the square-root of a minus,”’ as it is to say ‘the brotherhood of motherhood.’ Orthodox mathemat- ics itself agrees that it is meaningless to speak explicitly of the square-root of a minus—calling the ‘‘quantity’’ V (—1) “‘imaginary.’’ Asa fact, we can not even imagine that ‘‘quantity’’; it is absolutely inconceivable if taken explicitly. ae same thing applies to manipulations of second ‘‘pow- ers,’ third “‘powers,’’ and all other relationships. A rela- tionship can not be used as a One word or a Many word, or to ‘duplicate’ another relationship. f. But orthodox mathematics does get correct results as a usual thing when it uses /(—1) (and other ‘relationships of a relationship’). The way in which that is done is by more or less unconsciously introducing another similar con- tradiction which cancels the first (and, with a little common- sense, rejecting the absurdity that results when it happens that that is not done—a procedure which glaringly shows that conventional mathematics is not rigorous). So long as there is a balance, an even number, of such contradictions in an argument the result will obviously be logically consist- ent: and the verbal or symbolic expression of such dupli- cated relationships may be considered, not as giving or in any way having any explicit meaning, but as merely a mne- monic device for keeping account of the relating process. In the same way poker chips have no special meaning or value of themselves, but are used as mnemonic devices to indicate the relationship of the players to the stakes. To puzzle over (—1) is equivalent to puzzling over the ‘why- ness’ of a poker chip: there is no real whyness, but merely a convenient agreement. In identically the same way the 2's, —’s, etc., in our L?7'~*’s, etc., do not mean two absolute verbal links or relationships, or any relationships of a rela- tionship, but mean simply the verbal way in which space and time—the single relationship—is used in the language ma- chine (see the total discussion of space and time in this book), $44f V One But as this is not a treatise on mathematical detail, I must here omit the volume or so of ways of balancing and other- wise handling such self-contradictory but formal duplication of relationship counters. Those mathematical details will be implied in the investigation made of our general equation. g. The tacit, actual rule of conventional mathematics is that if its rules—which as we have just seen, are not com- plete—obviously do not work, then throw the result away, and with the same blindness try again. The savage says that if the lever at hand fails him, throw it away and try another. Actually, it is the only ultimate way to learn; it is still an excellent method; but it is good only in the ab- sence of knowledge, for it is uneconomical of time and effort. Some professional mathematicians and scientists of a medi- ocre sort tend to believe that mathematics is perfect—the ‘“queen’’ of the sciences, etc.,—and that if anything is ex- pressed mathematically we must in submissive awe ‘‘believe”’ it, or at least pretend to understand it. Well; the reader has now seen that orthodox mathematics is no more certain to produce an intelligent result than is orthodox language. That ““queen’’ stuff is obvions nonsense—the protective cloak of the egotistical dogmatist. h. The important thing which we have seen is that we get absurd results in expression whenever one sort of word is asserted to be another sort. We have seen that orthodox mathematics needs a more precise restatement to make it self-consistent. We could at this point go ahead and trans- late the above simply expressed results into the technical terms used by Jlogisttcs—which is mathematical logic, or what might be called the science of mathematical founda- tions. But I omit that; for ] assnme that most of us have more need for ordinary language than for technical mathe- matics. It takes more skill to say some given thing in words than it does to express it mathematically. a CHAPTER VI. Names for logic, and chief application ef valid logic to men. S45. a. We have seen a way of expressing a complete or unifying sentence or equation. And we have seen some important conclusions which were obvious from that complete sentence—finally seeing the simple rule by which consistency of expression can be achieved:- the three parts of the Trinity must not be confused. That rule was, for clearness and vividness, exemplified by showing the absurdities resulting from its non-observance by orthodox mathematics, which is presumably the most precisely rigorous sort of expression. b. Inthe remainder of this Part One we consider the same things from different aspects, and in addition notice more or less interesting details. I shall hegin this chapter by giving the most important general application in everyday life of our precise unification. After that we shall try to find a conventional name that fits the unification. To antici- pate the results of that search fora name:- We definitely find by observing the meanings of various conventional names, the important fact that our valid logic and concrete truth is the same as the logic and truth of the average man —that the race for centuries has somewhat unconsciously been using valid logic and obtaining truth, naming it com- monsense. ce. Then, I give in the next chapter (VII) a new sort of proof of our whole argument in a way which shows the indefinite flexibility and possibilities of language. Next I show (in VIII) amechanical model of language, as concrete proof of the argument, and for more definite guidance in the use of language. Then (in the last chapter in Part One, IX), UNIVERSE 34 as an actual example of the fact that merely our investigation of language will enable us to unify knowledge rigorously, I apply what we have learned to elementary physical science, and we see its formal completion. $46. a. Man is chiefly interested in man, because man is man and hence most directly and steadily perceptible and familiar to himself; it is merely a truism. Consequently, the most important application of the solution of the One and Many is its application directly to man. This whole book is with more or less directness engaged with that particular application. But now that we have the solution, we here at onee apply it to man with explicit directness, in broad out- lines. We see further details throughout the book. b. Itis held by the dualists that man is of two-fold nature:- soul and body. The soul isnow usually considered to be the same as mind, or spirit, or consciousness, or the ‘vital spark.’? There have been many ideas as to soul (see ‘“Ency. Brit.,’? Index, s. v. ““Soul’’). So many people have considered it some separate entity or thing which in some way dwelled in the body, that “‘sou!s’’ have rather gone ont of fashion because it was so glaringly self-contra- dictory to consider the soul absolutely separate and also not separate, but more or less attached to the body; also, be- cause no one ever succeeded in putting his finger on such a “‘soul,’’ although many attempts were made. ‘The modern fashionable name for soul is personality. Soul, or any of its several synonyms, is simply the unified or joined sum of parts of an individual, considered chiefly from a ‘‘mental’’ or ‘‘spiritual’’ or nervous-system aspect—as will be proved. ec. Some dualists further hold that there is a dualism— an unbridgable, unesecapable, essential difference in kind or quality—between the ““body’’ of man, and “‘matter.’’ I. e., they hold that ‘‘body”’ is “‘alive,’’ and “‘matter’’ “‘dead.”’ We take that up in detail in the chapter on biology (XVI, especially $144; and it may be remarked that the matter of the old Clerk Maxwellstyle of scientist was viciously ‘‘dead”’ verbally—but erroneously; see Index, ‘“Dynamic,’’ ‘‘Max- well’’). Here, we simply note that that dualism—‘‘vital- ism’’ is the name of that variety,—and all others, will disappear in the same way as that between mind and matter is shown to disappear in par. f and following. We may an- ticipate here, that all the universe is “‘alive’’ in any real or One sense (or “‘dead,’” if itis preferred to talk lugubriously). Whether or not a given thing is, in everyday and Many language, to be considered alive ornot, isa quantitative prob- lem, the solution of which depends upon what perceptible degree of organization or structure or personality—what in- tensity of internal and external reactions—we arbitrarily agree to require of the thing that is to be called alive. d. The orthodox way of “‘logically’’ bridging the dual- isms alive-dead, and mind-matter—the way of Descartes, Aquinas, the Catholic church, and most other pluralists—is to use ‘“God’’ as an entity, a concrete or Many link, or ter- tium quid to join the two. (In that sense, God validly should be a formal relationship word, God the Holy Ghost—in which case there is no dualism.) Other dualists do not like the name God and use some synonym. Some materi- alistic scientists substantially deny that there is any such thing as mind, or a real relationship or organization or per- sonality or soul. In effect, they deny that there is (say) friction in a machine. We consider their views in detail later (Index, ““Materialism’’); in general it has already been shown that the classical logie which those materialists fancy they are using asserts some sort of relationship, e. Obviously from the last paragraph, the dualists (ex- cluding that queer variety:- materialists) do get mind and matter absolutely together. So essentially, all that their 35 UNIVERSE talk amounts to, is that they assert that the two were abso- lutely apart until they (the dualists) themselves with super- Godlike power created a God to put them together. Hence, a commonsense question that obviously disposes of their talk is:- Why do the dualists keep on chattering about mind and matter being separate if they have been so good as to get them together for us? do they want us to keep on being grateful to them for having remoulded the universe nearer to their hearts’ desire, and keep on appreciating their skill and miraculous power in making a God? f. The obvious principle is that mind and matter are unified or related, and hence ultimately identical. The dualists by inventing their poor sort of God did not change the universe, and produce the relationship which they tacitly admit now exists. The shortest proof of the identity of mind and matter is that we attach some meaning—regardless of what it is—to the phrase ““mind and matter’’: and a meaning is continuity or unity. If we didn’t, obviously it would be nonsense to use the phrase. g. In Part Two, where we observe matter in detail, we see that it is identical in all respects with mind, life, per- sonality —except in quantitative respects, which are unessen- tial. The formal proof in the last paragraph is of course rigorous; any dualism may be destroyed in the same way. But it is destructive proof. For actual, intelligible proof of ‘no dualism’ we describe things as they are. 847. a. If we consider a man, superficially he seems to be a separated part of the universe; and it seems at first that we can not actually perceive that he is inseparably joined on to the remainder. __ But if we look closer (if need be, using microscopes, etc., as tools to intensify our percep- tions), we can see that the man is not sharply cut off or bounded from the rest of the universe. His breath extends indefinitely inward into his blood and indefinitely outward into the atmosphere. His skin does not bound him; for his sweat extends indefinitely in, and vaporizes indefinitely out into the atmospliere. There isobviously no definite place at which his food and drink become a part of ““him,’’ or ccase to be a part. Obviously, it is not possible to say where the man begins or ends. Like our circular logic, which starts from truisms and ends in them and stays always inside such a verbal One, the man ultimately, or in eract language, has no positive beginning or end, or sharp boundary. A man himself is precisely like our valid logic. b. We can at this point be somewhat more definite about his mind and body (see XVI and XVII for remainder). It is observable that if we remove part of his nervous system we remove part of his mind. So obviously, in that rough way it is shown that there is no essential difference between mind and body. Also, it is not possible to observe any exact or positive boundary between the nervous system and the organs in which it “‘terminates’’ (§152). Any tool which we take in our hand (say), isobviously a perceptible extension of our body or nervous system or mind; for nosharp bound- ary may be distinguished anywhere; and very evidently we can—with the ordinary tool—feel or observe perceptibly with the outer end (8165). ce. Except for rough statement that he isa This, the man is really continuous with the universe—inseparable from it. He is actually This...; any unit of the Many is actually This..., as we have seen in “‘theory’’ and are now broadly seeing ‘“‘coneretely.”’ If we try to assert that the man is at least bounded by the surface of the earth or by the atmospheric boundary, a closer look will convince us that the assertion will not hold. For obviously the air and the water on the surface of the earth (and some of his vaporized sweat, etc.) extend into the earth with all degrees of percept- One VI §47¢ ible connection. And the air does not stop at any outer boundary. There is an outer zone of attenuated air from which parts (molecules) bounce up, and mingle with similarly bouncing gas from the sun, and so on. We see that continu- ation of the atmosphere in zodiacal light ($121). And in turn, it is observable that parts of the solar system mingle with other such systems, then on to other galaxies, and so on indefinitely or in infinite regress (ED); d. Therefore, the so-called individual man is an arbr- trary part; for no exact boundary can be fixed for him in any way, short of the total universe. And even if we were to fix a formal boundary for him as a definite ‘‘individual,’’ with glaring obviousness that boundary would constantly change. Every time he breathed there would bea continuous cycle of change; his heart beat usually moves parts of him percept- ibly in and out; the ingestion of substances constantly pro- duces changes. Obviously, even such a formal boundary is not definitely or positively fixable. e. Therefore, from every point of view the man is sim- ply arbitrarily a unit of the Many. In termsof the Trinity, he is, considered roughly and inexactly,a God the Son. The only accurate boundary we can give him is to say that he is ultimately, without any real break in continuity, the whole universe, or God the Father. Explicitly, each man, when accurately described, absolutely includes in himself all other men and things as parts of him, and is God. That is the most intelligible description of God (particularly God the Father) that can be given. The description is thus far very thinly intellectual—i. e., mostly formal and abstract ;—this whole book adds details, and under ethics (XVIII) we get some small measure of its actual infinite emotional content. f. The conventional ““belief’’ of the dualists is that God is something outside the “‘universe,’’ separate from it, and absolutely apart. Obviously, as a truism, if God or anything else is outside the universe and apart from it, our very asser- tion of the existence of that extraneous thing implies an as- sertion:- ‘the universe avd it.’ And that assertion, by the ‘and’, explicitly asserts a connection so that ‘it’ is actually implicitly a part of the universe and included zm it (or else the phrase is utter nonsense and unintelligible). In short, it is absolutely self-contradictory to assert that we are even aware of the possibility of anything extraneous to the universe or separate from it; we can write such a form or assortment of words, but the form is self-contradictory and pure nonsense —or else it implies some new and novel meaning of the words used. I might add a volume of the same sort of ob- vious proof, But the foregoing part of this paragraph is rigorous, and is sufficient for the intelligent reader, in spite of the wide currency of the yarn that God is outside the universe. God is the universe. g. To take another point of view of the last paragraph :- There is no ‘‘something’’ exterior to the universe with or by which to describe the universe’s boundaries. JI. e., the uni- verse is not a This, which we can speak of positively and ex- plicitly (as we can of the color red) by comparing it with a That “‘outside’’ or even formally different or separate. The universe is the complete “‘finish’’ of all different That’s and This’s, and has nothing by which to fix its boundaries (except that they include the sum of everything inside): day language, the universe is not ‘‘bounded.’’ It is not quantitative. Consequently, when we achieve complete accur- acy by describing a man as ultimately the universe or God, there is no way of expressing any boundaries or size, in pos- itive words (see Index, ‘‘Difference surface’). We are really truthful, ‘essential,’ qualitative, and accurate then ; but we are indefinite, and not verbally positive. The universe or God or any ultimate thing is ineffable or mystical, or is in every- §47g VI One quantitatively absolutely indeterminate, or is really infinite. h. Thus far we have seen rigorously—in formal, thin intellectual expression at least——that a man is arbitrarily an individual or unit of the Many, and in ultimate reality is the universe or God the Father, or the One. It is now similarly obvious that ““man’’ as a class is a word which implies the relationship of al] individual Many men. In that sense, man is God the Holy Ghost, or a relationship word. That use of man is rather common; the more explicit names for the same relationship, which also include an implication of a Many meaning, are mankind, brotherhood of man, and society. ‘The science of sociology emphasizes that point of view of man as God the Holy Ghost. All governments and other human organizations obviously take the point of view that man, from one aspect, exhibits relationships—is God the Holy Ghost. So the solution of the vexed problem in sociology of What is sovereignty? is obviously :- sovereignty is the name of that relationship (is a relationship word); and various ‘‘sorts’’ of sovereignty are nothing more than such a rela- tionship of ““natural’’ continuity or ultimate identity, ob- served in various perceptible quantitative degrees of extension and intensity in various historical circumstances. When it is said ““God is love,’’ fundamentally it is meant that man as God the Holy Ghost is a linkage or unbreakable organization or organism called love. The same ‘‘connec- tion’’ in ‘‘science’’ is called “‘cause and effect’’; or cohe- sion; or, negatively, pressure (§86). In philosophy and theology the relationship aspect is called reason, and mind, and the ‘‘moral sense,’’ and “‘spirit,’’ and teleology. The chief dificulty in orthodox doctrines is that there is such an everwhelming profusion of names for that same thing. For centuries theologians, scientists, philosophers—prophets— have come forward with ‘‘systems’’ or “‘truths’’—special or particular ways of unifying knowledge,—each thinking that he had some bright new idea, to which he often gave a new nae and said it was the most “‘important’’ thing in the world. All of them were talking about the same simple thing :- God the Holy Ghost—or copulas in language; or the relationship of the One and the Many. And all of them ob- viously were fundamentally right, even if they were a bit narrow minded and over-proud of their new little names. i. When in everyday terms we speak of a manas having personality, we obviously mean that he is strongly consist- ent; i. e., all of him hangs together or works together so energetically that it all “adds together’’ instead of there being appreciable mutually conflicting and hence neutraliz- ing parts; and hence he is on the whole vividly perceptible. He then is not futilely vacillating, or noisily contradicting himself, or awkwardly ““falling all over himself.”’ Hence, even in conventional meaning personality substantially is perceptible relationship—a definite continuity inside a given man as a standard universe. Obviously, when we consider man as a complete universe, personality is still God the Holy Ghost. Or in that relationship sense, and also in the sense that a man is accurately and ultimately the One, God is a person. That is not using person in quite a conventional sense, which Jatter sense usually makes a person a standard One (vision being too short conventionally to see a whole One), and hence in practice makes God a sort of senile gray- bearded Oriental or Prussian kaiser seated on a sort of un- supported gold throne nowhere in particular. But obviously, our conclusion that God is a person uses person in its essen- tial conventional sense of continuous, or organized, or con- nected; we agree completely that a standard universe may have such a personality, and note that in it the personality, to our rather restricted vision, may be perceptibly much more vivid than is the personality of the whole universe (al- UNIVERSE 36 most stupendously so in the case of Christ, e. g.): but it is quite evident that the facts show that the whole universe is also a person. ] may make the technical philosophi- cal remark, that in that sense the present sort of deism tru- istically is practically opposite to the customary historical pantheism. That pantheism usually was substantially nothing but what we now cal] materialism (§49h), with a silly, cloying sugar coating. j. It is to be kept in mind that consistently with pres- ent conventional language, God is a person. I. e., the uni- verse is organized, connected, organic— ‘something more’’ than a mere “‘heap’’ of parts or Many. The universe is a real machine—one held together by friction (or love, if we prefer the ethical term; or cohesion or force, to use scientific terms), and is not a heap of disparate parts. The machine works. It is a person (88144, 153). An ordinary locomotive has a personality quite perceptible to me: in principle it ought to have slight personality, as we shall see by the whole of Part Two. Many people have asserted that they can per- ceive the personality of a locomotive or similar machine—as witness the affectionate name ‘‘tin Lizzie’’ for a Ford car. §48. a. Wehave seen that nearly any name can be used for each of the three sorts of words (§§28h, 29, 30, 43-4). We have seen it vividly in the case of man ($47). And we saw by the absurd matheinatical conclusions that the confu- sion of the three produced nonsense ($44). ft is therefore evident that to be consistent or rational——to see things as they are,—we distinguish in which of the three meanings we are using some given word, so that mere names shall not confuse and blind us while we are ostensibly using them to avoid that:- to aid our memories. Any normal child can readily judge which of the three meanings of a given name is intended, or else see that in a certain case he can not and hence that the word or sentence is unintelligible to him. There is no intrinsic difficulty about being logical, and see- ing the truth: the difficulty is that we are in the habit of confusing the words. b. It is further evident that by considering any name ultimately and accurately as designating God the Father (as may be validly done), we therein have a formal religion that is really correct, as it means or indicates the whole related universe. Obviously, as a further truism of that, any person who considers and observes that the results of his activities are an inseparable part of the whole universe, and are needed as that part to round out the whole, they being absolutely indispensible because inseparable—any person who can thus regard his activities or his life has a real, everyday, working religion even if he is no more than an unskilled laborer (for further details and proof, see §§166-7). Theology does not necessarily express a valid religion. If you will refer to an authoritative orthodox theologian’s statement of what theo- logians think is the Trinity (‘“Ency. Brit.,’’ vi, 284-5, in Art. “Christianity’’), you can readily see, in the light of what we have now observed about the Trinity, that no so- called Christian theologian, aceording to that statement, has yet consistently expressed any valid religion. Ifit is not obvious from that short citation, then the remaining pages of the article cited make it more obvious. “© Many theologians bThat article (p. 289) explicitly states in effect that the theolo- giams are evasive—i. e., that they will not agree to say that 4=A and stick to it, nor yet will they refuse to do so (ef. §22). E. g., the writer states that officially both the Protestant and the Catholic churches assert certain doctrines which many scholars in the church find ‘‘no difficulty’’ in rejecting and “remaining Christian.’’ He says that they produce a large literature ‘‘reconciling science and theology by softening and compromising and adapting’’; that men are not ‘‘prepared to carry principles to their logical conclusions. By 37 UNIVERSE of course have a valid religion, and have had. I have merely pointed out that by their own statement their expression of such religion is grossly inconsistent. Yet that theological dogma, worthless when strictly interpreted, implicitly points a fortunate power of mind they are able to believe as truths mutually inconsistent propositions.’’ The writer goes on further, actually ap- proving that extraordinary refusal of theologians to abide by any verbal agreement they may make. Obvionsly, he asserts in effect that a theologian will agree that .1—A, and will then at any time he likes, and without notice, assert that A is not=A. That writer is an authoritative Protestant (whose name in simple kindness ] omit), and perhaps the Catholics may hold that he bas no right to speak for them. So we shall let the Catholics exhibit fundamental evasiveness for themselves:- If you will refer to the Art. ‘‘Philoso- phy,’’ inthe authoritative ‘‘Catholic Encyclopedia’’ (xii, 37-8), passed by their censor, you will find that its official Catholic writer (in an extremely confusing manner which may have confused even himself —and which on the other hand may have been sophisticated guile to prevent anybody’s pinning him down, which is the acmeof evasive- ness) dodges definite statement of what the Catholics fundamentally believe as expressed in philosophical terms, and finally makes this ‘‘shifty’’ statement as to official authoritative imposition:- ‘The Church has never imposed any philosophical system, though she has anathematized many doctrines.’’ [That of course is equivalent to asserting that the church has negatively imposed philosophical sys- tems-—but let that pass.] Bnt another writer in the same official work (“‘Cath. Ency.,’’ v, 170) substantially flatly contradicts that first writer by stating:- ‘‘From the thirteenth century, through the influence of Albertus Magnus and still more of St. Thomas Aquinas, the philosophy of Aristotle, though subjected to some important modifications, became the accredited philosopby of the Church’’; and, ‘‘The distinction between the bumaao soul and the body it ani- mates was made clearer and their separability emphasized; but the ultra-dualism of Plato was avoided.’’ An authoritative Catholic theologian, Ryan, in a more or less casual book not officially recog- nized by the Church so far as I can discover, asserts as asort of mat- ter of course and as actual practice, that the Catholics are dualists (‘‘Socialism: Promise or Menace,’’ 261-2); and he goes on to make the nonsensical dualistic statement (which in actual practice Catho- lics claim to hold), that ‘‘science and religion as such *** deal with entirely different spheres of reality,’’—which remark of course im- plies as a verbal truism no need of consistency between science and religion. Also, J. J. Walsh, in ‘‘The Popes and Science,”’ officially censored by Catholic authorities, states (p. 327):- ‘‘At the end of the nineteenth century Leo XII]. crowned the tributes which many popes had conferred on Thomas [Aquinas] by selecting him as the teacher to whom Catholic schools should ever turn by formulating the authoritative Papal opioion—the nearer to Thomas the nearer to Catholic truth.’’ And see also Walsh’s ‘‘The Thirteenth, Greatest of Centuries,’’ pp. 81, 276-81. lt seems to me that those quo- tations prove both sorts of theologians to be officially evasive, irre- sponsible and unreliable in their assertions—or else to have minds of such weakness of perception and hence unreliability as perhaps oc- casionally to border on pathological insanity. The Germans repudi- ated a ‘‘scrap of paper,’’ and the rest of the world would not tolerate it—it is becoming bad taste, and sometimes dangerously unhealthy, for even statesmen and diplomats—a ‘‘government’’—to lie in these days, although Henry Adams says in effect that they feel quite free to lie. We here see the theologians acting even more reprehensibly than that defunct German government—for that government was at least honest in giving notice that it did not propose to keep its word unless convenient, and those theologians in those quotations evade even that much of explicit statement of how far we canrely on them. As a matter of fact, if the Catholic theologians are ever forced to notice these remarks, quite probably they can ‘‘prove’’ by technical canonical law that I prove nothing officially by such quotations—a characteristic Catholic procedure (e. g., see Walsh’s ‘“The Popes and Science’’) which if followed proves my point. There is actually a history extending over centuries, of theological lies and evasions: see ‘Pious Frauds’’ in Lecky’s history of the ‘‘Rise of Rationalism in Europe.’’ And the Protestant theologian quoted gocs so far as to assert that none of mankind will live up to their principles: the truth is that most theologians even have excellent principles and live up to them quite honestly as a usual thing. So far as I can find, all other classes of men try to be verbally honest. Even the first Catholic writer quoted above makes a sort of verbal claim to the intended honesty of Catholics in dealing with science. But in view of those quotations, ] have no choice but to state that in no case in this book do I place any particular reliance upon what a theologian professionally or officially says. One VI §48d out the complete truth. So obviously, theology need not be taken more seriously than any otherscience. And orthodox theology is explicitly wrong when it pretends to any *‘auth- ority’’ (such pretension being substantially the invalid claim that expression is rea] proof; see §35). Also, theology is, in making such a claim, an aristocracy, autocracy, or kaiser- ism. The Catholic church explicitly pretends to such auth- ority (ibid., Art. ““Christianity,’’? 289); hence, the Catholic church is absolutely wrong by its explicit words in that re- spect (which is an important practical one), and is in prin- ciple intolerable (§169). ec. In the old days the Trinity was a governmental problem. It is now the verbal custom to consider that in some countries there is no religion in government. Obvious- lv, in a complete sense, we can not possibly keep religion out of government: man himself is clearly the Trinity, and man is society. But what is meantis that we keep theology out of government (allowing free speech in the matter—as theology, with its claim to ““authority,’’ will not willingly do)—which is quite right and practically necessary until such time as theology becomes a valid science (when it itself will accord such free speech; §169f). As a matter of clearly obvious historical fact, the reason this country removed the- ology from politics is that theology is essentially aristocratic or autocratic in its substantial claims and inits practical ten- dencies—a so-called ““spiritual’’ dualistic doctrine of kaiser- ism that can not possibly be reconciled with democracy in principle, it being the flat contradiction of democracy—as we shall see proved in detai) in XVIJ-XIX. d. The historical fact, with an obviousness that is pain- fully glaring to me, is that most churches, and especially the Catholic church, have opposed any verifiable, objective proof that certain of their dogmas failed to agree with things as they are. Theologians have tried to force men to accept their “‘authority’’ even to the irrelevant point of torturing them bodily. For historical proof see the Catholic Walsh’s officially censored ‘Popes and Science,’’ where the facts glare through his formal denials and ““explanations’’; or, for explicitly stated proof see White’s ‘‘Warfare of Science with Theology’’ (note that White advisedly says theology), or Buckle’s history. The reason for that insistence of theologians upon their ‘‘authority’’ is of course the same as the reason for the maintenance of any kaiserism:- it was a more or less selfish, personal effort to get and keep them- selves in a position of power and privilege and ‘‘emolu- ments’’ (i. e., graft)—and of course their doing so did con- fer some very temporary benefits on the laymen (e. g., it saved them the pain and effort of doing a lite thinking for themselves, giving them the lazy comfort of saying that those subjects are of course outside our line and we will leave them to the specialists—just as some presumably intelligent people have talked to me about this book); and those temporary comforts were paid for later by mental and moral deteriora- tion, as is all kinds of paternalism or parasitism (cf. Part Three). It is much easier to claim to be right (especially after one’s brain is so debauched—i. e., partly killed—by the evasiveness described in the footnote, that it no longer rebels against such dishonesty), than it is to dig into things by hard effort and find out what zs right. Consequently, so long as there are men so weak and stupid as to tolerate being duped (and even actually to invite it, as has come to my notice repeatedly in working up this book), there are going to be dogmatic theologians, as well as other sorts of dogmat- ists, who are mentally sufficiently depraved to dupe them. The dogmatist pays for the ‘“privileges’’ and graft he gets by suffering that brain destruction——a very expensive payment, although he in turn is too stupid to know what is §48d VI One hurting him, and fills the air with complaints about the ““unbelief’’ of the people. This book will show unescapably that we pay for everything we get, and get everything we pay for. In the aristocratic kaiser-theologian-dupe game the payment is merely a trifle slow——and that fools boobs. e. The extent and intensity with which we perceive the ultimate unity or organic personality of the universe determ- ines its mental effect upon us (including emotional effect), and hence its worth ($168). The remainder of this book is a series of evidences that there is such ultimate unity or con- nection or love or cohesion. Jn that sense the book expands and intensifies the reader’s religion or enjoyment of life if he sees and verifies that evidence for himself. f. The argument of the book is now complete. It was complete when we had examined the sentence 2-+3=—=5 in 812; but now all implications of that form have been stated and shown in a broad way. Hereafter I simply repeat the argument in terms of different sorts of details, as a means of making it applicable and more thoroughly intelligible. Hav- ing now achieved that genera] completeness, it may at this point be of interest to see what the conventional] name of the argument is:- 849. a. There may be said to be three general histori- cal ways of viewing—interpreting—the Trinity (‘‘Ency. Brit.,’? Art. ““Christianity’’). “* | Each of those historical interpretations consists of emphasizing one sort of our three sorts of words, at the expense of the two remaining kinds. Sometimes the emphasis is so violent that the other two members of the Trinity are claimed to be non-existent. Thus, the atheist or the materialistic scientist emphasizes the Many so much that there is to him nothing else—no unity, no God, but only “‘a fortuitous concourse of atoms’’ (an obviously self-contradictory phrase that thus implicitly re-establishes the Trinity). Or, the technical mystic will so violently emphasize the One (or may be it is relationship or God the Holy Ghost: no one ever knows just what the technical mystic is saying), that he substantially denies the existence of the Many. And there are other varieties of doctrines that wholly deny one or more parts of the Trinity. Sometimes people become exasperated with the theological dogmas, as Wells apparently did, and deny the Trinity in toto—and then more or less unconsciously construct another, with new names. But as we have seen the formal need in language of each of the three sorts of words, it is obvious that the truth is not any of those doctrines which deny one or more parts, either very largely in a quantitative way, or wholly—in really a qualitatively impossible way. So technically, we are neither Christian Scientists nor theoso- phists (two species of mystics), nor atheists, nor materialistic scientists (who are almost German ‘‘monists’’)—not yet ag- nostics, who say they know little or nothing of the matter. b. Nor are we dualists, who undertake to make some real split in the Trinity, so that any two parts are “‘perfectly equal’’ to each other. The parts are not real or essential or distinct, but merely arbitrary or verbal, and actually merge into each other even in the nsing of such logical formal distinctions. ec. It is not profitable to examine at length the names of the doctrines that in one way or another gave greater ‘The writer mentions four more technical ways as being ‘“‘Christian,’’ but I shall ignore such technical dogma as being too trivial for intelligent readers. EE. g., the Catholic Trinity is briefly this:- ‘‘In this one God there are three distinct Persons,—the Father, the Son [i. e., Christ], and the Holy Ghost, who are per- fectly equal to each other’’ (Cardinal Gibbons, ‘‘The Faith of Our Fathers,’’ Chap. I1)—and | take it that the reader of this book is too intelligent to desire a discussion of such balderdash, that is so glar- ingly self-contradictory and meaningless if explicitly considered. UNIVERSE 38 emphasis to one or two parts of the Trinity than to the re- mainder. There are already bundreds of tiresome books on the subject. We shall look at a few important doctrines. d. The Buddhists seem to me to make relationship words—explicitly time and its numerous substantial synonyms —the most emphatic of the Trinity. I. e., they make re- lationships or God the Holy Ghost “‘real.’’ (For rhetorical purposes I tacitly take it for granted that I am _ historically correct in my interpretations. I am not able to make out with much definiteness what the Buddha did mean, and I doubt whether he knew very clearly himself—there are places in this book [they are labeled] where I do not know clearly what I mean; e. g., the full extension of the theory of harmonic periodicity: and I know considerably more about things than the Buddha did. All my historical state- ments are similarly liable to error. Such statements are quantitative, and I can do no more than give reasonable guesses, some of which are most likely to be very inaccu- rate.) To make relationships real or truth, is, truist- ically, valid, provided that there is at least formal] recognition of the logical existence of the other two forms. I. e., we validly can emphasize relationships very much—say they are ‘‘real’’—and at the same time say that the other two forms logically exist, but will verbally be called not ‘‘real,’’ but “‘arbitrary”’ (real and arbitrary in that usage merely take on quantitative meaning). The Buddhistic way of making time real (doing so in practical effect by emphasizing the long temporal duration of training or education, or what they call the “‘way,’’ to ultimate perfection—to grasp of the One) obviously makes the One a form—it makes the One what we may cal] a ‘negative reality,’ or Nirvana. Buddhisin is hence obviously quite right; it does not deny the formal or logical need of those three forms, and their ultimate unity. But we Occidentals do not talk that reversed language (it is in practice an Oriental, more ‘selfish’ [ef. §151), introspect- ive language; whereas we prefer an objective or ° ‘scientifie’’ language). So Buddhism is inconvenient for us—and also possesses inherent tendencies towards selfishness which are inadvisable (e. g., the conduct of the Buddha himself in coolly deserting his family would get him a jail sentence in some of our states), and are technically and historically primitive. In speaking of Buddhism I refer to the original Buddhism, which was essentially sound, and an ex- traordinary advance. The Buddhistic theologians seem to have perverted Buddha’s teachings as ours have Christ’s. e. Those who emphasize the Meaning or One or God the Father member of the Trinity are now perhaps most oft- en called monists. The chief objection to that name as a proper name for our valid logic is that its German users, in their exaggeration of detail (of the Many, of ‘‘material’’), have rather spoiled it. They usually call their doctrine scientific monism,”’ and fail to recognize that the phrase implies a dualism of “‘matter’’ and ‘‘spirit’’ that instantly stultifies it. Some theologians in a somewhat similar way try to appropriate the name monism as being more up-to-date than the ancient equivalent theological term monotheism, — and then make a dualism out of their *“monism.”’ Or, the Germans are sometimes equally shallow in asserting what they call a monism, that in effect denies relationships (so that they can formally use the elassieal logic with it); such monism again implies dualism. Before the war I used to devote considerable space to showing that Ostwald and Nietzsche, who seemed to be the Germans’ actually ae- cepted leading “‘thinkers,’’? were exceedingly unsound fundamentally. (I am aware that Nietzsche attacked Prus- sians—in a way which was really complimentary in their view—and that Germans verbally often repudiated him. I 39 UNIVERSE think however that in view of the psychological principle shown in §155, it is reasonably correct to say that Nietzsche expressed German general views:- they being chaotic and selfish. I also recognize that Nietzsche was tremendously in earnest, and was actually likeable in many ways on that account; and that he was a victim of his time, and hence deserving of much approving pity by really intelligent per- sons. As we saw in the case of the Kaiser (§25c), if we take an ultimate One view of Nietzsche, he was completely con- sistent and beautiful. I am however restricting my remarks about Nietzsche to what he actually wrote; and that was a violently emphatic dualism and hence perceptibly insanely incoherent. ) But now that the war has occurred, I judge that any extended proof of German unsoundness in principles, due to too much emphasis on detail or the Many, is no long- er needed—just those very general remarks about German monism being all that is needed to call attention to the facts. ‘Those remarks show, what will probably be accepted as the historical fact, that the Germans did not asa rule grasp any real meaning of the One, or couldn’t generalize well (and hence talked loudly and sentimentally of being monists because essentially they were so far from being such; for the psychology of that see §155); although they were very industrious and prolific with details of all kinds. That detail work they did well, and it is of great value. From the point of view of theirown best interest, they did that detail work too well, becoming unbalanced in it (cf. §149). f. Consequently, although monism is thus a somewhat spoiled word, and gives conventional misleading indications, it may, if stripped of those conventional accretions, serve as a poor name for what we have observed to be the truth— subject to another defect to be mentioned in par. i. For it is an observable fact that Occidentals have acquired the ten- dency to consider the One, or a unified God, to be the “‘re- ality’’ or ‘‘truth’’ whenever there arises any definite question as to what is ‘‘real.’” That seems to be the result of several centuries of a religion that in usual practice tended to be rather monotheistic (or without a ‘‘center,’’ or formally not anthropocentric) if it were explicitly pinned down to definite statement (and Occidentals formulated such a religion be- cause they appreciably had greater mental or general vigor than the Orientals, and that in turn had many causes, climate being the verbally final one—Index, ‘‘Climate’’). E. g., the ignorant Catholic layman substantially has five coordinate Gods (Christ, God the Father, Holy Ghost, Vir- gin Mary, and a null-God, the Devil), and the Protestant Trinitarian usually substantially has four Gods. (As people lose in mental vigor the number of their Gods increases, that being merely truistic with inability to see the relationships that give unity; hence it is another truism that the numerous Catholic Gods appeal to the ignorant who can’t or won’t think for themselves.) But if either layman is pinned down to an explicit statement he will verbally assert one God, in spite of the glaring fact that the assertion contradicts his ritualistic practices. But in spite of those practical vagaries —they are emotional or ritualistic (§167d) survivals of that ancient day when men were too weak mentally to see and express considerable unifications,—whenever a question of formal speech or explicit logic comes up, the Occidental] has become accustomed to asserting a unified universe or God, and as a result our whole language is formally permeated (cf. par. j for actual practice) by the implication that the One is *‘real’’ or ‘‘true,’’ or that monism orits theological synonym monotheism is the truth. And to repeat, that mono- theistic ‘‘religion’’ did not absolutely ““cause’’ Occidentals to progress ahead of Orientals; the Occidental progressed because he was able (for reasons we implicitly see in numer- One VI §49h ous places below) to get a wider grasp of the connections of the Many. He stated that grasp as monotheism, and that religions expression in turn reacted as a‘ ‘cause’’ that widened the grasp, and so on in infinite regress. g. There remain those people who emphasize the Many part of the Trinity—substantially saying that the Many is most important, or is ‘‘real.”’?. The more usual name for them is pluralists, meaning finite pluralists. A name nearly as common is realists. Probably most people who are said to have “‘scientific’’ tendencies are what are popularly called commonsense realists; i. e., without much investigation they take as being “‘real’’ what the theologians call the things of this world. We have seen that the Many zs form- ally or logically true; hence, those names for truth may serve as poor ones except that we have to be explicitly infinite pluralists (a verbal self-contradiction of course— needed on account of the fact that the Occidental names things as stated in the last paragraph; see also §24d). How- ever, we see better names in par. i. There is one special objection to calling the Many real, and the One ar- bitrary. We are in the habit of calling the One real, and to call the Many always real turns our customary language topsy-turvy (and fundamentally is perhaps the most import- ant, theoretically superficial but intensely practical, cause of the warfare between science and theology—which is hence seen to be mostly verbal and unessential; and science was under an obligation to show that an advantage accrued in the long run from such verbal innovation, and science neither recognized nor met the obligation, although there zs an ad- vantage, as indicated in footnote 100c). -That turning of language topsy-turvy can be validly done (§51, ete.); but it is rather confusing. We shall see ($891, 84, 93, etc.) how Reynolds in his scientific theory correctly called the Many real; he got ““matter’’ as being holes in the ether, the holes traveling when ‘‘matter moved,’’ and other weird verbal results, in an elaborately upside-down language. The Many, or an infinite pluralism, zs real or true; but if we steadily verbally consider it so, we have to construct an upside-down language in which to state it. h. There is one variety of person (other than the ag- nostic), unwatrrantedly usually called a scientist, who is a pseudo-species of realist or pluralist that logically departs wholly from the truth. He is the materialist. He starts with what he considers an exact, sharp This, and he keeps on saying desperately This, Thisg Thiss Thiss Thiss but holds in effect that no One is achievable. Usually he does not explicitly assert that no One is ever synthesized; in practice he tends to be vociferous that there is no ‘“PROOF’’ that we can ever sum up his “‘scientifie’’ string of This: 23 45 6 ete. into any meaning. He excitedly overlooks the fact (and it is an example of the principle that man can not make a real error) that his very vociferousness is a violent dogmatic assertion that This: 2 3 ete. = Nudl- Meaning, which logically is precisely what he has been deny- ing. However, in practice we shall take the materi- alist at his word, and say that in brief, instead of making an intelligent equation he makes a sort of formally disconnected single member of it, This: 2 3 ete. , and denies that there ts any actual equation even while he is striving desperately to run down all the This’s:- Thiss 1 3 ete. —and pile them up as mountains of statistics—an attempt to put salt on the tail of the universe, so to speak. Obviously, his acts and his implicit logic contradict the folly of his outward protes- tations—although he vociferates so much that it sounds noisy just to talk about him. He views his mountains of statis- tics, which he erroneously calls science, in despair, and em- phatically denies that any complete grasp of knowledge, §49h VI One such as we are seeing in this book is in actual fact fairly easy, is possible. He says this book is ‘‘impossible.’? In charac- ter, he is a pessimistic, talkative weakling. i. The defect of the three ways of calling one or another member of the Trinity the important one—'‘reality’’ or the *“truth’’—is that those who undertake to do it are usually opposed by other schools with doctrines giving a different emphasis. Then the opponents get excited, increase their emphasis, and tend to finish with each school substantially asserting that its emphatic part is its only part, and that the opposing schools are wholly wrong. Such fanatics are very entertaining, even if distressing. History, including yes- terday’s newspaper, is full of their vagaries. When not ameliorated in some way, thcir excess tends to cumulate until it reaches the borderland of insanity as some form of megalomania, paranoia, or Nietzscheism. E. g., materialism is obviously the result of becoming so emphatic about the reali- ty or ‘practical importance’’ of the Many that the other two parts are either wholly or practically denied. j. The essential characteristic of those three ways of considering some one of the three parts of the Trinity the important one, and naming it “‘real,’’ is that such emphasis is considered a fixed emphasis (i. e., it nominally does not change, and fall on some other part); so we may call such forms static logic. We can note that the average man (who is paying slight attention to ‘‘logic’’—and that includes even professional theologians and mathematicians for the most part of their lives, and perhaps for the greater part of their professional writings) does not use any such static logic. The average man, whenever he uses any one of those three sorts of words, regards that word at the time it is used as pointing to or meaning the truth or reality. It is a dynamic logic:- the emphasis (“‘reality’’) is laid on that particular sort of word which is at the moment being used, and then changes or moves to the other kinds as they are used. And obvious- ly, the emphasis is thus in principle distributed in evractly proper proportions. Consequently, that sort of logic is the strictly valid sort (and the same sort of principle of validity is extended to the end in footnote 100c). Hence, our gen- eral equation is valid in that sense; for we have not consid- ered that one member or one symbol of it is any more ‘‘real’’ or important than another. And whatever word wil] name that sort of logic is an appropriate name. Those given above are not quite appropriate, as we may now see; they are usually somewhat quantitatively inaccurate for us. k. But the reader can now see definitely (cf. §§25, 13) that our observation of things as they are, especially of lang- nage as it is, has showed us that all of the historical doc- trines of the truth which have had any special vitality are qualitatively substantially right. All the great religions have been substantially right when considered apart from the theological perversions. All those valid doctrines were obviously conscious ~or ‘‘intellectual’’ attempts to state a unity already dimly perceived by people (§170}), and the inevitable result was an over-emphasis somewhere in them ($155). Poor emphasis does not make a statement “‘wrong’’ qualitatively; but it does make it quite liable to be misin- terpreted (even by the author of it—which is why we may often properly assert that we do not think that some writer knew what he said or meant), as it is more or less quantita- tively inaccurate. (And then science came along and at- tempted, usefully and properly, to correct such doctrines quantitatively by measuring. Some scientists in turn so vio- lently emphasized their correction as to become materialists —thus making a religion, but one of the null sort.) So it is glaringly obvious that the simple solution of the riddle of the universe is that the man in the street uses valid UNIVERSE 40 logic, and there never was any riddle about it. There is nothing strange abont the fact that the average man has always been qualitatively right (even if somewhat inarticu- tately so): as arapid proof that he has been, we may note the truism that if that average man had not been right the race would have died out long ago. And cows and birds use valid logic so far as they need it for their environ- ment—which is far enough to use One ejaculations. The overtalkative people— philosophers, scientists, priests, poets, and other varieties of persons who, being more or less biologi- cal sports and unbalanced ($159), write books—became verb- ally self-conscions and hence rattled, and manufactured *“riddles’’ and ““mysteries’’—even for themselves—where there were none. But somebody had to do it thus more or less wrong, by that ultimate method of trial and error, in order to develop the highly useful and sure language tool we now have. ]. Consequently, as the valid Jogic is such a ‘“common- place’’ affair, there are a number of common and familiar names which conventionally apply to it. **Valid’’ is one; *“dynamic’’ another. We have seen that ultimately all things join together as identical; and we have seen that the em- phasis on the three parts of the Trinity is identical in valid logic; hence, we may call it the logie of identity. (Classic logic is obviously logic of non-identity, as each premise is nominally distinct and different.) And since our valid logic is used by the average man it may conventionally be called commonsense logic, or simply commonsense—or common logic, or everyday logic, or intelligible logic. m. And the reader, finally, may like to know when and where this logic made its appearance in literature. Of course, as a truism, it has zmplicitly been used in all intelli- gible writings that came to correct conclusions which were stated with fairly balanced emphasis. J have not invented it. Jt is simply the ‘“commonsense’’ that people so often mention. |] am merely pointing it out and describing it. The prehistoric men who invented language invented it, ap- parently half-consciously and without formulating specifica- tions. The whole universe acted on them to cause them to invent it—in ways we implicitly see in Part Three. n. The valid logic has explicitly been used by a number of men in forms that were pretty definite. Christ was very obviously somewhat consciously using valid logic (§162e). So far as I can judge, his reported utterances in the Bible have been somewhat falsified (perhaps both unintentionally and intentionally); but they still show that Christ recog- nized valid logic and was deliberately using it. That was a stupendous feat in his day, and indicated his remarkable balance or great character (XVIII, §167b). Any fairly in- telligent and honest person ought to be able to do it now. o. For his age, Christ was reasonably definite in his use and indication of the valid logic. So far as I am aware, the next man to become more definite was Buckle, in his essay, Mill on Liberty.’”’ Buckle attributed the ideas to Mill, but in my opinion Mill is largely innocent of them. The next person I know of is Dewey; his “*Psychology,”’ writ- ten over thirty years ago, was more definite than Buckle, and his later works are steadily more so. Dewey has often been accused”’ by classic logicians of using circular logic, which was precisely what he was doing, and doing validly, and with rather good technique. Dewey, as far as I can Judge, was the founder of the present and valid, school of psychology, named behavoristic psychology. That name ob- viously means dynamic—and such psychology is of course in general agreement with valid dynamic logic. I use that psychology in this book (XVII), rewriting it in simpler form and eliminating its overstock of technical names. And it 41 UNIVERSE is shown repeatedly below, that all other valid knowledge, like valid psychology, is “‘dynamic.’”’ p. James gave the name pragmatism to substantially the same logic—but bestowed the name before he worked out the technical details very well. There are technical defects in the expression of pragmatism—which do not, how- ever, warrant explicit consideration in this condensed book. The leading American philosophers, headed by Dewey, have corrected the substantial ones; and some of those philosoph- ers have repudiated the name pragmatist along with the re- pudiation of James’s errors, and call themselves neo-realists. (So far as I can find, living philosophers outside America are searcely out of the amateur class. ) And David Starr Jordan independently, and before James and the neo- realists did so, worked out the valid logic in ““The Stability of Truth.’’ = Alfred Sidgwick has, with somewhat less defi- niteness, the same valid logic in his book, ““The Use of Words in Reasoning.’’ Stallo rather definitely implied it in his ‘“Theories and Concepts of Modern Physics,’’ which was explicitly perhaps too destructive. And Karl Pearson, in ‘“Grammar of Science,’’ nearly thirty years ago explicitly and emphatically made for science the distinction between Many words and One words under the respective names per- ceptions and conceptions, and went so far as to deduce from that distinction the principle that mass varies with velocity: that ““deduction,’’ as Pearson showed, was simply a correct interpretation of Newton’s laws (§88). | Pearson’s book is now scientifically accepted almost as commonplace; _ but it was novel when published, and I think was, in spite of its grave defect, one of the five or six first-class books on physi- cal science of the last century. It contains a bad defect which has marred Pearson’s later work:- it omits explicit naming and consideration of relationship words, and that perhaps technically comes close to making Pearsona materi- alist. What seems to have been the actnal difficulty is that Pearson tends to be a mathematician; and as mathematic- ians write relationship words as symbols +. =, &, different from ordinary words, therefore he more or less unconsciously took it for granted that no ordinary words were needed for or about relationships: so he omitted them. As a truistic con- sequence, his book was not intelligible to non-mathematicians (it is readily intelligible when the omission is supplied); also, the person trained in orthodox mathematics could more or less understand the book, but as he himself did not ex- plicitly know the language trick with reference to the rela- tionship symbols, he could not clearly express what he had understood. This paragraph of course simply states my judgments. There is no space to show the historical evidence for such quantitative matters, and my guesses will probably be disagreed with by some. And nearly surely there are other historical instances of fairly definite use of valid logic which have not come to my attention. There are not likely to be any very substantial uses of it which I have overlooked; for such use would have been by a person of such unusually strong cbaracter that he would not be the sort that is overlooked. For further remarks on the charac- ter of men who could use the valid logic, see §167b. q. Probably it is safer never to use for very long any particular name for the valid way of expressing the truth. The way itself hasan indefinite number of possible variations (S63, etc.). If we adopt a fairly fixed name for valid logic, some soft minded person might take it to refer to a fixed system—and thus be a word idolater. But there is the graver danger that the intellectual exploiters will prompt- ly grab any definite name for it, and capitalize it for their benefit. The exploiting capitalization of the word ** Christi- anity’’ is so pernicious and generally prevalent that many One VI §&49t people are becoming doubtful whether they wish to be named Christians. Democrat will probably be the next word exploited on a large scale; the demagogs have already been watering the stock of that word generously, and as this book is likely to make it definitely no longer respectable to be an aristocrat, probably all the intellectual bunco men and their soft minded followers will scramble even more to steal the now better trademark democrat. r. The common, untechnical, everyday name of the truth set forth by valid logic—other than democracy, which applies particularly to people—is idealism. Hopkins, in his Dartmouth inaugural address, names the common views of that truth (he expressing them implicitly in valid logic) :- “constructive idealism.’’? That name gives as much descript- ive information as to what is truth as any I can think of. It is somewhat obviously a verbally self-contradictory name, meaning an idealism or unified One or religion, definitely expressed mechanically (so that it will be applied). s. In the process of giving a large choice of names fairly suitable for the valid logic, so that the very number discour- ages exploitation of the name, I have tried to make clear the complete meaning of the valid logic, and to attach it so strongly to all the historical knowledge and well established emotions possessed by the reader that that essential part will be easily remembered. I of course would not have used the space discussing the choice of merely a name: one line would have sufficed fora name and nothing else. There has further appeared implicitly the answer to ‘“What’s in a name?”’ The answer is:- history—meaning mental connections or associations, or unification, and emotions, so that appropriate action readily results where there is much history—or ‘‘advertising’’—and hence habit attached. So it obviously is an advantage to have a familiar, common name, even if the exploiters do capitalize it, stealing its trademark value. We have to balance—compromise—be- tween having a name that automatically arouses emotion, and having one that is not so very automatic as to make it worth the exploiters’ efforts to steal. But that answer to ‘“What’s in a name?’’ includes what the name points to; the mere name is a little ink, or sound. t. We have now seen in a little intelligible detail that everyone with ‘‘commonsense’’ has previously understood the essentials of this book. For I am simply writing ont the explicit details of what for centuries has been recognized as such commonsense. We have seen that the general argn- ment of the book has been rather definitely stated numbers of times in the past. Hence, because such knowledge is so old, itis rather obvious in theory, even without observing the actual facts, that a normal five or six year old child can un- derstand the book—and even more so that an intelligent adult can: that the adult is quite competent to grasp all essen- tials of the book. But there is another side to all that, which other aspect shows some important conclusions :- The reader may occasionally find himself struggling to grasp something which is written in the book; and so wonld nat- urally feel resentful if it were held that a six-year-old could understand what he himself finds so diffienlt. But those difficult details are the Many, and of course probably would not be grasped by the child—and are not essential. The es- sential parts are the One conclusions—the seeing that ulti- mately things are related, and work together. Iam forced to state those Many details from my point of view; and all readers ocenpy other points of view, so that those details are more or less unfamiliar to them, and hence “‘hard.’’ Of course the reader finds it hard at times to ““grasp’’ things from my point of view. Also, as those details are in infinite regress, very shortly I find it extremely difficult for me §49t VI One myself to grasp the series far out. The better the reader is as an observer and thinker (a “‘thinker’’ is an observer of the relationships of his ‘‘observations’’), the more emphatically will he be conscious that he is not grasping all the Many de- tails as I see them—is not getting the detailed significance of what I say. But, to repeat, those details are not essential; they are the Many and are ultimately arbitrary. The reader who is a good observer will substitute his own details for mine. If the circumstances were reversed, and the six-year-old were the writer and I the reader, the same principle would hold:- I would be forced to see (if 1 were a reasonably good observer) that the child expressed details that ran on to infinity, and that I couldn’t “‘grasp’’ them or understand them as well as he did. Considered from that aspect (of details) the child would be ““mystic’’ to me, and hence deserving of the highest wonder and awe from me. Or, speaking rigorously and more definitely, I could learn from the child. Yet at the same time | could readily grasp the One conclusions of the child, just as the child can grasp any of the essential conclusions of this book if I state them in words he knows (it is possible to do that for the average child). So obviously, all of that is proof of two im- portant practical points:- (1) The definitely observable facts about so “‘abstract’’ a thing as “‘logic’’ or words show that other people are really deserving of our wonder and respect for their capacities and ultimate dignity (or even ‘‘divinity’’) and lovableness; or those facts show rigorously that we can learn from anyone, but need not be essentially troubled or ‘“‘lowered’”’ if somebody knows more details about a certain thing than we do—for in nearly every subject that state of affairs does exist. (2) Those facts further rigorously show the error of the frequently encountered erudite person who prides himself upon the possession of some special knowledge or intricately complex knowledge of some sort of details. Any ‘‘knowledge’’ which is so complex that it can’t be ex- plained to a child well enough for him to get the essential meaning of it, is either unfinished and in that degree unin- telligible to its erudite possessor, or else is wrong in some de- gree and not knowledge—simply isn’t so. When such knowledge is also concealed from the average person, as in ‘“secret diplomacy,”’ it has the same defective character, and in addition the concealment is undemocratic and immoral (8167-9), and its possessors deserving of contempt and scorn—instead of envy and an idle curiosity, as was the case in the crude and aristocratic childhood of the race. We shall from time to time see more familiar proof and ex- pression of this paragraph. ] have here simply given the general outline from both the One point of view and the Many point of view, of what the reader can ‘“understand,”’ or has need to; and of what that implies. CHAPTER VII. Statement and proof of valid logic from additional points of view. §50. a. In this section valid logic is briefly but rigor- ously demonstrated by using the principle of incommensura- bility (or commensurability). Two “‘quantities’’ or ‘‘num- bers’’ or units of the Many, or two things, are said to be commensurable when there is some third quantity of the same kind (another thing), called the common measure, which is exactly contained a definite or whole number of times in each. Two quantities are orthodoxly said to be incommensurable when they have no common measure. _ E. g., the diameter of acircle is incommensurable with the circumference; i. e., if the diameter is 1 unit long, the circumference is 3.1415... units long-~meaning that no number will exactly express the UNIVERSE 42 circumference. (Obviously, that orthodox definition agrees with the argument of this book, and does not consider 0 and co ‘‘numbers.’’?) The “‘number’’ 3.1415... or 7 is said to be an incommensurable number—meaning that it is not act- ually a number, as it ultimately can not be positively ex- pressed. b. I shall make some digressive comment in this para- graph, anticipating the conelusion we are to derive, but anticipating it in a not very intelligible form. If the diameter of a circle is a line having a definite length, then it can be conceived, or considered to “‘exist’’ (i. e., to assert that there zs a diameter is not a self-contradiction A—A and A is not=—A; specifically, is not Line—Definite length or Line, and Line is not—Definite length or Line), and its repre- sentation can be “‘drawn’’ as a “‘line’’ on paper. There- fore, if there is a diameter, then it is glaringly obvious that there is not any such thing as a circle or circumference ac- cording to orthodox mathematics—for the circumference is not definite and hence not a line—or can’t exist as anything. A circle is thus conventionally inconceivable, for if we have a circle it can not have a diameter, and vice versa. Similarly, by orthodox mathematics it is absolutely inconceivable that a square have a diagonal, an equilateral triangle an altitude, etc. Orthodox mathematics itself asserts in effect that it is irrational—i. e., nonsensical—to say thata circle may exist, when it says 7 is irrational. Hence, by following the same argument we demolish all orthodox geometry and related mathematical doctrines. In brief, classic logic, as used in geometry, definitely gives nonsense. The immediate conclusion from that reductio ad absurdum (it is somewhat difficult to see clearly to the conclusion here, as the reductio is naturally negative in form), is that there is no exact science. If we do start with the absurd assumption that a line is ever in any Many sense something absolutely exact, then we get into those orthodox difficulties :- briefly summed, that there is no geometry possible. Or, more remotely, we see that the Many members of our equation, That... X This..., and M(varying with)L?T~?, necessarily assert the infinite regress even in geometry. And it can also be seen further that a consistent geometry is dependent upon the ex- plicit solution of the One and Many, and that another way of viewing the orthodox difficulty above is to note that ““line’’ (and similarly point, surface, solid, etc.) is a name containing considerable relationship meaning—is often practically a re- lationship noun, or is “‘abstract’’’—which must in any valid logic be distinguished from Many words. To separate out such relationship terms is equivalent to rewriting geometry and its allied subjects, and the several volumes of that is omitted from this book at this point. Orthodox geometry is Substantially valid; it is merely vague and inaccurate and verbally inconsistent (cf. §$60-3). The reader need not fee] that I have destroyed anything substantial; but in just one paragraph he has seen that he is warranted in being somewhat unimpressed when a mathematician thus rhapso- dizes:- ‘“‘Coterminous with space and coeval with time is the kingdom of mathematics; within this range her dominion is supreme; otherwise than according to her order nothing can exist.’? So-called hard-headed scientists used to listen to that sort of thing soberly. Now it is more kindly to omit the name of the man I just quoted, as he is still alive. c. We may generalize the fact that the diameter is in- commensurable with the circumference into this proposition :- any perimeter is incommensurable with its average diameter. I have not been able to find any published proof of that proposition. It is obviously to me true, simply as a truism involving the solution of the One and Many. If it is not thus obviously true to the reader, or obviously true as being 43 UNIVERSE a perfect analogy (§94g) to the conventional special case of the circle, then this whole book furnishes the proof, and the further proposition which ] show in this section works back- wards to establish the foregoing genera] proposition. d. It therefore follows as a truism, that 7f there were any fixed or exact or constant parts of the universe, it would be absolutely impossible for them to join with the other parts and form a body or a universe that had a_ perimeter. And that truism holds vice versa:- that if there is any real, connected, mutually-working-together universe, then it is absolutely impossible that it should be composed of exact, definite, constant parts ef any given finite size or sizes (for such would give impossible definitely-measurable diameters). e. That last paragraph is the verbal expression of validly rigorous mathematical proof of the truth of this whole book or argument, with respect to its general consistency. Or ex- plicitly, it is rigorous proof of the consistency or formal truth of our general equation, and hence a proof of the erroneousness of all equatious of whatever sort which fail to conform in principle with that general one. And that proof is perfectly reversible; i. e., it itself works vice versa as was seen; also, if the proposition in par. c is accepted, par. d proves the book; and if not now accepted, the book proves the proposition. And obviously, that is a general example of the principle that valid logic is circular; a formal proof of that principle is this:- all expression of proof if valid is re- ducible to the truism A=A, and it is immaterial which 4 of the two A’s comes first, as formally or logically they are identical (§§35, 58}). Hence, if there is any “‘rule’’ that will not work both ways, the “‘rule’’ is not a rule or prin- ciple that is subject to any proof, but is simply a quantitative guess, subject only to temporary inexact verification by meas- urement. Therefore, obviously, as a general principle, no quantitative fact—no proposition which includes in itself any particular time and space (as contrasted with our general L and J, that are relationship words that may be applied to any particular units of the Many)—is susceptible to any such thing as expression of proof; it is subject only to direct obser- vation, or what I called “‘real’’ proof (§35). Or, we can put it at once into scientific terms:- no so-called cyclic pro- cess, short of a cycle including the total universe (in which Land T are not particular measures) is perfectly reversible (Index, ‘“‘Cycle’’). Or, more specifically, xo machine which exists or can be made, short of the total universe, is perfectly reversible. I. e., any well-designed machine will (1) per- form pretty nearly the same operation or cycle after making one ‘‘revolution’’ (such as the earth’s rotating daily in nearly the same time); and may (2) run backwards in revolutions or cycles that more or less approximate the cycles in the ahead direction (in some ordinary machines the approxima- tion is so remote that we briefly say that they ‘‘won’t’’ run backwards, in the same way we say the Kaiser was wrong; §25). But in no case, short of the total universe, will that repetition of a ‘‘cycle’’ ever be an exact repetition (and ingen- eral, repetition includes reversal; see Index, *"Direction’’). Part Two proves that general] principle in useful detail. f. We could go on from that point of view and consist- ently completely describe the universe. The orthodox point of view of the science called heat would be the next step. Or we conld at once shift that principle of cycles to ethics and show that a workable or moral life was ultimately or as a One a perfectly balanced cycle (i. e., reversible cycle, in which the ‘‘other fellow’ had a fair deal or reaction) of vari- ous acts, which cyclic balance is commonly named temperance. In a really unified knowledge, obviously, as a truism, we can start from any point of view and consistently describe the universe; I mention those two large extensions of the One VII §50h present point of view as an example of thet principle. The practical need of having an end to this particular book ob- viously precludes my ever going on toall the implied details —of ever continuing explicitly to name thedots of That... X This...—or even of pointing out that possibility often. g. In this paragraph I summarize the general proof of the argument of the hook, by the use of incommensurables. It is so brief as to be hard to follow. The fact that Many units can not be bounded by a definite or exactly com- mensurate perimeter or One obviously shows that the One and the Many are absolutely irreconcilable in their formal contradictoriness. If we say that there is really and truly a One, then it is, by our everyday language agreements, formally or logically impossible to say that there is simultaneously a real Many. And we can see at once that in general there are two immediately applicable ways of reconciling that con- tradiction:- (1) We can say that the Many is absolutely infinite, and as such is absolutely true at the same time that the One is absolutely true (dué that changes our everyday language agreements, as we shall see). That is what we do say, in our valid logic, in the formal way of reconciling the contradiction (i. e., we formally say L*®7~”). For then obviously we can, in the absolutely infinitely small units of that infinite Many, which are really absolute zero, find a common measure that will serve as a complete measure for the otherwise incommensurable One. Logically, that way is consistent, and gives us our zero-infinity logical rule. But our everyday language is constructed ona formal implication that the One is “‘real,’’ and that the “‘infinite Many”’ is not “‘real,’? and hence is a verbal contradiction (cf. footnote 100c). By such verbal agreements, infinite “‘really’’ means continuous, and not a ‘‘measure.”’ (2) But we can use that formal reconcilement, and at the same time use the practical reconcilement of stating and showing that there is no exact science—that we can not be exact oraccurate about the Many,—that when we do make a ‘‘real’’ or definite perimeter or One, then the Many or that perimeter’s diame- ter actually is not exactly commensurate in any measure that we are verbally able to set down in full. In short, we drop the L°7'—” and use L?7'~, and say that practically there is an infinite regress, which we formally merely imply by writ- ing + as 3.1415..., or as This.... And that practical way of handling the difficulty clearly agrees with the obvious fact that we can and do conceive geometrical circles, and have no difficulty in representing them approximately. h. That rigorous and concise proof of the argument is so brief that it is scarcely susceptible of being more than superficially comprehended at first. Probably a million cor- olNaries—implications—cou!d be dug outof it with but casual vision. Hence, in theory, and also according to my actual experience in using it on some of the ahlest thinkers, it slightly dazes the reader at first. You can use it to gauge your own mental capacity:- If on first reading it you get a vague glimmer of what I am talking about, your mental pow- er is as great as anybody’s in the matter of soundness, integ- rity, or keenness (although that will not perceptibly be a measure of the endurance of that strength—the ability to keep on using such a strong mind until you get, and not merely aspire to, whatever you are after). If you want to compare your mental! strength with mine, you are informed that I had to dig at that proposition for about two years be- fore I got what might honestly be called a definite glimmer —-you probably have a keener mind than mine, but I have considerable endurance. Incidentally, if anybody is fond of brevity, and thinks that anything which is true can be said very briefly, then here, in 29 words, is not only a statement of this whole book, but also a rigorous proof of the §50h VII One truth of it and of a unification of all knowledge:- Any perimeter is incommensurable with its average diameter. Hence, if there are exact finite parts it is impossible for that Many to combine into a One; and vice versa. With further reference to brevity, the title of the book, UNrverss, is a condensation of the book into one word. The defect of brevity is that it is not positive and intelligible. When we say ‘“Brevity is the soul of wit,’’ it is really meant that the essential of language is given by Meaning—that brevity, in the ultimate, is the One word; and that it, like humor, gives us a mild rebirth (§8162a, 34b)—that the equation is, Humor...= Brevity, or Wit, or the One. In that One sense obviously brevity positively expresses nothing, but is relig- ion. We must have a temperate amount of That... * This... (of details) before we can expect to be understood. $51. a. I shall now briefly summarize and prove all the theory of language, using a somewhat different point of view that gives some additional fine points, and also shows that language itself is so flexible or changing or incapable of being put into any absolutely rigid form or logic that it is practically imperative that each person who is going to un- derstand and use a valid Jogic achieve that understanding and skill by experience of his own—getting in the end a valid logic (a style) which although thus valid is formally a_ little different from that used by any other person. Even the expres- sion of the most rigorous mathematics can not validly be put into an absolutely fixed mould or form: always judgment ts needed. Hence, we need to look at some of the fine points of language; and truistically the argument must be- come complicated, and will for that reason require attention if it is to be understood. This section is very hard reading. If the reader is not an expert at mathematics, science, or logic, or desirous of being one, he can perhaps most satisfac- torily and usefully to himself merely scan the pages of it, taking only what strikes his interest. b. We made an agreement as to what words do, and the formal agreement that we shall not say A—=A and simul- taneously A ts not—=A. We then observed, as a formal] basis of all language—or language mechanics,—that there are three more or less distinct forms of words, which are analo- gous to the three parts of the Trinity. The fundamental truism concerning those three forms omits the use of one form (the One), and is this:- if we are going to talk about parts of the whole (as we tacitly agree to do when we use language of any sort), then we must have (Z) the names of those parts (God the Sons), which must, as the truism, then be joined into the whole [which One need not be explicitly named] by (2) symbols or names which do join them togeth- er (relationship words, or God the Holy Ghost). So far as logical necessities of language go, we could verbally stop there, with just those two forms of words—(Z) and (2),— and understand the unified meaning, but not say Meaning. And we could consider that formally there were two reacting parts (i. e., the Many words with the relationship words)— a verbal dualism fundamental to all speech that is positive, all doctrines, all machines. The reader may note that I have shifted view point, and instead of taking a con- crete view of the actual Many, with zts parts reacting among themselves, I am looking at language directly, and consider- ing what I call the reaction on each other of its two sorts of words that have been mentioned. I therefore truistically consider that there is a verbal dualism (1) (2), in place of the That... < This... heretofore expressed (for explicit con- sideration of that new form, see footnote h). That shift of point of view of itself shows how very flexible our language is, and how, if we formally omit some part, other words will UNIVERSE 44 imply it (I have omitted mentioning any but one formal] unit of the Many:- naming only (2) ). ce. So we have (2) verbally reacting with (1). But, to obtain the previously mentioned convenience in jogging our memories and attention (and probably as a vestige of prim- eval Janguage, in which there existed only One words, while and before men were inventing the other parts of the lang- uage machine), we all actually do go on toa tautological process, and deliberately repeat what the primary necessity in formal speech would and does do of itself; i. e., we use (3) words or symbols which again assert—which now explic- itly name—the whole or One which the other two forms have already said or positively expressed,—these third, tautologi- cal words being God the Father. It is that pure tautology of (in a way) deliberately saying twice everything we have to say, that has been the final ‘“‘mystery’’ that for ages puzzled the seers. We knew so well what that mystery was that we exuberantly said it twice—which was most illogical by the classical logic, which frowns so on exuberance that it has almost killed our quite proper and correct commonsense in- stinct to use two or a dozen negatives when we are sure we mean zo, and has produced the monstrosity, “May I not?’’ d. We may summarize what we have:- The form (7) is parts of the verbally-split universe; the form (2) joins those verbal splittings together again into the whole; the form (3) tautologically names and thus repeats the whole. Or, (2) used in connection with (2) is the whole or meaning, and is also tautologically verbally equivalent to (3). We may write that (7) x(2)=(8). e. Obviously, (7) and (3) are logically or Jormally self- contradictory. Also, (Z) asserts a splitting, and (2) asserts a rejoining, and those two ideas are in reality or meaning ab- solutely self-contradictory; or (1) and (2) produce or assert nullity or zero in the sense that the things asserted by (Z) are not really split off or separated. Again it can be noted that I am taking a different point of view, by explic- itly considering as a form itself the contradiction introduced by (3), and considering contradictions in both form and meaning. As a matter of fact, we have started on an infinite regress of logic itself (see par. h). It should also be definitely noted that when I said ‘the things asserted by (Z) are not really split off or separated,’ we are using real merely as a tacit verbal agreement:- for we could just as well have said that the One (3) was not really connected. And it can again (see §49¢, etc.) be seen directly that by thus reversing the agreement we produce no real changes in the conclusions which we are going to derive, but merely reverse language or the dictionary. f. It is also obvious that (7) and (2) are Jormally totally different or contradictory, being the two sorts of words which are formally needed together to make an explicit or positively expressed whole. Hence, when we use them together, as (1) X(2), we have the fundamental lingual requirement of the truism in par. b:- that we split the universe and then join it. So that formal contradiction must inhere to make the logic valid, as it balances and cancels the formal contra- diction we started with. That finishes, from the present point of view, with formal agreements (but see par. h for extension of the point of view). g. We then have the disagreements in meanings—(Z) X (2) being made up of parts, and (3) being really a whole. But (1) x(2) is only formally made up of parts, because the explicit meaning contradiction inheres only in (2), and is re- moved or really contradicted by the (2). Consequently, though there is a contradiction in meaning of the words we use, the contradiction is destroyed as stated, and is not real in language as a whole. Consequently, the whole equation 45 UNIVERSE (1) X(2)=(8) is absolutely true, and must contain the double contradiction—one of form and one of meaning. That double contradiction also justifies, or formally necessitates, from this point of view, the existing tautology. h. But, language as a whole thus being without any act- ual self-contradiction, it follows at once that we have now really failed to use our requisite mechanical truism that was started with in par. b:- that language must have reacting or contradictory parts. "" Hence, we start all over again with our equation, and consider the total single symbol ‘(1)X (2)=(3)’ as being a standard whole that is now a Many, or a new (1), which we may write ((7)); and then we construct a new (2) and new (3), and put them together into an equa- tion in order to get a positive assertion that is not ineffable. In short, we now have to begin to duplicate ‘language’ or ‘logic’ itself, in order to get the intelligible expression or equation that applies the truism. And obviously, it is an infinite regress. | When we do it infinitely (use up ail time and space—or, do what is practical, take time and space as unreal), we achieve a logical and also a verbally complete lang- uage, or an eract language. I know it sounds queer, and is hard to understand. Well; there are always some men with minutely seeing minds (who as a compensating characteristic usually fail to see wholes or commonsense very well). They would find considerable fault with our original general equation as first derived, because the equation was substantially said to be finished or absolute. To say that, is equivalent to our conclusion in par. g, that the form of equa- tion there was absolutely true. It is true; but only when it is seen that the infinite regress stated in this paragraph is also implicitly contained in it, and considered formally com- pleted in it. But the men who have trouble in seeing a whole—usually the materialists—demand the details. So 1 have explicated the infinite regress for them. They can now follow it out in detail as far as they care to go (keep on drawing in the actual smaller and smaller picture of the ad- vertisement), and keep on until they are by actual experience convinced that it will give an absolute whole. Obviously, they can not honestly assert that it does not give a whole un- til they have actually kept on infinitely on the regress, if it does not sooner convince them that they fave seen a whole. So if they can’t see, they are rigorously tied up to an experi- mental occupation that will keep them occupied and quiet forevermore, or allow them only obviously inconsistent talk. §52. a. The last section, in making the flexibility of language obvious, implied some definite facts which are set down in this section somewhat at random. b. We have seen more vividly that the same word may be used in each of the three forms. Often, many meanings that have been attached to some given word in the past may be now nearly dead, but still slightly remain as implications 5lbThe reason J succeeded in making an intelligible or positively expressed equation, instead of winding up with an equation or lang- uage which, as just asserted, was without reacting parts or ‘contra- dictions,’ and which hence was ineffable and unintelligible, is this:- without saying anything definitely abont it in par. b and d (where it would have been confusing), I introduced into the equation the re- lationship symbols X and =, which was equivalent to implicitly re- duplicating the three forms in infinite regress, or toimplicit assertion of this footnote. A simple description of that literally infinitely in- volyed statement is this:- inan advertisement which contains a picture of a man holding a periodical on which pictured-periodical again appears the same advertisement, it is obvions that to be consistent the second picture must contain another picture of the man holding the periodical on which again appears in still smaller picture the same advertisement, and so on ad infinitum. That eqna- tion (2)<(2)=(8) was the original ‘advertisement,’ and it, sO far as] at first explicitly stated ought to have been (2) (2) ()—an ineffable, unintelligible language without contradiction, etc. See the text for the further unwinding of that infinite involution. One VII §$52e —or implication-ghosts, so to speak. Words, like science, can’t be accurate or exact, and it is now quite obvious that our formal separation of words into classes is itself just a con- venient, arbitrary form which is inexact, and is subject, like all Many things, to infinite regress. c. We thus again see that we can not validly make any sharp separations in the universe—not even of words into classes, although words are obviously as arbitrary as any- thing. And that fact will often serve as a useful measure of the ability of men. If we observe a man insist- ing on “‘sharp distinctions’? between any classes of actual things, or insisting that kis way of making classes (of judging any Many proposition—or that in human affairs he knows just how to separate the sheep and the goats) is essentially right, we may at once safely decide that he is more or less incompetent, and knows little of his subject. In this day, that test is perhaps the most easily applied test of mental competence. But of course the incompetent who is cock- sure about quantitative problems will quickly discover what yardstick we are using on him, and superficially avoid being so obviously foolish. d. Or we may express it, that a word used in a context has ““fields’’ or implication-auras that stretch out and bind the word continuously in meaning to the context, even if the word does appear superficially to be ““printed separate.’’ Hence, words in use have the characteristic of other Many things; just as there is no sharp This, but always Tits..., so no word is sharply Word, but always Word.... Modern physical theories have atoms with such “‘fields’’ (§89, XI). e. And we may observe that words are perhaps the most highly specialized tool, or machine, or means of trans- mitting force, that we have—meaning that it is possible to control the extensiveness and intensity of the force, and hence its resulis, more completely when we use the language machine than when we use any other machine (e. g., than when we use the skeletal levers and muscles behind a fist; or apply them to shoot a gun). Words actually ‘“‘exert force,’” just as explicitly and definitely as do molar bodies— as do machine guns, a heaved brick, or an engine. The words printed here (even if primarily considered as only so much ink) consist of very energetic atoms that *“foreibly”’ make very perceptible changes in your eyes and nervous system. Considered more indirectly as directing your atten- tion to certain things (and that is also what a 16-inch gun is ‘for’’), they act as a trigger—a slight starting or initiating force—that may result in enormous force transmittal. The advantage of words is that they can be devised to transmit very accurately the kind and quantity of force (the modern technical word of course is energy, but we may here continue to use the ambiguous but more forcible popular *“foree’’), which it is desired to transmit in order to effect a given pur- pose. Truistically, the effectiveness of words depends, like that of all other tools, upon the skill] and strength and endur- ance of the user (actua]ly upon his whole personality; cf. §140e), and also upon the personality of the receiver. Every- body except infants and marked defectives uses words—and the infant really uses the primitive words (One ejaculations, or cries), and makes up by emphasis some of what his words lack in positiveness. | The business man carries on much of his business with words—often all of it, ina direct sense. Bullets and clubs are obviously very crude tools for the ex- ercise of force, as they are under very poor contro] and give very uncertain results. The truth of that is rather well recognized, as is proved by the fact that people who wish to seem intelligent or even barely civilized invariably try to show that the other side started the use of ““brute’’ force— i. e., poorly directed force. Of course, if militaristic persons §52e VIl One of such inferior mentality start using ‘‘brute’’ force they thereby definitely indicate that they are incapable of very well understanding or using more efficient forces, and intelli- gent people have to give them a sufficient dose of the sort of force they do understand (§114c). A person who is militaristic in ““private’’ life—in affairs between individ- uals rather than between societies and governments—is con- ventionally called a blackguard or bully. Militarism is merely wholesale blackguardism or bullying—and still exists simply because it is a little harder to see the nature of a reaction between many scattered people than it is to see the nature of the same reaction between a few close together **private’’ people, so that some persons of a low grade of intelligence fail to see its blackguard character. f. But ultimately words are a tool—a means ;—funda- mentally a relationship, just as ““force’’ is ultimately a rela- tionship (888, etc.). Because they are so useful, we are prone to mistake words for the actualities to which they point us or join us. That is word idolatry—a mistaking of formulas, ““systems,’’ creeds, dogmas, books, for the One, which is as silly as bowing down to and being afraid of a golden calf as such—and a good deal more prevalent. g. And finally, we may note that if we begin to state our observations of words in detail, we have the collection of conclusions that is called rhetoric. I give a minor example :- Adjectives and adverbs are observably not very definitely anv one of the three kinds of words; they are rather vaguely Many words which supply some of the dots after This.... Hence, because of that vagueness, when they are used they subtract from the forcefulness or clear simplicity of what is meant. Therefore, where force and rough-clarity is desired adjectives and adverbs should be at a minimum. But where explicitness and considerable accuracy is desirable—where we have to be definite about some of the dots: display a keener judgment,—adjectives and adverbs (and parenthetical phrases somewhat equivalent) have to be used to some extent. h. Rhetoric is commonly called an art, or an empirical science—meaning that no definite relationships or unity be- tween the observed facts of it was easily perceptible. We now see that the statement of the details of a valid logic be- comes a connected, rational science that includes rhetoric. Hence, the argument unifies logic and rhetoric; and the facts of rhetoric serve as observations that verify the forego- ing description of logic. A definitely scientific treatise on rhetoric is omitted at this point. It is a historical fact that centuries ago the name for general or unified know- ledge was rhetoric or grammar. Apparently, men rather consciously recognized then that in the mechanics of lang- uage lay the solution of their puzzles. But the rhetoricians failed to clarify the puzzles, started exploiting and became idolaters of words, and fell into such disrepute that conven- tional “‘rhetoric’’ is still tainted with it, and their more hon- est successors were known by a new name:-_ philosophers. OC CHAPTER VIII. §53. a. In this chapteris discussed a mechanical model of the forms of language. This model is a so-called single surface ring, including its infinitely numerous variations from what we may consider its regular form. This model is capable of being directly used as the model, or mechanical] representation, of everything (S63i, Part Two). In_ this chapter we confine ourselves to such few simple facts as are needed to givea brief but rigorous description of the different possible sorts of language and-or space (and time; cf. 8150). b. Iam unable to find any full mathematical treatment Mechanical model of language. 46 UNIVERSE of our single surface ring, although | remember seeing & statement that there was such a treatment. I have not gone very far into the investigation of the figure—just far enough to see the possibilities of unlimited application of the model, which has been a geometrical curiosity for years, and is nee mentioned in the usual text, or ‘Encyclopaedia Brittanica. A good popular description of single surface rings is given by Hering in ‘‘Scientific American,’’ Feb. 21, 1914. He also gives a preliminary mathematical investigation of those rings and some additional interesting facts in another article ( Se. Am. Supplement,’’ Dec. 21, 1918, reprinted from Jour. Franklin Inst.,’’ Aug., Nov., 1918). S54. a. The best way to comprehend this single surface model is to make a rough one—which can be done in a min- ute. It is such a surprising figure on first acquaintance that only the actual model is likely to be easily intelligible. Take a strip of paper (say) nearly a foot long and about an inch wide. Lay flat. The strip has two surfaces (neglecting now its thickness, and the conse- quent very narrow surfaces of the two side edges and two end edges), which we may term surface A and sur- face B. Hold one end of the strip flat, and lift the other end and turn it—twist it-—over (around 180°), so that sur- face A is up at one end and B upat the other, with the strip twisted a half turn, as shown roughly in Fig. 54a. Then, without further twisting the ends relatively to each other, bring the two ends together to form a ring, and fasten the ends together (preferably with glue; or with a pin). It is then a rough single surface ring (unsymmetrical or warped in some respects, as we shall see). A picture of a symmet- rical ring (with appreciable thickness) is shown in Fig. 63c. b. If you place a finger on any part of the surface, and move it all around the surface, touching the surface, it will then be on the surface that was originally opposed to the surface you started on, although your finger never left the continuous surface. I. e., if you started on surface A, after your finger moves all around the ring it will be on surface B, which is now a surface continuous with A, and not. structur- ally opposite. The reason for that is of course that the 180° twist gradually turns the finger onto the ‘‘other side,’’ and the twist also permits the surfaces to be continuous when fastened into a ring and the thickness neglected. c. We may note some preliminary properties:- If with a knife or scissors the ring be split in two in the direction of its length (i. e., the original strip, if it had been flat, as in Fig. 54c, and not in a ring, would be cut along the dotted line), then there results a single ring; but this new ring has a 360° twist in it (a double twist), and has two sur- faces, and has twice the | | _ length around. Then, if that ring be similarly split, two rings result, interlinked or beknotted with each other, and each with the same double twist and length around as the double-twisted ring. All subsequent splittings result in adding one more interlinked ring of the same length and the same double twist. But, if the single surface ring has an edge cut off (not ‘splitting’ the ring so that the ends of the dotted line in Fig. 54c would come together if the strip had been in a ring), and we kee on cutting around (twice) until we come to the place a started from, a narrower single surface ring than the original is left, interlinked with a double surface ring of See th length, which is the edge that is cut off. : Fig. 54a, ZG. Fig. 54c, 47 UNIVERSE d. Let us now tentatively agree that a single surface ring is a symbol of language, and hence a symbol of the uni- verse. Or, we may call a symbol a model. Let us agree that one surface of the original strip, say surface A, repre- sents the One; and that surface B represents the Many. And let us consider that the thickness of the ring is negligible (for the time being), and that the ring joins together at or in or as a geometrical line, instead of our having to lap the ends over each other in order to glue or pin them con- veniently. I. e., let one end of the original untwisted strip as shown in Fig. 54c be ZI, and the other end I’Z’; then, when we make the ring, Z joins to Z, and I to 1’, and we have the single line ZI for a joint—it coinciding with ZT’. Finally, let us agree that the 180° twist represents relation- ship. It then at once follows as truistic that neither surface is, or ‘‘defines,’’ the ring, nor is the 180° twist the ring. But the three together—Many surface, One surface, relationship twist——completely define or express the ring. e. In this paragraph I digress slightly from the direct argument and show the nature of the infinite regress, and also of a “‘symbol.’’ I said that the three parts completely define or express the ring. Yet the three together are ob- viously not really the ring. The ring itself is the actual thing between the surface A and surface B, which thing is twisted and is not the twist, and which we are taking now to be of negligible thickness. | We might say that the ring is what or that which is between the two defined surfaces: the geometrical surfaces are merely the limits of the ring, and ‘describe’ or de-fine it. In the same way, the universe is what is described by our words. But if we are asked to state verbally what that ‘what’ is, then all we can do is to begin to divide the ring up and define it as the collection of parts which are then given by surfaces which are closer and closer to coinciding, and to being pure geometrical surfaces of zero thickness. But sero thickness is not positive language, as we agreed before; it is mysticism (also, that attempt to say ‘what,’ may be observed to be truistically circular language or logic). Hence, we can not, with positive language in our finite lives, go absolutely to zero language and name all the zero parts of the ring. We keep going closer and closer, in infinite regress, towards that zero thickness, or really exact quantitative intelligible meaning. And the symbols are those Many steps, which use time and _ space. And obviously, although all attempts to use language wil] clearly be of that eternally formally self-contradictory nature (as a truism; be- cause the language formally and finitely is xot the thing it describes), the use of our concrete model gives us at once the conclusion that we know what we mean, even with that verbal regress which we can not actually finish. We know about the ring by looking at it, observing it: we experience its ‘existence’ (cf. §22); or really prove it (cf. §35) by see- ing it. Ina few words here I describe the ring—symbolize it, or point to it intedligibly, and you know the ring—and I do that without giving the infinite words of the regress. [n- stead of using an ‘‘infinite number’’ of words I have actually used about 800—and you not only ‘‘know’’ the ring in gen- eral, but you have already seen a number of related things. §55. a. When we take the surface B of the ring as representing the Many, then we have arbitrarily agreed that we shall divide it into parts, or the Many, and that each part may be given a name—and must have a definite and positive name when referred to. We may agree that instead of naming the parts as various This’s and That’s, we can give them the general sort of naming called numbering. Suppose we divide surface B into parts by lines across it, parallel to ZI (Fig. 54c). Then obviously each number may be, conventionally, one of two things:- (1) it may be the One VIII §é56c name of one of those lines; or (2) it may be the name of the part of surface B between one really geometrical or zero line and the next. b. Usually, the mathematicians and logicians seem to mean that a number (and by implication, azy name-—but they probably would not acknowledge the implication) refers simply to one of those zero dividing lines—to a dividing (which is actually zero; and *‘abstract’’), and not to what is considered divided), In that case it is obvious that regard- less of how many actual or positive numbers we used innam- ing all the parts of the Many (of B), always there would be the spaces left between those imaginary geometrical or inef- fable zero lines or numbers, which spaces were the actual things to be indicated. Inshort, by that rather conventional practice, we have to name or number to a read infinity in or- der to get that surface B actually verbally named; and a real infinity here obviously contradicts the nature of that conven- tional numbering or Many—for real infinity means continu- ous. Also, it is further obvious that this more conventional way of naming or numbering the Many results in what is practically an infinite regress (see §58d for the details, etc.). c. If we take the second view—that the name or num- ber refers to the space between one line and the next (e. g., that 2 means the part of B between say Z,]; and Zel2),—it is again obvious that there is nothing whatever which determines or fixes how long (kow much) that space is, or should be; nor how long the surface B (i. e., the whole of the Many) is. I. e., if the model ring is the universe, there is positively nothing outside it, which serves as a standard or as a meas- ure to determine the length of surface B (or its width, pro- vided we divided B in other ways than by those parallel lines). Consequently, it is glaringly obvious that there is absolutely nothing which determines fundamentally what— how much—a unit of the Many is. We take such a unit ar- bitrarily, making it convenient. Also, it is equally obviously a truism that there is absolutely no way of verbally stating positively how much the universe is—of giving it positive ““boundaries’’ (we see the nature of its ‘‘boundaries’’ in Part Two; Index, ““Difference surface’’). | For time and space obviously do not apply to the whole universe or to the whole model of it. Time and space are simply the arbitrary con- ventions we use in dividing upthe surface B:- for obviously, we determined Z]), Zele...Znln..., by saying ‘the space or length between,’ and tacitly took it that we required time to go over the space (or to take the parts in a one by one order, if we look at it that way). It therefore again follows by this second point of view that we may name a part of the ring anything we please (call it any measure); and that there is an infinite regress of naming. There can be no exact science for the simple reason that ultimately there is nothing which serves as a fixed standard or “‘center’’ by which we may judge any exactness. As soon as we have this concrete model before our eyes it is fairly easy to see directly that those things are true. §56. a. When we take the surface Aas the One—as God the Father, or monistically,—it is obvious that we con- sider it undivided, or as being a whole, and thus take it into our perceptions or consciousness at once—at one time. Itis one surface; a child can conceive or perceive that—he does, in fact, and does it before he is able to divide it into the Many, as we saw when observing a child count (§26), b. This One surface as a model of the universe or One is characterized chiefly by its simplicity (i. e., familiarity), obviousness, and total lack of definiteness, “positiveness,’ and properties. It simply is continuous, or One, or the whole. c. Possibly the most important point of view to be taken of the observable fact that the One surface as a model has §56c VIII One absolutely no properties in any positive or definite sense, is that the One is not determined or bounded in any way. That is obviously a truism, and it clearly implies that time and space does-do not apply to the One. There are no paris of the One, considered apart (spacially **separated’’) from the other parts, and hence comparable with them, the com- parison being fundamentally a ‘‘property.’’ 857. a. Relationship words are represented by the 180° twist. Obviously it is the existence of such a continuous twist that maintains the ring as a continuous surface. We have seen (§28h) that the chief characteristic of relationship is that all relationship is that of identity. That may be clearly seen from our model:- Suppose we hang the ring over (say) the left forefinger held horizontally, placing the left thumb on the ‘upper’ surface of the ring; and then pull the ring so that it slips around between the finger and thumb. ‘Both’ surfaces finally rub on the thumb, without the thumb’s changing its space location: the 180° twist or relationship simply travels in the down-hanging part of the ring. The thumb obviously always bears identically the same relationship to the total form of the ring, although it rubs all of it in turn. (I. e., it does, assuming that the ring represents the universe with nothing outside, which is the same as assuming that the actual model ring is perfectly homogeneous and flexible and acted upon by steady forces, thus making it always hang in a constant loop—none of which is true of the actual paper ring. ) b. It is to be emphasized that the last paragraph tacitly assumed that the ring was ‘‘symmetrical’’—which means ultimately that space and time, as used to name its Many aspect was unchanging (or agreed with the “‘space’’ of or- dinary geometry, called Euclidian). © When that space and time is not considered Euclidian, we have other aspects of relationship (§§$60-1, 66). We may observe here that ‘sym- metrical,’ if applied to the One, or to the ring considered as a One and without reference to the arbitrary Many naming of surface B, meaus just the same as ‘unsymmetrical.’ That is obviously true, from this truism:- if the ring, as a total universe or whole, hangs from the forefinger, then except for its own arbitrary Many parts, there is nothing whatever by which to determine or to state whether it is ‘““symmetrica]’’ or not (whether its ‘“space’’—which in that One aspect is not ‘‘ased’’ at all-—is ‘‘straight”’ [i. e., Euclidian], or variously “‘curved’’ or “‘warped’’ [i. e., non-Euclidian]; cf. §38); hence, the twist then is always merely the whole 180° twist (regardless of whether it be named 180° or not), and hence is always as such absolutely identical as the same relationship regardless of any sliding of the ring on the finger. We shall see (beginning at $60) that those very simple considerations (they are merely truisms, which are easily seen by observing the model—as a mnemonic device), are fundamentally the complete solutions of the modern verbal puzzles about non- Euclidian space, whether parallels meet at infinity, 4-dimen- sion or n-dimension space, and the theory of relativity. So this paragraph, obvious and trivial as it is just of itself, is important. For some authoritative thinkers get their minds into a soft foggy daze contemplating those puzzles—and all the “‘evils’’ of the world result from such states of mind. 858. a. Taking the ring as a whole, and as represent- ing the three sorts of words, wesee first that our three forms of words actually are completely symbolized. The One and the Many are formally contradictory in that the first is not formally separated into parts and the second is. But the ring shows that the two are really the samc, and inseparably continuous—that continuity being achieved by the identical relationship or twist. b. The next important thing is to note that it would be UNIVERSE 48 impossible positively to express or symbolize a meaning (any whole) unless we use some sort of arbitrary contrast (or a self-contradiction—such as is given by considering B split into Many parts) and subsequent identification of the con- trast by a **relationship.’’ The very nature of the matter is a truism, as we have seen before in several ways, and now have before our eyes in a concrete model. So a verbal repe- tition is unnecessary. Many similar models and many valid languages can be made, as is shown in detai] in this chapter. The foregoing is merely a statement of the essential characteristic of all those models and languages. And to repeat emphatically, the foregoing about contradic- tion and subsequent identification refers to a posztive lang- uage. Itis not essential that we use posztzve language: cows do not, having merely a few One vocal ejaculations, and cows therefore do not have our verbal puzzles. But cows pay for that advantageous immunity by failing to have a very useful, or ““controllable,’’ language tool. ec. And the final rather important thing we can see at once from the whole model is a concrete illustration of the sole logical rule that it is always self-contradictory nonsense to confuse one sort of word with another sort (that confusion being always equivalent to saying A=A and A is not=A). We see the explicit details of that general rule, in terms of our model, in the remainder of this section. A further ex- tension of the rule, in details from other points of view, is given in subsequent sections (§§59-66) about space and time —that extension amounting to the general principles of measurement or judgment that are in practice used by all people in all their activity or living, regardless of whether they are conscious of it or not. d. If we make aring of the strip in Fig. 54c we may consider that ZI is the geometrical line from which we begin to name or number the universe, and Z’l’ the line limiting the other end. By usual conventions, ZI is therefore 0, and ZT’ is ©. Obviously, if we follow more or less conventional mathematics and say that the line at the end of a space (or part) is the “‘number’’ (§55b), then ZI is not a number, but is the beginning or limit of the first number, 1, of which Zil, (and not ZI) would be the name or number. __In brief, ZI is a line not in the universe (the model universe), in the same sense that Zh, etc., are zn it. Consequently, even if we are going to agree to name an abstraction such as a zero line a number (it can be validly done; but usually itis inad- visable; doing so gcts us into other puzzles mentioned in par. f), it is impossible to say that ZI or 0 is a number (or that its coincident line ZI’ or © isa number) in the same sense that Zi],, Zala, are numbers. e. The simplest way to consider ZI is to take it posi- tively that a number or name actually applies tothe part that is in the space between the lines. That actual part is ab- stracted in the mathematicians’ idea that a number names just the line. The truth of the matter obviously is that if I say just ‘2--38—=5,’ the sentence of itself is explicitly utterly meaningless; and hence nobody can have the remotest idea of whether it is true or untrue. In practice, we consider that 2 and 3 and 5 imply “‘things.’’ Therefore, if we act- ually supply what mathematics abstracts (ef. next para- graph) then each actual number must apply to a part of the ring, and it is glaringly obvious that 0 (or ZJ) is not a num- ber, there being no part or space on the ring to which it applies. In precisely the same way, regardless of any other consideration as to “‘numbers,’’ Z'I’ or © is also nota num- ber, but the upper limit of numbers. The actual unit space or part that just ‘precedes’ Z’J’ obviously has a name that is indefinitely large, but which, if we are rigorously explicit in speech can not be © or any fixed ‘“last number.’’ 49 UNIVERSE f. As the mathematicians actually imply the space be- tween lines as being what it is the numbers name, regardless of whether they say abstractly that a line—a zero part—is a number, we need not use time and attention showing and seeing in mathematically abstract language that © or ZI’ is also, by such language, truistically not a number. Ttis broadly obvious that it could readily be done, by considering that there is positively nothing which may be used as a standard showing how many numbers there are in the uni- verse, or in our model of it (also, see par. d). g. When we explicitly consider that the strip in Fig. 54c¢ is made into a ring, then obviously ZI and Z’I’ are co- incident as ZI, the line-joint—butt-joint—of the ring; or 0 and © are coincident, and the joint may be called the gero- infinity line. Clearly, therefore, it makes no difference in which direction we name or number when we sum up and be- gin dealing with the One; or, in an absolute sense ‘‘down’’ and “‘up,’’ etc., are identical. (That matter of direction repeatedly comes up hereafter; see especially 899b. The essential point of it is that time and space are ‘direction,’ and are arbitrary and simply disappear from the One or real meaning, just as that line which is the ‘beginning’ and the ‘end’ of time and space or direction has really disappeared in our model as a zero geometrical abstraction. ) Also, Oand © are obviously logically identical—their ‘‘lines’’ co- incide. Jf we are on the Many surface of the ring, and pass over that zero-infinity line, going in either direction, we are then on the One surface; and vice versa. I. e., if at any time in language we introduce a O or an %®, or any of their equivalents, we have by so doing shifted from the Many to the One, or vice versa. h. This paragraph is of slight practical importance, and hence is condensed so much as to be hard to see: The relationship words are obviously as asum total reducible to Land T; i. e., the 180° twist is itself actually a change in direction (i. e., in space during a time). That is nothing but an implication of our second member, M(varying with) L*T~?;- for that member says that M or the Many changes as we pass over space during time. Consequently, it is ob- vious that if we speak of that time or space as being a Many part of the whole One (if we make a relationship word into a Many word or into a One word), that change implies that we have tacitly assumed the whole of the twist before we thus change the form, and hence have formally passed over the zero-infinity line by assumption. In short, it introduces a 0 oran ©, andif that is not provided for by the context, 4 logical contradiction results. Hence, we may validly say that we need only one rule in order to be absolutely consist- ent logically :- do not introducea Ooran © without balanc- ing the formal contradiction introduced (ef. §43). i. The nature of the error of confusing relationship words with others may be observed directly from our ring:- Suppose that it be held, hanging down, with the One or A surface up. Then the upper loop of the ring may be delib- erately turned over on the finger (through 180°) so that loc- ally at the top the Many or B surface-is now up. We may call that process:- ‘going over the edge of the ring.’ Sometimes that additional twist put in the top loop of the act- ual paper ring will simply ‘run’ itself out through the bottom loop—ttaveling down through each side of the ring and ‘mutually cancelling’ itself at the bottom. But unless the paper is rather elastic, that local turn-over at the top puts in a twist of 180° on one side of the upper loop of the ring, and a twist of 180° in the opposite sense on the other side—a total additional twist for the whole ring of 360° (‘‘arithmeti- cally’? it is 360°). And it is directly observable that the whole effect, relative to getting onto the opposite surface One Vill §59a (getting from the One to the Many), is equivalent to sliding the whole ring around once (as in 857a), bringing in the original 180° relationship; for sliding the whole ring around is 360° (or corresponds to the universe or ©—or to 0 and 0°). Now, going over the edge of the ring, to get from one sort of words to another, is obviously equivalent to using a relationship word as a Many word, or as a One word (or, to put it negatively:- going over the edge ignores relationship). And doing so, as we have seen, is equivalent logically to introducing the whole relationship or 180° twist—or to pass- ing once over the zero-infinity line. Hence, it is directly obvious that all relationship is identical—is that ‘twist.’ j. It is further obvious from our ring that all valid logie is circular logie—meaning specifically that it is continuous logic, or expression that in the end comes back and closes with itself—‘‘checks up,’’ verifies with itself, concludes with the truisms from which it formally started. We may see directly from the model that the reason for all that is that all valid reasoning must have a complete statement of relationship, or a relationship which goes all around the ring in order to go continuously from the One to the Many, or vice versa. Only such a complete relationship is explicitly a relationship of identity (as we saw, from a somewhat dif- ferent point of view, in §57b). If we go over the edge of the ring we clearly have not explicitly put in a complete rela- tionship—-which was in the last paragraph emphasized by the concrete fact that a two-sided contradictory twist was thus put into the ring. If we go over the edge, we say A=A (that A is, say, a Many unit), and then simultaneously (on the other surface) we say A is not—=A (that A isthe One); obviously, A is’ ultimately the One, but the way to get it ex- pressed as the One is not to talk fast and loose that way, but to follow our agreements and go through all time and space, identifying it with ad/ others of the Many—that being equivalent to sliding the ring around. Get-rich-quick schemes won’t really work, even with mere words. k. All that of course is rather confusing at first. The model helps to make it conciete, and gradually clears up the confusion. The actual difficulty lies in the fact that although time and space are primarily used to express relationship, we often use them as the other two sorts without noticing the differences. I merely show how the change from one form to another must be explicitly made. We can acquire such conscious skill in the use of words only gradually: for familiar affairs we instinctively have that skill, but we get corfused in less familiar affairs—to the extent of agnosticism. l. The model, besides serving to help us consciously avoid the customary confusions of the three sorts of words, gives a clear insight into the solution of What is real? or What is truth? Taking it in terms of the Trinity, we see at once that neither (1) the God the Father or One surface A, nor (2) God the Sons or Many surface B, nor yet (3) the God the Holy Ghost or relationship twist, is itself (regarded separately) the ring or ‘‘reality.’’ | Nor is any combination of any two of those the ring or ‘“truth,’’ or the universe. Obviously, only the three together are real or true. Conse- quently, the valid or dynamic logic (S49j1) which takes it that each part, as it comes up, is real, simply means that one part, if it is intelligible, implies the other two. Hence, the dynamic or everyday logic is shown to be ultimately true. 859. a. We may now see, by this model, just why there are three dimensions of space, and not some other number of dimensions. Our final conclusion is going to be this simple one:- we have devised (invented; agreed upon—per- haps mostly unconsciously in the past) for everyday use the language with the fewest possible forms or dimensions that §59a VIII One could still be positive or explicit; three-dimension space contains the fewest number of dimensions out of the infinite regress L®7'~@” that oould explicitly be so. In get- ting that conclusion we shall see that an unlimited series of other sorts of languages is possible (cf. §38a; and as indi- cated before, English, French, etc., are ‘ different’’ lang- uages merely in having somewbat different vocabularies; formally or logically they are the same). This investigation of the number of dimensions of space is obviously a quantita- tive one. ‘There is no absolute necessity about using three dimensions: there is no absolute necessity that we use lang- uage, Or any space. Three dimensions are ‘‘necessary”’ only jf we are to talk in the easiest, shortest, or ‘‘simplest’’ way. It is a fundamental law that we do act in the path of least resistance (with ultimate accuracy :- in the path of zo resistance; §$§98m, 104). Consequently, acting according to that law with more or less consciousness or explicitness, everybody takes it for granted that we are going to use the simplest language. So the reader need not fear that I] am going to inflict any new dimensions of space and-or time on him. [am going to show that those who try to do it, and those who try to assert the “‘reality’’ of other kinds of space [or time] (such as the ‘“two’’ non-Euclidian spaces, and the variable space of the relativitists), are implying different languages—and are usually failing to completely formulate and use those other languages, but merely indicate implicitly their possibility. So of course, as a truism, their different sorts of space and time are not intelligible when expressed in ordinary terms of everyday language: such spaces logic- ally contradict that everyday language (assert that they be- long in other, different languages). In order really to understand our language, and use it without making verb- al puzzles for ourselves, we need to understand how to make those other, different languages. At the same time we thus protect ourselves from ever taking seriously, or being puz- zled by, the introduction into or language of such contra- dictions of it, when taken as belonging in our language, as 4-dimension space, ete., which by no means whatever ex- press any idea in our language. We are not familiar with those other languages, of course; so my description of them will truistically be a bit novel and strange—even to the mathematicians whose familiarity extends mostly to views that aren’t so. Unless the reader is a professional scientist, philosopher, or mathematician, or intends to become one, he does not need to grasp especially well the details of the rest of this chapter. If he merely reads it casually he can get all that interests him. b. The model ring is, as a model, considered to be a standard universe; i. e., we use it as a universe, neglecting the remainder of the universe; it is, so to speak, abstracted from everything else, and is, in that abstract condition, for the moment, the whole universe logically. Consequently, every standard universe is obviously an abstraction. When we are talking, and using the valid dynamie logic, consider- ing each sort of word temporarily real, that reality is an abstraction—for the whole reality comes only of actually sup- plying the other two forms. Hence, we see that any use of language, or of any sort of symbol or model, involves a tacit temporary abstraction. That is equivalent merely to the quite obvious fact that we can not say everything at once. Con- sequently, we shall carry the idea abstraction, with reference to our model, to the end, and see what we get. After that, we add everything to it, and get surprising conclusions. ce. We have been considering the ring to be of negligible thickness. If it has zero thickness obviously the two surfaces are coincident (as well as being continuous). If the surfaces are thus absolutely coincident, it is obviously verbally 50 UNIVERSE contradictory (or nonsense) to say that there are two sides. But the fact is that it is nonsense to say that there is any such thing as a geometrical surface; for such a surface 15 what is left of (say) a cube when the cube is wholly removed ; obviously, nothing is left. Consequently, it is obviously sen- sible (as the cancellation of two nonsenses) to say that there is an upper surface A and a lower surface B of the ring when it is an abstract geometrical surface. Please keep those apparent trivialities slightly in mind for a moment. d. This model ring has been tacitly taken to have some breadth. The one we made was casually said to be about an inch wide (§54a). It is obvious that the 180° twist (the es- sential relationship that establishes ultimate continuity of the two surfaces) requires that the tacitly accepted breadth be warped some. Now suppose that we make the ring still more abstract than the mere geometrical surface, and thus take it to be a dine, without that breadth. We may consider that line to have the surfaces A and B, and to have the 180° twist (and the line in taking that twist would obviously have no warp). It clearly is formally explicit and cancelling of zeros, to have that line with two surfaces, and hence be thus “twistable’: see last paragraph. | e. Therefore, we now have it, in considerable abstrac- tion, that the universe may be completely represented, in a positive way, by a point, of no dimensions, (1) moving in a line, and (2) turning or revolving so as to form a closed ring, and at the same time while describing its closed path, (3) ro- tating or twisting 180°, so that its original side A joins tn JSormal continuity the originally opposite side B. In that somewhat abstract model, obviously we need make no real demands, or have any real necessities, as to time and space:- for the length or space of the point is zero, non-existent, or not real; the /ength or space of the closed path may be taken as zero, and the ¢éme of that revolution hence zero; and then obviously as a further truism the rotation will require zero space and time. In short, making the closed path of no length, the ring has become a completely abstract, or zero, point— although still formally or logically a ring, and hence repre- senting formally the three parts of the Trinity. The model contains no *‘actual quantity’’ of space and time; but it does contain the forms of space and time, as we see in the next paragraph. It is obvious that our model, and with it the formal requirements of language, is here reduced to the very “lowest terms.”’ Any further reduction in the form will destroy formal language and give some incomplete language described in §62c. (We have already subtracted the total substance, or Many actuality—and also the One reality, in our everyday usage of considering the One ‘infinite’, al- though in a Buddhistic sense of zero reality, and also obvi- ously in strict logical technicality, One reality remains. ) f. (1) It is obvious that as the point moves in the zero line path it formally does one thing (i. e., that doing or moving in a line constitutes one dimension’? of ‘“space’’—really con- stitutes one dimension’’ or ‘one formal part’ of the One, or of whole reality or the complete ring {see $581], or of be- ing, or existence). (2) When it revolves so as to close on its path and make the path continuous or the One it formally does the second thing (and that revolving more dimension’’ of ‘ constitutes one nore space,’’ giving now ‘‘two dimen- sions.”’ (3) And when it rotates or twists so as to relate those first two contradictory forms, it does the third, and obviously last, formally necessary thing (and that is one more “*dimen- sion,’’ making finally ‘‘three dimensions’ ’), Obvi- ously, no fewer forms will serve. Equally clearly, if any other is added we have taken at least one step on the infinite regress of possible languages (§51h), and we then have not our everyday language, but have a language that is at least 51 UNIVERSE ‘duplicate,’ and hence formally different from ours. Those three forms are the “‘three dimensions of space’’ (for obvi- ously each form was a needed sort of ““motion’’ in a hence formally different aspect of ‘“space’’—i. e., motion and space are formally or logically synonyms). Clearly those three constitute the lowest practical and still positive reduction of the infinite regress ML°7T~°, where M is the “‘thing’’ or that point. The whole of Part Two may be considered (al- though explicitly it is nothing of the sort) to be a description of a point moving in a closed path in that way (§§98m, 104). g. In no casein the last two paragraphs need the formal model occupy actual “‘space,’’ in onr everyday usage of space. We have actually been using the Buddhistic ‘nega- tive’ form of zero-space: for a primitive or original state- ment, such a form is easier to grasp—and for that same general reason or trnism, Buddhism historically preceded Christianity, its equivalent in “‘infinite’’ or ‘positive’ terms, by five centuries, it taking the race that long to grow the few needed nerve connections. So we may now consider the ring (which is still our zero point) to ‘depart’ from that condition, and acquire some ‘room’? or space for the M (now also become “‘actual’’) to move in. The only logical way to get those zeros or abstractions into ‘positiveness,’ or into the other aspect of the One (the infinity aspect) is to multi- ply them by infinity. We then have a “‘solid’’ ring, still indeterminate (i. e., ©) as to the measure of all the space, but containing ““space’’ and time in usnal meaning—though they are obviously merely the same verbal forms as before. Or, the ring now has “‘real’’ length and breadth (and real but negligible thickness—see §$63f for explicit consideration of thickness), and we have the nsna] conventional but arbi- trary space:- for obvionsly, in onr usnal convention of an infinite One, we now have in our model that represents the universe a ‘ length’’ (ete.) that is ‘‘infinite’’ (i. e., continv- ous), and the three forms occnr jnst as before, in, or as, 3-dimension space—a _ trnism. That is the total ‘‘mystery’’ of the three dimensions of space. We are so in the habit of using those briefest, simplest means of talking tbat all parts of our language imply those three dimensions or forms. So when we speak our language, it is a contra- diction—utter verbal nonsense—to say that there is any other number of dimensions: for such an assertion says that “now another language will be talked while we still talk our ordinary one.’’ It can be noted that as soon as I explicitly made the ring of no thickness (of two dimensions) in par. c, I abandoned onr ordinary language, and was talking nonsense with reference to our langnage and said so (even though the language I was using is the language of ‘‘plane’’ geometry, and quite conventional). And when I reduced to zero di- mensions I was very nonsensical. So 1 had to balance or pair off those contradictions to our everyday language, and do it explicitly to be intelligible; and that obviously consisted of really stating our forms (which are the real ‘three dimen- sions’’), and thus actually talking of three forms of zero space—or, I reversed language into Buddhism, that being the reverse of the truism mentioned above. Hence, with those evident truisms, the foregoing proof of the exist- ence and meaning of three dimensions is quite rigorous. That proof is, 1 think, the hardest thing to state and under- stand, in this book. That is becanse it is so obvions. Or- dinarily, we simply say that we ‘‘see’’ that we have to use three dimensions to talk abont things definitely. | And that is substantially all I have said above—only | stated it in de- tail from a different point of view, so that it was possible to see definitely that the matter of dimensions was simply get- ting the fewest parts in a language machine, just as there are three parts in the ‘‘simplest’’ machine, the lever:- load, One VILL §60c power, fulcrum. Also, the foregoing argument is munch easier to see in §62c, where concrete examples are given of languages having other than three dimensions. S60. a. When we start to describe the universe, we take it that there is something (whatever it is) to talk about (§22). When we similarly ‘assume’ (i. e., agree to invent) our ring model, obviously we in the same way, all in a lump take the three sorts of words as being definitely bound to- gether. I introduced no complications, but took the barest agreements:- a contradictory One and Many reconciled by a single or ‘identical’ relationship or invariable twist. | We saw in §57b that in absolute or One meaning (taking the ring as a whole, as we must do to get any final intelligible mean- ing) that relationship between the One and the Many conld be only of one sort, regardless of whether the ring was sym- metrical or asymmetrical. (That is merely a special case of the principle that the One is ineffable.) We also agreed (in §57) that we would consider the actual ring to be perfectly symmetrical, as the means of getting our ordinary language. In this section we see the formal changes in language if we regard the model as being unsymmetrical in various ways. There are an indefinite number of quantitative ways in which it can be asymmetrical, each of which gives a different formal language, although every such langnage means the same as a whole. Those changes in form are conventionally said to be different sorts of ““space’’—‘“‘eurved’’ or non-Euclidian. b. We considered the ring to be symmetrical because that gave the simplest, average sort of language; i. e.,if we take any part of the ring, or unit of the Many, such as Zi];-Zel2, we may nameit 2,andthen—7f the ring stays sym- metrical,—regardless of the relative position of 2 (regardless of how we slip the ring around when hanging over the finger and thus changing the place of 2—regardless of where 2 is in the universe) that 2 remains formally or lingually the same; its relationships or L and T, with respect to the whole ring stay steady, or are average all the time formally; or the de- gree of twist and warp does not change. But if the ring is not considered symmetrical that part is obviously not warped in an average way (so that it does not take a proportionally av- erage share of the whole 180° twist); consequently, if we write for 2 its full general name M(varying with)L?T ~, the Land T of its name are always varying or varied Just in mere form. The reader possibly can not yet grasp that condensed statement—can not see Just what happens to language when the form of the language, or what we have called relation- ships or L and JT measures of units of the Many, (1) varies all the time, or (2) departs or is varied from the average in Euclidian space, and hence, fora given non-Euclidian space, has a ‘steady curvature.’’ The relativitists make L and T always vary—technically over all quantitative degrees of non-Euclidian and the average Euclidian spaces (866). And as neither the relativitists nor non-Euclidians grasp the ulti- mate meaning of what they do to Zand T there is in exist- ence considerable strange, weird, esoteric doctrine which tends to have the same hypnotically benumbing effect npon the brains of the authors and some of their hearers that the logically precisely analogous weirdly nonsensical incantations of ancient medicine men or priests had on themselves and most of their hearers. Both tend to superstition—fear of the fancied unknown. Such hypnotic deadening or fear in some degree precludes seeing things as they are, and hence prevents men from being as alive as possible. Soit is of value to investigate those possible variations in language, espec- ially as doing so further shows possibilities which may be of some use. For those languages are not “‘wrong.”’ ec. Some mathematicians substantially claim that there is no proof’’ that our ring can ever be symmetrical in any §60c VIII One portion; so that if we use Many words the same words (or forms) because of such lack of proof, by the theory of proba- bilities constantly mean something else, and that therefore if we use relationship words there is no continuous identity of relationship anywhere (i. e., in any finite space and time ——meaning that those mathematicians assert ignorance as to the sum total of relationship). | Again such a general con- densation is possibly not quite clear to the reader. The statement is equivalent to the orthodox claim that there is no ‘‘proof’’ of one of Euclid’s “‘axioms’’ or postulates (but ought to be, if it is used):- Euclid defines parallel] lines as straight lines which, being in the same plane and produced indefinitely in both directions, do not meet. And the postu- late, in common form, is:- through a given point not on a straight line, one straight line, and but one, can be drawn which is parallel to the given line [I give the proof of that postulate in par. i]. The mathematicians say that in the ab- sence of ‘‘proof’’ of that postulate, there are two general sorts of possibilities:- (1) It can be assumed that every straight line through the point [and in the same plane, of course] will cut the other line. That gives Riemannian or ‘elliptic’? space-——Riemannian ““geometry”’ {or really a new space language]. It is equivalent to saying that our bound- aries Z,]:-Zele of 2’ vary in such a way as regards their distance apart that the L (and T) between Z]; and Zel2 at some point becomes absolutely zero—or any such word or possibility of such word as 2 disappears: we shal] not exam- ine the details of the new language that results; in general, the Many word ‘2,’ or M in M(varying with)L?T ~, would vary in a way not conceived in our average language. (2) Or, it can be considered that two lines (including some angle between themselves which can contain an infinite number of other lines) can be drawn which are both ‘‘parallel’’ to the given line, in that they do not meet it, so that those two lines form the limits of the infinite number of other lines lying between them that also do not cut’ the given line. That is Lobatchevskian or “‘hyperbolic’’ space and geometry. It says that in our ‘2’ or M represented by Zy1\-Zele, Zelg may be two intersecting lines which do not ever cut Z];, so that there are really an infinite number of parts or Af’s all of which are named 2. Well; we can make a language of that sort if we like; again I shall not go into the details, but below we see the general implications as to such new languages. The Euclidian or ordinary geometry considers space as ‘‘flat’’ or “‘straight’’ or average (i. e., there is one set of two parallel ZI’s which formally fix the 2 with a steady or fixed or “‘straight’?’—i. e., undevi- ating—space, or really form); the other two sorts have ‘‘curved’’ space—i. e., are two languages where the forms or ways of naming depart or deviate from the average: one on either side of the average. For a somewhat technical orthodox account of such spaces see ““Ency. Brit.,’’ xi, 724 to 735 (in Art. “‘Geometry); or for a good popular account, see ‘Science History of the Universe’? (New York, 1909), viii, 143-52 (in the same volume is a more technical account —pp. 230-36—by Keyser, aleading mathematician). Those accounts are not really intelligible unless something be added to them (as we shall see). Consequently the reader need not worry if he has failed to understand the condensa- tions of them which I made in the first part of this paragraph. We shall now begin with the fundamental orthodox assertions abont those curved spaces, and get at their real meaning. d. The same Art. “‘Geometry’’ (pp. 730, 733) states that there is an unreconciled controversy about space, it be- ing shown substantially (on p. 730) that space is considered (1) as the One, (2) as the Many (i. e., in the paragraph ‘*Axioms’’:- a space ““known only from experience’’—as UNIVERSE 52 contrasted with ‘‘a priori’? or One space-—is obviously a Many word), and (3) as relationship. [Tt therefore follows that orthodox geometry would tend to mix the three forms of space—not meeting the fundamental logical necessity of distinguishing apart the three: it does rather mix them in the article I am quoting from.] Then it is shown that a valid geometry [or what we have been calling a valid logic or language machine] is merely one that is self-consistent, regardless of what arbitrary agreements are made. And two general sorts of valid geometry are distinguished :- (1) ‘In projective geometry any two straight lines in a plane inter- sect, and the straight lines are closed series which return into themselves, like the circumference of a circle’’ ligvecpca *“straight’’ line is a string or series of points that have a closed path: that is Riemannian or elliptic geometry ]. (2) “In descriptive geometry two straight lines in a plane do not necessarily intersect, and a straight line is an open series without beginning or end. Ordinary Euclid- ian geometry is a descriptive geometry: it becomes a pro- jective geometry when the so-called ‘points-at-infinity’ are added.’’ [That is Lobatchevskian or hyperbolic geometry; and it is more rigorous to say instead of that, that Euclidian geometry is the average geometry that is the limit of (1) and (2)—the geometry that lies just between the two. ] e. We now come to the illuminating facts regarding those orthodox sorts of geometries~—stil] quoting from the same place:- Projective geometry is developed from “‘two undefined fundamental ideas, namely, that of a ‘point’ and that of a ‘straight line.’’’ | Descriptive geometry is devel- oped from two undefined ““fundamental ideas, namely, of points and segments.’’ — ) earth. Then, speaking ? —_--—> sy ot ‘ : ee ee — roughly, the relative motion E of the earth about the sun Fig. 108a. is equivalent to a flow of ether between them, if we consider them fixed. Or, the result is the same as if there were a pipe, represented by the dotted lines, with the earth and sun contracting the flow of ether as shown. Hence, by the mechanics of this chapter there would be a lower pressure of the ether fluid against E and S in the space be- tween them. _As the ether is indefinitely extensive, and the dotted lines of the pipe are merely formal surfaces with equal pressure on each side, then that less pressure between S and E is equivalent to attraction. That attraction is gravity. b. That is the total of conventional gravity. For actual gravity we have to be somewhat more precise, and not stop thus with E and § tacitly rigid One bodies, and with the explanation concealing a considerable collection of zeros and infinities. In short, ] have tacitly expressed That... < This... by SXE (without dots); to be consistent, and reasonably accurate, we need to include dots. But when we do, gravity is no longer separable from other phenomena ($134)). ce. That inclusion of dots is accomplished by definitely considering the actual fact, thatif E and S were (1) regarded as simply two cells they would still in that elementary form be elastic, so that the difference of pressure at the contrac- tion would modify their size and bence in infinite regress modify the resulting contraction and hence the “‘force’’ of gravity. Or, (2) if E and-S were actual collections of whirls then each would have what we shall see is a field ($1148); and those two fields would react on each other, and theory cally be or give precisely the same modifications as in (1), in infinite regress. And the observed facts are that E and 5 do have magnetic fields, and that the pull of gravity is 113 UNIVERSE not absolutely steady or static (not exactly according to the inverse square law; IX). Therefore, both by direct theory and direct observation, there is some gravity attraction be- tween E and S and some chemical (or electrical, or ‘field,’ or whatever it is preferred to call it) attraction or union between them. And obviously, it is impossible to say that there is a real distinction between the two “‘sorts’’ of attraction (ex- plicitly, the attractions are in infinite regress); each is what we cal] irrational if asserted alone. Hence, we rigorously have W... A... (874), or inexplicitly, S...XE.... Or, the problem of any two actual or experimental bodies is in- soluble (§83). Or, there is no exact science. 8104. a. In this section I shall directly unify the fore- going mechanics with conventional mathematical science, and with the measuring theory in 1X. That is the sum of the book from a particular point of view, and so I have to con- dense; the section can become obvious in detail] only to those readers who follow out the thought from the hints given. This aspect of the subject is so extensive that I have followed the suggested steps only a little way in preparing for this book, and had to write a volume or two to express that much. The general reader has perhaps forgotten what he read in his physics textbooks so thoroughly that he will have slight interest in, or recognition of, what is here condensed to dry bones. If so, a casual, careless reading will give him the essentials and be less boring. b. We have seen (§§80h, 82) that any “‘perfect’’ part of the universe (such as pu—=Constant) is symbolized by a rectangular hyperbola. For instance, if in the actual total Fig. 104b. universe the sun and earth were an absolutely separable per- fect gas part, then SXE (without dots; §103b) would be represented in Fig 104b by the rectangular hyperbola CBD (including the third quadrant branch C3BsD3) in which the general point B represents S and E. Clearly therefore, in order that the geometrical hyperbola may accurately repre- sent bodies, the bodies must, as a truism, be reduced to geo- metrical point masses, of which there would be an infinity, so that the universe would be validly represented by an in- finity of such hyperbolas, and infinite pluralism would form- ally be considered reality. In that case it is obvious that the only way to represent azy phenomenon with logical Two XI §104¢ consistency would be to travel on the hyperbola representing conditions at the beginning of the phenomenon to the asym- ptotes (i. e., revert to monism, or mystic 0-@), and shift on those to the hyperbola or hyperbolas of the conditions resulting (and for intermediate steps of the phenomenon an indefinite number of those curves would have to be considered similarly used). Now, if Carnot’s perfect heat engine, or any perfect gas, or Newton’s gravity, or any absolute constants, or any exact cycles be asserted, obviously such a geometrical representation of them is consistent and valid. But, it is equally obvious that such a representation is actually an ad infinitum affair or regress, and in so far as it is explicit is mys- tic or religious language; it formally and largely explicitly is the old Maxwell science and is also identical with the meta- physics of Hegel, which 1 understand he admitted was un- intelligible to himself; it is obviously mystic language which is the opposite of Many language and to the usual tacit valid logic and commonsense used by science. I. e., every one of the bodies B is in every explicit expression (every actual curve) a perfect universe of itself. In metaphysical terms, each perfect curve is Kant’s ““thing in itself’’—and most other older dualistic philosophers had a pet name for it. Maxwell’s pet name for it was molecule or atom; that infinite collection of hyperbolas is equivalent to Maxwell’s kinetic theory (except that I am finishing it here); for clearly, the actual working together of the parts of the total universe is merely implied—the describer of phenomena reverted to One language (went into a verbal trance, so to speak) and_ said God worked them—moving in a mysterious way his wonders to perform. It is quite true; the universe did do them: but science proposes to say positively how it did. Obviously, so far as positive explicit expression of phenomena is concerned, that old kinetic theory—and similarly al] dualism, including classical logic and orthodox theology—makes no statement whatever of how or why or where such a universe or God works. Or what amounts to identically the same thing, it is glaringly obvious that those old doctrines provided no struct- ure, no real mechanism, no actual relationship (such as love), no working together, no binding together which 7s religion— provided none of that in any explicit way; but in geometric expression, left it all to the asymptotes at a 0-point at ©. Well; as is obvious, such doctrines are right ulti- mately, provided we dig out their implications as was done for classic logic (§24). Unquestionably that tacit taking for granted of relationship is the entirely valid religion which animals, ete., correctly hold; I remember that as a child ] took such a tacit religion for granted and wondered why peo- ple invented a God when all things worked beautifully and justly right before their eyes. The only valid objection that can be made to those dualistic, perfectly kinetic, orthodox theological doctrines is that they merely fail actually and positively to use the language tool; they stop before they finish and then get into a stew because their God is as empty as those asymptotes. Such doctrines obviously pretend or seem to use language, whereas in actual effect they are using formless interjections, like the clucks of a hen. c. But if we use as B any actual body (a finite Many part of our usual Trinity language), then the body does not stay on the perfect hyperbola. If we use Van der Waals’s partially corrected equation, which is a cubic equation, the body takes a swerve at some place (Daniell’s ‘‘Physics,’’ 376) and the body apparently usually has two imaginary values (see par. i). Richards’s form of the equation, or our That... X This..., or the S... XE... of the last section, obviously makes the hyperbola become a continuously changing line of infinite length, which is the single closed line we saw repre- senting the universe in So98m. Hence, any phenomenon is §104c XI Two represented by an actual portion of that universe line. But no phenomenon can be accurately described; only by sum- ming it into the One do we get accuracy, and then it is formal and mystic and sums as being the asymptotes, which directly represent the One. d. Also, although I shall not go into it explicitly, this hyperbola model is being given in two dimensions, with the third only implied. | We must add the third, and consider 3-dimension curves in order to be completely explicit. This modification applies to this whole section. e. If a symmetrical single surface ring of no thickness and infinite width be revolved, this hyperbola will always be related to the generatrix in ways suggesting mathematical laws, including the- inverse square law—and also the non- Euclidian geometries (by having the generatrix vary from a straight line) and z-dimension space (by extending or “dupli- cating’ the curve beyond the point where it touches the asymptotes—as in orthodox projective geometry). f. Suppose we take a formally infinite or One filament (as in §100df) in which the surface is a geometrical surface of zero or infinite velocity. Then suppose we change the filament so that it comes just inside those One limits, its val- ues becoming finite. Then the motion in its surface becomes helical with pitch angle different from 0° or 90°, but ap- proximately one or the other. Then a line of no force would be normal to those spirals, and approximately in the surface (we may take itso, omitting considering its other dimensions). The projection of any such line on any plane through the main axis would be (approximately, by valid logic; exactly, by classic) our hyperbola—which is a line of no resistance. But that line is at right angles to the line of no resistance of S98m. So we see by this geometry how the inverse square law comes in. This paragraph is condensed far be- low the point tolerated by mathematical precision. g. The last paragraph is another form by which par. b can be proved (and understood, if you have the patience and professional need to dig out the implicit truisms in the last paragraph). Incidentally, use of explicit logical expression in the last paragraph would make the One ‘line’ of no action definitely 3-dimensioned, so that the two ‘lines’ mentioned would be ultimately closed on themselves and identical. h. Also, by explicitly and with pluralistic consistency shifting from that One filament to actual or finite ones, we get the actual universe line of par. c again. The hyperbola of par. f is obviously simply the /imit or envelope of that act- ual line. So from that point of view all of Carnot’s theory and of old kinetic and cyclic theory can be seen to be only limiting statements of actuality, and not actuality at all ac- cording to ordinary language. That covers the whole theory of calculus, and most of physical mathematics. Jf it be un- derstood that each such dualistic or classic equation is summed perfection or absolute abstraction from our actual world, and hence (1) is actually inaccurate; and (2) is formally sepa- rated from all others, so that logically explicitly there can not possibly be any such thing as what is actually meant by ex- planation, or knowledge, or continuity—if that be under- stood or implicitly accepted, then even the mathematics of Maxwell is correct. And science nowadays does implicitly accept those things, as shown in the next paragraph. i. As noticed (par. c), Van der Waals’s equation makes a swerve (usually), giving two imaginary roots. Obviously, therefore, those imaginary or logically absurd values result when the actual observed curve, by everyday language leaves that One hyperbolic curve and exhibits at least two of the actual dots of 8... XE... or p... Xv...—and hence does con- tradict the classic logic it started with. So it is further tru- istic that the swerve in Van der Waals’s curve is equivalent UNIVERSE 114 to the inverse square law (cf. pars. e-g), or to the principle of Ampere’s law. And Van der Waals himself substantially asserts that, when he says that the modification of the exact pv is due to a variable extension or ““field’’ of the bodies— which are molecules (““Ency. Brit.,’’ vi, 846). Richards’s theory makes all that explicit. Therefore, vaporiza- tion or melting or disassociation (etc., in infinite regress) lines in pv curves (or in any curve of the general That... X This...) are actually the verbal inverse square Jaw; or ex- plicitly represent (never accurately) the 3-dimension differ- ence surfaces of field and-or filament. Or, they are the explicit geometrical model (or equational) representation of the formation of whirls of a different order (cf. Reeve’s ‘‘En- ergy’’). Or, Van der Waals’s “imaginary states’’ merely mean that the M’s talked of become something else, that are not of the same order or ‘‘state.”’ j. The last thing to be definitely suggested about this sort of averaged or summed or ¢- form of model of the uni- verse, is that it shows that we may reverse the direction of naming of any quantity—i. e., that our location of the zero potential of any phenomenon is purely arbitrary. Ordinarily we fancy—without really thinking—that we name _ things which would be represented in the first (trigonometric) quad- rant as algebraically positive, and that all potentials are taken so that such positive trigonometrical] directions increase them numerically. But it may be readily seen that even science, with its more careful speech, does not thus consistently name potentials:- Ordinarily, with reference to molar bodies, the extensive factors F, W, Ent, and Q, and their respectively corresponding intensive factors L, A, Temp, and P, are named positively, as indicated in Fig. 104b. But p is a force which usually is named as acting oppositely to F; so a con- ventionally positive p is in the direction of OY’, and p... X v... is in the second quadrant— giving the conjugate hyper- bola, or a language from a different viewpoint. Also, when conventional science shifts from molar translatory mo- tion to vibrations the point of view changes from out to in (or vice versa, if yon prefer to look at it that way), and the direction-naming shifts from the usual branch in the first quadrant to the branch in the third. Hence, when Rey- nolds substantially begins by considering vibrations as real or positive sort of motion his whole nomenclature of molar bod- ies practically reverses from custom. But his vibratory mo- tions are consistent with the customary naming of vibratory directions, because conventional science is capsized in its language referring to them. Therefore, here in brief is the general theory of potential directions. I omit the several volumes needed to treat the matter adequately. k. So this section is a summary of the mathematical as- pect of the That... < This... member; mathematics, or ‘“seometry. ts repetition of IX, which gave the of the measuring member.) 1 have merely very roughly suggested its possibilities. I have not gone far enough into them to be very definite about them; but the mathematical physicists will have no difficulty in seeing that even this ele- mentary discussion unifies their equations. There is no fur- ther mathematical discussion in this book beyond occasional brief reference; this section is not actually mathematical, but only implies mathematics—as does the phrase ““Good morning.’’ Such a large proportion of all orthodox mathe- matics is infected with classic logic that it is a sort of neces- sary evil that we have to endure, to refer to such mathematics at all, The reason ordinary mathematics are so excessively boresome and offensive is that they are so wrong and mean- ingless (cf. §30¢). Consequently, they are not a pleasant topic for discussion, just as bad health is not usually a pleasing it becomes xaming (Obviously, it is a general ce = 393 * algebraic’ mathematics 115 subject. Hereafter, I mostly use the That... X This... di- rectly—usually asthe explicit machine Field... X Filament..., or some duplication of it, as Those whirls or cells... X These... . CHAPTER XII. 8105. a. It was shown in general in §100 (especially in pars. be) that the practical way we had of using the form That... X This... was to split the universe into parts on the criterion V;. Parts of our skin (including our eyes, which are physiologically parts of the skin; ‘‘Ency. Brit.,’’ x, 93) are used as standard parts; and that fixes all other parts with quantitatively a corresponding variation of limits (be- cause the skin itself is variable). That actual standard makes atoms the primary order of whirls, as atoms are the skin structures, with a velocity V, of difference surface (see XIII), so that other different-order structures have different, but proportionally related, velocities. All “‘things’’ in the universe are therefore in practice compared with that stand- ard or ‘primary’; e. g., our nervous activity or ‘‘thought’’ is (in this “‘materialistic’’-seeming phraseology) directly such atoms (XVII). ‘The first “‘higher’’ or superorder of bodies is molar bodies—such as the skin itself, or any arbi- trary part of it, as the eyes or nervous system; or such as a house, a man, the earth, the sun. Conventional science gets from the atomic order to the first super- or molar order by means of the kinetic theory—by making the atoms dynamic- ally fly around in 3-dimension space in order to produce a static molar body. And conventional science, in full agree- ment with the logic of this paragraph, finds that if the whole of a body has /;, its mass theoretically becomes _ infinite. I. e., the old Maxwell kinetic science has just two actual ord- ers of structure; the experimental introduction of the elec- tron, which is the first infraorder, thus promptly threw that theory into mysticism. b. We have seen that such a passing from one order to auother order logically implied an infinity of orders. Mod- ern orthodox science is in logical agreement with that. We have made a verbal form or machine in which by using the inverse square law we make the step from order to order. (Aud this is an important point:- because the conventional kinetic theory is logically one such step, it is clear that that theory is nothing but a verbal form which definitely «implies that inverse square in a negative fashion in its fundamental formula, $mv?.) And we have also devised a “ concrete’’ machine by which definitely objectively to make the step:- a whirl, or any of the indefinite number of machines to which it is equivalent. The old Maxwell dualistic kinetic theory is uot a machine at all, but a poetic adumbration of a machine. c. Therefore, we combine molar bodies into a next higher order, and get a solar system. The combination of solar systems into a higher order gives a stellar galaxy. And a combination of stellar galaxies gives a higher order for which there is no conventional name, but which becomes definitely identical with combinations of atoms into various molar hodies. Ete. According to such naming, molecules are molar bodies. The final truth is that those ““orders’’ are not sharply distinct from each other ($8101), 40); sol deliberately leave out molecules as an order, to emphasize that. A molecule is a transition stage from atomic order to molar order—sometimes a large atom and sometimes asmall molar body. There is no such thing as a fixed *“ele- ment’”’ or absolute atom. All other orders have ‘transition’ stages: the inverse square law never names actual bodies per- fectly. And proceeding in the other direction of orders from atoms, we get electrons, parts of electrons, etc., Astronomy. UNIVERSE Two XII §106b on ‘down’’ to cells. (Between atoms and electrons are vari- ous transition stages which are directly experimentally per- ceptible in radioactive phenomena.) It has been seen in principle that there is no essential difference between these orders—only a quantitative, or Land Zone. We are now ready to see, by directly observing the various orders, that they are essentially identical. By doing that we get some useful results. Those results are roughly anticipated in the remainder of this section, so that the reader may know what to be looking for. d. By observing the various orders of whirls, and seeing that they are qualitatively equal or identical, but truistically never quantitatively equal, we shall get a rigorous, intellig- ible proof and knowledge that men, as well as other things, are qualitatively identical and equal, but never quantitatively equal. J. e., it is absolutely impossible, and practically and theoretically irrational, to average men or anything else into FIXED classes. All of classic logic, orthodox theology, social- ism, al] the Maxwell kinetic pseudo-science try to assert the dualism that men are fixed in classes—that some are in- trinsically “‘better’’? than others. They all try to impose upon men hierarchies, autocracy, socialism, or some other sort of “‘line’’ or bureaucratic rule like the German in 1914 or the papacy, in opposition to democracy (XIX). We shall see that all those conventional dualisms are irrational by seeing that in the whole universe there does not and can not exist any essential or qualitative distinction in order—no fixed classes—no exact science. On the other hand, quantitatively no two men, no two atoms, no two of any actual things are ever equal (i. e., in size, or measure, or amount, or practical or Many zeeds or worth. I stated above that orthodox theologies arranged men in classes. As the truth of that may not be immediately obvious, | state it explicity:- So far as I can find, all those theologies technically assert that their God, or each of their Gods, is a person who is superior to, or essentially better than, other persons or men. That truistically gives at least two fixed (or “‘line’’ or military or bureaucratic or aristocratic) classes:- (1) men; (2) God. And that is irrational. This book demonstrates that man is God—that God or the universe is quantitatively different from any given man as conventionally specified (i. e., ‘skin- bounded’), but that God is in no essentials different. e. Wecan see the solar system, comets, etc., in more detail than we can see atoms. A comet, e. g., as is shown, is an electron of the solar-system-considered-an-atom. So from several points of view we may learn more about atoms by observing the solar system, etc., than by observing atoms. f. Also, as we have a consistent mechanics, we may, by investigating such ““higher’’ order whirls that are easy to see directly, get a thorough base for human phenomena— ‘life’’ becomes easily comprehensible (XVI). §106. a. Therefore, because it makes no essential dif- ference what order of whirls we use as a means of acquiring a full understanding of our immediate environment, we may without inconsistency employ such whirls as give us direct quantitative details. The so-called astronomical or celestial whirls seem to do that best to begin with. Those whirls ex- hibit all phenomena directly, as we shall see. But I arbi- trarily reserve light, electricity, etc., for other chapters. b. Many of the quantitative details which we observe have not yet been measured very definitely. So it is obvious that I shall have to make rough guesses at some we need. It is inevitable that there must be quantitative inaccuracy in my description; but it is most probable that that inaccu- racy exists in such a degree that some important and useful phenomena are made vague. I can hope only to be logically consistent. §106c XIl Two UNIVERSE 116 c. It may seem at first thought that there is no need to guess at anything—that such guessing is not science. The general reply to that is obviously that there can not be any exact science (§40). The practical reply to it is that we are forced, as a means of continuing to live atall, to guess at the characters or “‘properties’’—measures—of the people and things about us. Every time we eat anything we in effect guess at the motives and properties and attributes of the per- sons who were perceptibly concerned in the production of it —e.g.,as to whether they wished to poison us. The incom- plete physics or other sciences and theologies in textbooks furnish us with no definite or consistently expressed basis or criterion for making such guesses. We have been going through life without any consistent conscious basis of estimat- ing or judging or guessing at the majority of the important decisions which we actually do make. The universe or God takes care of us, by it as a whole causing us to make fairly correct guesses intuitively (i. e., with very vague conscious- ness—as we are a part of the universe)—which fact is more or less contrary to the hoary, conceited myth tbat man is a reasoning (i. e., conscious) animal: for only in small part is he conscious in the sense that he thinks or is intelligent. We see the proof of that in Part Three—and how man pays for sucb care by the loss of possible conscious life in some de- gree. At present it may be noted that we do some consist- ent guessing at astronomical quantities as a means of becoming conscious of a consistent basis of making everyday judgments. The more conscious we are of what we are do- ing the more life we are aware of having; e. g., if we are asleep we are unconscious and not aware of having any life. Hence, as real science can do nothing else but guess, it is honest to admit it, and then proceed consciously to guess. That does not mean that ] am rashly abandoning observations and measures; actually, I am doing much less guessing than does an astronomer who doesn’t know the principles. $107. a. Astronomers seem to agree rather generally that our stellar galaxy is a nebula; see Hink’s ““Astronomy,’’ Arrhenius’s “*Destiny of the Stars,’’ etc. **The Encyclo- paedia Brittanica’’ (xix, 332) gives eight arbitrary kinds of nebulas, depending on their genera] appearance :- (1) irregu- lar nebulas, (2) annular, (3) double, (4) planetary, (5) ellip- tical, (6) spiral, (7) nebulous stars, (8) diffused nebulosities. We shall see that nebulas may consistently be considered to be whirls. In that case those descriptive names correctly describe whirls seen from various points of view, and in vari- ous stages of growth or of wearing out. EE. g., an irregular nebula, of which the great nebula in Orion is a type (‘‘Ency. Brit.,’’ Art. ‘““Nebula,’’ Plate I) looks very much like a newly formed whirl, with its visible field, in a rather dis- turbed condition; an annular whirl looks like a filament, seen normally; a spiral nebula looks like a filament that has become comparatively stationary as regards traveling in the direction of its main axis, and has given off a number of sec- ondary whirls which hence traveled spirally roughly in the filiar plane (instead of revolving about the filiar axis as in Fig. 98w). We see more such details as we proceed. b. Thereis no definite agreement among astronomers as to what sort of nebula our stellar galaxy is. As we shall see, it probably is a rather flattened-out whirl, so that quite likely it has the spiral appearance if viewed from a neighboring nebula (§108b). However, our solar system is probably comparatively near the center of such a spiral, even though we are not (except in the direction of the Milky Way) per- ceptibly surrounded by nebulosity. I. e., our galaxy is probably shaped like a large double convex Jens—or like a grindstone, to use another conventional simile. That is ex- perimentally shown chiefly by the observed distribution of stars, the appearance of the Milky Way surrounding us as a ring, and by other details mentioned later. In Fig. 107e, DA and BC are cross-sections of a conventionalized or smoothed-out Milky Way or filament. We are near the cen- ter, at S, and around us we see that filament. It probably is smashed somewhat flat by surrounding whirls or galaxy- nebulas of the same order, so that it (the filament or Milky Way) has but comparatively slight motion of translation along the main axis PP’ (say as a guess 100 miles per second, which is very slow for such a whirl), and hence has compara- tively more motion of rotation about that axis (resulting in a spiral motion in the field, not shown in the figure). Our solar system § is in the inner field of the whirl, a little above the filiar plane (for clearness, the figure probably much ex- aggerates its actual distance above), ina dynamic equilibrium with that field—which inclines the ecliptic somewhat to the filiar plane (the ecliptic is the rough plane in which the earth revolves about the sun and which the other planets more or less stay close to; that is not quite the strictly technical definition, ‘“Ency. Brit.,’’ ‘‘Ecliptic’’; the inclined azis of the ecliptic is roughly NS’), and which equilibrium also in- volves the revolution of the whole solar system about the stellar main axis PP’, as we shall see. ce. Our galaxy is equivalent to an atom in everything but size (and 7), and that is unessential. It is obviously surrounded by other stellar galaxies. I do notknow whether those galactic atoms constitute a ‘celestial’ gas, or liquid, or solid (perhaps a solid; see par. g). We probably can not see farther than a very few layers of such surrounding atoms: light itself is absorbed by those surroundings (§§131-2), so that comparatively speaking we are probably in the same kind of darkness that we would say existed in the center of a lump of coal (although there would be light there to the parts of coal atoms). Even if our galaxy were an atom of a celestial gas we would have comparatively short vision of surrounding atoms (XIII). d. In technical astronomy the usual unit measure of stellar distance is now a parsec, which is the distance at which the orbit of the earth subtends an angle of 1 second— i. e., gives a ‘‘fixed’’ star a parallax of 1”. It is equal to about 206,000 ‘‘astronomical units.’? An astronomical unit is the average radius of the earth’s orbit, which is about 93,000,000 miles. An older measure of stellar distance is the light year, or the distance which light at V; travels in a year. It is equal to about 4 parsec, or to about 6 trillion miles. I use light years, as that is more familiar. e. There are no agreed upon figures for the size of our galaxy. Eddington (‘‘Stellar Movements,’’ 225) roughly guesses that the distance apart of the inner surfaces of the Milky Way (the diameter of the hole in the ‘doughnut’; or the distance from A to B, Fig. 107e; see par. b for prelimi- nary description of this figure) is about 700 light years. Other men guess considerably higher and also lower. I shall to some extent use Eddington’s guess as a base (although it probably is considerably tuo small), making other figures in proportion. The field of the galaxy in the figure has a dif- ference surface with much inaccuracy represented by the outer dotted line (to save space, etc., one end of figure is cut away). That field probably has a long diameter of something like 20,000 light years, and a short diameter of something like 2000 light years (the diameter along its main axis PP’). f. The Milky Way filament has an ether flow as indi- cated very roughly by the arrows. Hence, in so far as that flow is not balanced by a rotation of the whirl around PP’ and a spiral reaction of the whole whirl] with adjacent whirls (due to the spiral flow of the field ether, which is not indi- cated in the figure), there will be a motion of translation of 117 the galaxy as a whole down, in the direction PP’, as was seen to occur in Fig. 98n (§101d). Although I do not show that spiral flow for the galaxy field in the figure, I show in rough perspective the general spiral translation of the solar system S (by the dotted line on which the various S’s are): the motion down of the galaxy in the direction PP’ would act- ually be a similar corkscrew motion among the surrounding galaxies. g. Astronomers’ observe motions of translation of neb- ulas which are apparently ont- side our galaxy to be as high as 600 or 700 miles a second. Several thousands of spiral nebulas are observed around us. The average motion of snch nebulas is observed to be perhaps 250 miles per second; hence, our nebula possibly corkscrews down at about the same rate (but see par. a). There is not much reliability abont such figures as yet; for nebulas are faint, and are difficnlt to measure even in photo- graphs. But it is already obvious in part, and will become More so as we note more details, that such motions are very slow compared with the size of the objects. I.e., very little change in our galaxy as a whole is produced by that, to ns, rapid motion. Such motions of translation are comparatively speaking almost static conditions; i. e., the collection of galaxy whirls in which onrs is one atom would be, if those velocities are fairly good gnesses, abont as fixed and steady as atoms in what we calla solid. And that possibility that we are in a celestial solid is further strengthened by the fact that observed distances of other galaxy nebulas are roughly of the same order as the size of onrs; i. e., the galaxy whirls about us are packed in as steady as the bricks in a wall—always speaking comparatively, of course (and in spite of the fact that it is conventional to hear of the ‘“enormons’’ “‘waste’’ spaces in astronomical structures). I shall keep on speaking comparatively, and omit repeating the obvions and unimportant and nnessential qnantitative fact that a short astronomical distance is a long terrestrial one. We are cus- tomarily expected to marvel at astronomical figures—espec- ially velocities. The truth is that to anyone with a fair judgment of proportion, astronomical velocities are compara- tively slow. From analogous points of view it is Just as diffi- cult to detect the slow motion of the solar system as it is to detect the slow motion that is the growth ofa plant. So it is to be hoped that the old-style popular writers on astrono- my will stop tacitly inviting that we stand like rustics, with our provincial mouths ajar in wonder, whenever they mention a comparatively negligible number and tell ns that it is mar- velons and stupendons—for relatively it is nothing of the sort. The psychological effect on themselves is obvious. §108. a. The last section gives in rough ontline the de- scription of our galaxy. = All other astronomical structures, as well as atoms, etc., are of the same general nature at the youthful stage of their lives. | Experimental evidence of the consistency of that description is given by the remainder of this chapter. There are such a number of things in the gal- axy, and the changes init are usually so nearly imperceptible to us, so slow are its movements, that the experimental ob- servations and measures are rather unreliable. So we shall mostly use the solar system whirl instead of the galaxy. b. Many astronomers are inclined to consider our galaxy as being a well-developed spiral nebula, with the solar system UNIVERSE Two XIl1 §108c at S, as in Fig. 108b (the figure is adapted from Arrhenins’s “Destiny of the Stars’’; cf. p. 45ff). So far as I know, the galaxy may be considerably broken up, as indicated in that figure ; but I am inclined to think that the Milky Way Fig. 107e. directly appears to be so well-formed as to indicate the better preserved whirl of Fig. 107e. However, as that is not reli- able proof, and as there are no other facts that I know of. to decide the point, what I shall do is to describe onr nebula (including details of the solar system) in a broad way—cov- ering all the probabilities, which are innnmerable. Then, if the astronomers by further and more complete observations of stars as they actually are, find onr galaxy to be of the character shown in Fig. 108b, that will be a special case of our description. My personal guess at the qnan- titative character of onr gal- axy and solar system is that the galaxy is a rather regn- lar spiral that tends towards being an annular nebula, with the solar system rather near the center, as shown in Fig. 107e, which 1 shall call a regular spiral or a whirl spiral. |The spiral shown in Fig. 108b is more like a spiral that would result if two large bodies or clusters pniled each other apart by gravity, and I shall call that a gravity spiral. As we shall see in the next two paragraphs, there can not be essentially different sorts of spirals: the difference is quantitative, and each kind is partly the other kind. ec. I may here briefly anticipate some conclusions, in or- der to state what are the two general kinds of nebnlas into which I arbitrarily divide the eight sorts in §107a. If we had a nearly homogeneons fluid whirl, practically as our ex- perimental whirls may be considered tobe when first formed, or as an ether whirl containing only cells would be, then as we have seen, it wonld wear out or grow old by giving birth to lower order whirls, and those whirls would tend to collect into spherical “‘solids’’ like the earth. We shall see that in detail later. (1) During the process of wearing out, that fluid whirl, if rather closely surrounded by whirls of the same order, would be what was called a regular or whirl spi- ral. Or, some large secondary of the whirl, surrounded by other secondaries, wonld pass through the stages of snch a rather regular whirl or spiral. Or, finally, if two rather fluid whirls combined (as in §102f), the resulting single whirl, if surrounded by others of the same order, would pass through the stages of a whirl spiral—as shown in one stage in Fig. 107e. But on the other hand, a whirl, which had wa Cowes a" % iy, $ rte x = > YW Win, Me % % y if ‘ty y * Z % Fig. 108b. §108e XII Two reversed or aged or ‘ degenerated’’ into a spherical solid like the earth (with usually one or more solid satellites like the moon), might approach fairly close to another similar whirl. (That would be possible because the field of that solid would be comparatively weak, as we shall see. I do not think that such approach is often probable, but I do not know the quantitative chances: cf. the remainder of this chapter.) In that ease the two solid whirls (never perfectly “solid’—always there would be some sort of ‘atmosphere’ of satellites, etc.) would combine by pulling each other to pieces. Some of the pieces would probably stay rather “‘solid’’; most of the pieces, for reasons which we shall see, would ‘evaporate’ into ether—i. e., break up into pieces as sma)]] as electrons, etc. The resulting single whirl would be what I call a gravity spi- ral nebula (because ordinary gravity was the major force pro- ducing the result), That whirl would become, more or less quickly, practically identical with a fairly aged fluid whirl. At some age of each sort of whirl or nebula they can not be distinguished apart. The differences occur in their youths. So the differences in the nebulas are quantitative differences of past history. That history determines the kind of spiral. d. We could say that the rather fluid regular whir) is chiefly dynamic, and that the rather solid sphere is chiefly static, and we have the same quantitative distinction. As before, it obviously is not possible to have in any pluralism a perfect fluid, or a perfect solid. That is equivalent to what we saw in $80 concerning no perfect static or perfect dy- namic phenomena: we see here in general that there can be no essentially different kinds of nebulas. And we shal] see that that is equivalent to saying that there can neither he any gravity alone, nor chemical affinity alone; both act to- gether in astronomical structures, sometimes one and some- times the other temporarily having the greater effect (IX). e. Ina fluid or whirl spiral, in the stage pictured in Fig. 107e, chemical affinity has perhaps the greatest influence with respect to the whole whirl. Inside our solar system as it is now, gravity has the greater influence with reference tothe larger bodies in it, or with respect to the whole whirl. As is now rather well known, the efficacy of gravity pull has in the past been considerably exaggerated. The orthodox nebular theory of Kant and Laplace (‘“‘Ency. Brit.,’’ Art. *‘Nebular Theory’’) substantially makes gravity the whole (i. e., infinite) cause—which obviously is correct as relig- ion, but is pure nonsense if claimed to be expression in plu- ralistic or scientific everyday language. Because gravity pull has been conventionally so much overemphasized I am here more or less forced to make a somewhat dispropor- tionate amount of remarks about its completing factor, chemi- cal affinity (or electric or magnetic forces, as they are more usually called in this connection). The reader will note that rhetorical result, needed temporarily now. S109. a. We may briefly consider the general origin of the galaxy, although it will merely be a ‘‘concrete’’ repeti- tion of the previous proofs (X, XI) that any splitting of the universe into parts implies, by our Trinity Janguage, a struct- ure. If we like, we may commence with a perfectly fluid ether universe—perfectly static or perfectly dynamic,—and existing as anything, or nothing, just as you please. If we consider it pluralistically split in any way, then by our usual language we introduce time and space as methods of naming the results, and the results are finally atoms, which by our human criterion have difference surfaces at ’;. Some par- ticular order of those whirls in infinite regress would contain a particular whirl which is our galaxy. Its existence implies us, with our V; criterion; and our existence with that cri- terion implies that whirl. Like the chicken and the egg, neither comes “‘first,’’ except by purely arbitrary agreement UNIVERSE 118 as to what is precisely quantitatively a chicken, and what an egg; and that agreement can not be made exactly in a finite number of words. So ultimately the chicken and the egg are identically the same (and we and the galaxy are identi- cally the same), and are the universe. Like Topsy in **Uncle Tom’s Cabin,’’ the galaxy whirl ‘just grew.’ This paragraph consistently states what grew ultimately means (§35f). b. Topsy was expected to state her immediate parents —to talk in finite, Many terms. So we too may drop that tacit infinite time of the last paragraph, and undertake to state the finite origin or parentage of our galaxy whirl. I am unable to find any observed data which will give that parentage. Or, the whirl may not have had ‘parentage,’ but may be the result of a marriage or joining of two large spherical ‘solids’ (those ‘solids,’ with their satellites, are us- ually called star clusters or systems) which had previously been born perhaps. I. e., our galaxy whirl (1) may bea secondary of some larger whirl (an electron of that larger atom); or it (2) may be that (A) two large suns, or (B) two clusters that were not so far condensed into mostly only two such suns, or (C) two more fluid whirls, united to make it. ec. Both those general possibilities could produce our galaxy whirl. Obviously, our machine is in principle per- fectly reversible—going equally well “‘down’’ or “‘up’’ in order of whirls. All we need to note is that whatever the actual origin was, the primary whirl that gave off the new secondary, or the old whirls which united to form a new one, was or were partly fluid and partly solid, so that there was at all times no perfect characteristic or property (no ‘egg’ that was essentially and absolutely egg and nothing else), and no absolute homogeneity or heterogeneity of any sort. (We shall see that those same processes apply precisely to the birth of biological organisms; 8146). It may be observed that this investigation of the origin of our galaxy is perfectly general in principle. | Consequently, it will apply as the description of the origin of any structural part of the universe:- toa chicken and an egg, atoms, electrons, etc. ; it will apply to (say) chairs, provided that the man and his tools and materials which produce the chairs are considered as partly joined together during a given time—as they are. d. If we tentatively accept the guess in §107b that the galaxy and the solar system are both roughly whirl spirals, then a fairly reasonable guess as to the age of our galaxy would make it as a minimum a trillion of onr years (10!2 years; I use the American and French style of numeration); the solar system would as a reasonable minimum be a number of billion years old (say 50 hillion), counting from its first rough splitting off from the Milky Way filament. However, both might be a million or more times older than that, as we see later. Possibly the astronomers may readily find data which will give more definite guesses at the ages. If the galaxy is a gravity spiral, then I am unable to find any rea- sonable basis for a guess, except that by geological observa- tions the solar system must be a numher of billion years old; as will implicitly appear, the galaxy must be older. S110. a. We shall begin to get more explicit proof of the last two sections by considering the birth and history of the (our) solar system. Suppose we have the galaxy filament (the Milky Way) somewhat as shown in sectionin Fig. 107e. The difference surface would be continually subjected to varying velocities (equivalent to pushes and pulls) from inside and outside the filament—every phenomenon that happened in the universe would in time be registered thus on the gal- axy difference surface. Any push and any pull would form a whirl in more or less completeness (§§101-2). Those whirls would form in harmonic sizes (or else be quickly destroyed or assimilated’ by sizes which did have such proportionality) : 119 UNIVERSE see Index, “‘Harmonic periodicity.’’ Consequently, the difference surface would continually form whirls of various sizes. The smallest made in considerable number would probably be the new-born forms of our atoms; those which were not in fairly good proportions would be destroyed, but in such disturbed conditions atomic weights would vary widely in several ways from our present weights. For rea- sons and facts we shall see, those atoms of a certain atomic weight or size there, would, if it were possible to transport them to our laboratories without changing them, be consid- erably different from our analogous atoms in every property. I. e., C atoms there would not quantitatively be much like C atoms here; yet the collection of mutual ZL and T relation- ships possessed by the carbon atoms would, relative to each appropriate location, be practically measurably identical (not exactly identical; if exact identity be required, then the names of ‘‘elements’’ promptly require to become an infinity —~as may be readily seen from the fact that any change in conditions changes the spectrum of any ““element’’; XIII). b. The small or atomic whirls would have difference surfaces of a velocity which of itself gives visibility, or nearly so (proof:- we see the Milky Way; also, the rest of this book), That velocity would be of the same order as /; (it differs somewhat, as those atoms are not in an environment like our neighborhood; cf. XIII). The atoms would also in most circumstances be visible by diffusing, reflecting, etc., light that came from atoms in other places that had light- giving difference surfaces. The Milky Way atoms might locally be in sufficiently dense and extensive clouds of them- selves to become dark, if their difference surfaces were not at a visible velocity. But obvionsly, without going into the lengthy details which are implied in XIII on light, we may take a short cut to the conclusion, and see that the chances are that usually there will be enough visible atoms about the Milky Way surface (or the difference surface of any galaxy in our neighborhood, or any large whirl in those whirls) to make the outline of that surface visible to us. We see more of the details and proof of that under zodiacal light (§121), and in §111 and XIII. What we particularly need to get at now is the meaning of the ““‘temperature’’ of those whirls that are new-born at the galaxy difference surface. c. Those new atoms (and other whirls) would have plenty of room-—they could not be rubbing each other hard, but would have well-formed (newly-formed or young) fila- ments, and comparatively extensive fields. If we could stick an ordinary thermometer among them, its expansive sub- stance would almost certainly freeze. For the ‘‘temperature’”’ of the “‘gas’’ which those atoms ordinarily form is almost *‘absolute zero’’ in spite of the fact that they are glowing— *‘slowing hot.’? The temperature of the ether which is the difference surface of the atoms is ‘‘high’’—for its velocity is near V, (if we could get our whole thermometer im that sur- face zone of ether, it theoretically would indicate nearly an “‘infinite’’? temperature: any actual thermometer in the usu- al sense would explode into electrons and smaller pieces). But that ether is obviously very small in amount compared with the ‘insulating’ slower ether of the fields. Our ther- mometer would come into contact with the comparatively very slow difference surface of the fields, and there would be nothing in the rather free environment near the galaxy differ- ence surface to ‘smash’ that high-velocity ether close up to the atoms of our ordinary thermometer and hence the ‘*tem- perature’? would register low. There would be some rad- iant heat; but radiant heat in quantities sufficient to affect the thermometer very perceptibly can come only from a col- lection of considerably smashed together atoms. In brief, to sum up what has been said, the entropy of those Two XII §110e atoms is nearly zero (by our standards) and consequently one of our thermometers, which requires an average entropy of our environment before it will register an average tempera- ture, simply would register almost no temperature of the whole gas. (Asa matter of fact, for reasons later implied, the or- dinary thermometer will itself most probably begin to break up radioactively in such an environment. And precisely the same low temperature will be registered when atoms are very strongly pressed together, with high entropy, as inside the earth; itis the opposite aspect of the wide departure from the average conditions we use as a standard; cf. §§122, 120.) If we devise some method of forcing some of that dif- ference surface ether that is at a ““temperature’’ of nearly ‘infinity’? close up to the atoms of the expansive substance of our thermometer, those atoms will locally radioactively explode, as implied above-—and the exploded atoms wil! then tend again to bave a temperature, relative to the origi- nal thermometer, of nearly zero. d. We are so accustomed to judging heat anthropocen- trically that it is difficult at first even to understand the last paragraph, which (except for the “old heat’ inside the earth) describes ‘young heat’ instead of our everyday “middle-aged heat.’ But it can be seen at once that tbe paragraph is a concrete summary of the theory of heat in §§78-81. As we see additional details of heat below, the last paragraph will become more intelligible. All we need to grasp now is the general fact that temperature is an intensive factor (which means roughly that if we want “‘high’’ temperature, we must get high-speed ether at the spot where there is to be such temperature), and entropy is the extensive factor of heat (which means roughly that there must be an amount of ether which will both build up a properly supporting struct- ure about that point and also maintain the flow to it). e. I have described atomic whirls as being secondaries of the galaxy whirl. There may be snch a relationship of periodic sizes that the galaxy difference surface can not give off such comparatively minute whirls directly as secondaries, but must in the ordinary course of quantitative events give off large secondaries of (say) the order of the solar system, and then have them give off atoms as tertiaries of the galaxy. Or in the same way atoms may be an even lower order of whirl with reference to the galaxy asa primary. If so, it is merely a step by step quantitative process, which makes no essential difference in the brief description we need. For rhetorical simplicity I shal] make the experimentally unguided guess that the galaxy difference surface gives off secondaries that range in sizefrom electrons and atoms to solar system whirls: that is valid in principle (§101h-j). If it is not quantitative fact at a given time, then future closer observation of details and investigation of mechanical size-relationships will show what is so ata given time. But even then, atoms would be formed near (not in or gf—as stated above) the Milky Way surface; and the actual phenomena and subsequent descrip- tion would be quantitatively about the same as that I give, and logically identical. The same general remarks as to the order of whirls will apply usually to my description of them. In short, I can not get enough data to make a reasonably accurate guess as to how many generations there are usually between galaxy and (say) electrons. It is pre- cisely the same as being unable to guess how many genera- tions there were between Darwin and a given one-celled ancestor of his; the actual facts are that by following differ- ent lines of intermarrying ancestors there nearly surely would result different numbers of generations; and also there is no accepted arbitrary agreement as to what does constitute one generation of one-celled organisms. But obviously, with electrons and with Darwin, the essential thing is that there §110e X11 Two are generations and changes of order or “‘species,’’ even though the numbers or measures vary with the point of view. So it is obvious that in the description of all pbenomena I give, infinite variation of quantitative detail is possible, and does occur in varying conditions: there is no exact science. S111. a. Thus we have the galaxy difference surface outlined by atoms. That result happens only when that sur- face is in fairly stable equilibrium. If there were rapid changes in the galaxy whirl as a whole, that outlining would disappear. Our galaxy may move about 250 mi/see (§107g) —and that, though slow, seems to be enough to cause the galaxy field difference surface to clear itself pretty much of secondaries of all sorts, so that the outer field surface is not appreciably outlined (cf. §112a). The same thing has hap- pened to most of the solar system; i. e., its difference sur- faces are nearly imperceptible, except what are now the main difference surfaces of it, such as the surfaces of the sun, planets, etc., as we shall see. Below we see encugh details to make those galaxy phenomena clear. b. And thus the galaxy filament surface continually gave off secondaries into and out of the filament (it still is doing so). We may guess that about 50 billion years ago there was from some cause a knock, or addition of energy, given to the galaxy field, so that a whirl which was to form the solar system was pushed out of the filament at C, Fig. 107e. That unbalanced knock, which was almost negligible compared with the size or energy of the galaxy, reached its fair equilibrium, or was balanced, by the birth of that sec- ondary, the solar whirl, according to the mechanics given for Fig. 98w and in §101e. For severa] reasons which we shall see, the solar system virtually lived faster than the galaxy; also, we can observe it better. | Hence, I shall discuss its general history, and thus imply the further detailed descrip- tion of the galaxy whirl. c. Asareasonable guess the solar whir] would be at least several centuries a-borning, and would, as a fairly sym- metrical whirl like our soapy water whirls, staré traveling out from C to the right (more or Jess in or parallel to the galaxy filiar plane) into and through the outer field of the galaxy at a speed of say 300 to 400 miles per second—probably more. This solar whir] would contain in its field ether a lot of glow- ing atoms, and also quite probably a considerable number of what we may call condensations (§114)—or more explicitly, planetesima] condensations. Also, it would be born into a disturbed environment; its very birth was due to asymme- tries or lacks of equilibrium which locally were comparatively marked. Hence, the solar whirl at once began to form sec- ondaries and wear out (i. e., “‘live’’?) much more rapidly than the larger galaxy whirl] had in general been doing, or does now. ‘The galaxy whirl] is apparently still virtually rather young, while the solar system is virtually middle-aged. In the periodic table (App. B) column 0 (He, Ne, A, etc.) are virtually young atoms; column VIII (Fe, Co, Ni, etc.), virtually old; and column IV (C, Si, ete.), middle-aged, and fairly stable like our earth, which is typically middle- aged, tending to elderly. d. Before proceeding to follow the solar system from that guessed-at beginning, we may note the possible varia- tions in its birth. In the first place, observation seems to indicate a thicker collection of solar systems in the center galaxy field where we are now, than outside (there may be a thick collection in the plane of the Milky Way outside, as at M,N, Fig. 107e: as we shall see, theoretically there is a tendency for such a collection to form, and astronomers with recently improved methods for measuring star distances are rapidly collecting data that will settle this and similar mat- ters). If that apparently thicker collection in the center field UNIVERSE 120 is a fact, it then follows that the galaxy is moving rather steadily and is gaining in speed, so that usually the knocks are negative and the solar whirls are now mostly born into the filament, where by rapid trave] they remain virtually of the same density and are hence retained. A whirl born into the filament would encounter a spiral fluid motion of rotation and hence would revolve chiefly about the filiar axis, and with the galaxy filament would also revolve about the galaxy main axis PP’. That secondary in the Milky Way would it- self revolve and rotate about its own axes, and proceed to condense into a solar system similar to our present one. Those solar systems would then interact, partly by affinity and partly by gravity. | Those general interactions may be fol- lowed through in detail by analogy with what will be said. of the solar system. We on earth are not yet appreciably af- fected by what happens inside the galaxy filament; we prob- ably shal] be so affected some day, as what happens there is likely to be the prelude to the Many end of this astronomical speck, the earth—as will implicitly appear. e. And there could also be anindefinite number of vari- ations as to the relative locality on the filament surface where the solar system was born. Birth at a different place would give quantitatively a different subsequent history—consider- ably different if the birth had occurred at say B, Fig. 107e, instead of at C. Qualitatively, the histories would be the same; all history must repeat itself qualitatively, as all prin- ciples are identical; but no history can repeat itself quanti- tatively exactly (all that being obvious truisms; Part One). So the history given according to the quantitative guesses J have made will implicitly contain al] those unending varia- tions (and those following from other possible origins of the solar system mentioned or implied later), and the interested reader may fairly easily work out as many of such variations as he likes from the following. The most probable place of birth of larger whirls would be on the outer side, as at C and D in the cross-section. Thatis so because obviously the field is least stable there: in all other places the field in greater degree supports itself more steadily. Consequently, any really large whirl would, as a mechanical truism, tend to be born on the outside. As we see in the next paragraph, the same mechanical principle will tend to produce spiral nebulas. However, the solar system is a comparatively smal] whirl; hence, there is no great probability that it was born at C unless it was born (as it may have been; cf. §112d) when the galaxy was quite young. 8112. a. The young solar whirl starts out to the right from C, as seen, and encounters a fairly vigorous upward ether flow in the galaxy field. Consequently (as was seen in §So8w, 10le), it rather soon (say in fifty centuries after it more or less appreciably finishes being born) perceptibly be- gins to move downward along the dotted path as shown in Fig. 107e. Now, if the field had not been relatively vigor- ous (and usually with a somewhat old whirl, or with respect to a large secondary instead of our rather small solar whirl, it relatively is not), then there would not have been enough fairly steady reaction to push (pull) the new-born whirl down along that dotted path. It would have kept in the galaxy filiar plane, with more or less wabbling or oscillation up and down with respect to that plane, depending on the minor asymmetries it encountered. Consequently, it would have steadied into some sort of fairly stable equilibrium while re- maining more or less in the plane, as shown by the whirls M and N. Those whirls theoretically could be tilted in any direction, depending on local conditions, ete. There was in the difference surface from which they were born a component of rotation about the main axis PP’. The second- ary whirl itself would @f its own internal energy continue to 121 propel itself in that revolution about PP’ and for a consider- able time if it were a large whirl; for it would take some time for enough asymmetries tu accumulate to stop its motion in that direction and ““head’’ it some other way. Also, as the secondary traveled out more or less in that galaxy filiar plane it would keep on ‘spilling’ its field (like a comet; §120) until it got into some reasonably steady equilibrium (cf. §111a). And all those results, with a field not relatively vigorous, would obviously produce the observed phenomena and appearances of a fluid spiral nebula—the large second- aries staying more or less in the filiar plane. The small secondaries would proceed as we shall see in the case of the solar whirl. (There would be whirls more or less on the dividing line between those ‘small’ and ‘large’ secondaries, which would produce a variety of intermediate phenomena. ) Also, the large secondary whirls which produce the spirals would, in a considerable length of time (say some hundreds of billion years), condense, and they too would then fall out of that spiral (out of the orbit of revolution arouud PP’) and shoot around the galaxy filament asa comet (analogous to one of our comets; §120) on a path analogous to the one to be described for the solar system. So it will implicitly appear as we proceed thata spiral nebula, by whirl mechanics, will gradually turn into a star cluster. The star cluster, if let alone (if not too much knocked by an asym- metrical environment) until entropy piled up too high, would automatically break up (precisely a does a radioactive atom; §§139, 141) into a largely fluid whirl. Or, two clusters more or less colliding would produce a more or less fluid whirl of the gravity type. The whole process will work in either direction from any stage, and contains infinite possibili- ties. And, as perhaps is already obvious, there is in that process or life never any comparatively explosive or *“quick’’ or ‘‘violent’’ action; relatively speaking, everything always works smoothly and rhythmically and without violence— which means that there is always easily visible continuity, or efficient cause, or least action. If we speak very carefully, anything that may be properly said to be violent or explosive refers to a comparison between different orders of whirls; if in such comparisons we explicitly include the inverse square, verbally even then no violence or catastrophe is apparent. b. As the solar whirl traveled (Fig. 107e), the steadily changing direction of the galaxy field, as it flowed about the Milky Way, would force the solar whirl to change its direc- tion into a revolution about that filament (about the galaxy filiar axis), as shown hy the dotted path. The solar filament and field, by their own rotation about the solar filiar axis, would obviously keep the whirl moving ahead; i. e., at first the energy which makes the solar whirl travel as shown by the dotted line comes mostly from the solar whirl itself; the motion of the galaxy field at that time serves chiefly to direct its path (see par. g). Those fluid reactions are the same as those shown generally in §§98w, 101e, 107e. c. Now, some unusual combination of circumstances may have caused the solar whirl S to move along practically in the plane of the paper through S2 and §), as shown in the figure ;—i. e., S might possibly have been given off with scarcely any revolution about the main axis PP’; only in one chance in infinity could there have been zero revolution (for a finite tame, of course understood), which means not at all. But even if S did move so “‘simply,’’ only by one chance in infinity could it keep on in such non-revolving motion. (Even if, as in par. a, a whirl wabbled back and forth in the plane of the galaxy filiar axis, without perceptibly revolving about that axis, it is but a temporary substantial non-revolu- tion; for after a time definite revolution resulted, as shown. We are seeing an analogous thing here.) Consequently, S UNIVERSE Two Xil §112d would sooner or later begin definitely to revolve about PP’. As a fact, S started out from C with a component of revolu- tion about PP’, derived from the spiral in the galaxy filament surface. So as a necessary truism, (cf. §§980, 101e, concerning spiral motion), S revolves about the main galaxy axis. In Fig. 107e the solar system’s spiral path is roughly shown in perspective. | That path is neither a perfect or geo- metrical spiral nor a similar helix, but is a combination of both which is forever varying as the galaxy field varies and as the internal processes of the solar system proceed, as may be readily deduced by Bernoulli’s principle. Also, the rota- tion about PP’ might have been in either direction; it depends upon circumstances—perhaps usually chiefly upon birth con- ditions, although analogously to man, ‘astronomical nurture’ may under certain conditions take a chief role. [That revo- lution may be considered left-handed or counter-clockwise as viewed from above, and as drawn. Possibly that agrees, as it should, in relative direction with (1) the left-handed revo- lution of the planets, and (2) the arbitrarily drawn fluid mo- tions in the figure, and (3) the naming of the poles of the earth’s magnetic field, and (4) the usual direction of twist in the fiber of trees, the fact that man is usually right-handed, has his heart on the left side, etc. But 1 do not know; see Soob. | All of that is in direct agreement with the fact that the galaxy field has a spiral motion. Consequently, and as a further reaction, the spiral in the galaxy field be- gins to tilé the plane of the solar filament (which is at the present day still roughly the plane of the ecliptic), so that the solar main field becomes or stays more definitely aspiral, and so that the whirl is tilted with respect to the direction of its path as shown at S; and S—the latter being the solar system’s present location (exaggeratedly high; §107b). And that agrees with the observed facts about the motion of the solar system as a whole, now. Also, it analogously tru- istically requires that the axes of our planets be tilted just as they actually are. And it further truistically re- quires that the magnetic poles of the earth, etc., be displaced from the rotational poles somewhat; and it is observed that they are so. Those magnetic poles continually vary in loca- tion, which indicates that none of the fields is steady—which is in agreement with ‘no exact science.’ Similarly, the tilt of the whole solar system would slowly change some, as it encountered varying strength and spiral of the galaxy field. That is a motion of the solar system which has not been di- rectly recognized yet, so far as | can find. d. There are no data known to me which will deter- mine whether or not the solar system in past ages has had time enough [also youthful vigor enough, and-or environ- mental non-interference| to go on spiraling upwards, turning over the top of the Milky Way, until it made one or more complete revolutions in a spiral path about the galaxy jfiliar axis. Fig. 107e shows just a little more than one-half of such a revolution—and I have guessed that so much of travel oc- curred in 50 billion years. But there may have been many previous revolutions of the solar system about the galaxy fila- ment, so that it may be nearly as old as the galaxy whirl— in fact, it is possible that by the calendar (by our arbitrary L and T verbal forms) the solar system may be older than the galaxy (but improbable):- for it may have been picked up by the galaxy as a galaxy comet from another galaxy (cf. §120), where it could have been born (or not) as described above (the heat of the sun will indefinitely survive, depend- ing on galaxy conditions, as we shall see, so that it is possible that the solar system has been long wandering around as more or less a particular structure, or galaxy electron, from one galaxy to another). As a somewhat rash guess, based intuitively on the present ‘smoothness’ of the solar system, §112d X11 Two my personal opinion is that our system has not made a com- plete revolution about the galaxy filiar axis, but has had a path somewhat as in Fig. 107e, although directions may gen- erally be reversed from actual fact in that figure. e. I shall here complete the general description of the path of the solar system, although parts of the description anticipate the statement of the concrete evidence. Such evidence is implicitly given below in the description of inter- nal details or processes of the solar system. f. As the solar system moves around to the central gal- axy field in Fig. 107e, it obviously encounters a stronger and stronger spiral reaction from that field. Consequently, the path of S flattens out (the helix pitch becoming less, the path then expanding spirally). It is quite likely that now S is revolving around the galaxy axis PP’ almost in a plane, without helixing or corkscrewing up very much. It is some- what probable (because S is so small) that S has, or nearly has, used up its energy of self-propulsion in an upward helix, so that the galaxy center field has made it spiral downward for a while. Then in such a case, S would wabble or oscil- late up and down with respect to the galaxy filiar plane in a more or less circular orbit around PP’—which is mechanically identical with the possible wabbling of a large whirl in an orbit on the outer side (par. a). If the galaxy remains in a fairly steady environment, obviously such an oscillating orbit will finally be taken up by S, regardless of how many times it may have revolved around the Milky Way (unless S pre- viously gets assimilated by some other structure). Also, as seen in par. a, all other secondaries finally get inside the hole in the galaxy doughnut and take up such an orbit. Hence, it then becomes inevitable, assuming sufficiently steady en- vironment for the galaxy, that the systems in the central field will get crowded and will proceed to combine plan- etesimally into a central sun, as we shall see in the descrip- tion of the formation of our sun. It is most likely, however, that before that happens (before the galaxy turns itself intoa system similar to our present solar system—which would re- quire perhaps some decillions of our years), the galaxy will ‘collide’? with (which usually means ““side swipe’’) another galaxy—both having become somewhat elaborate star el] ust- ers in that process of condensing (so that their fields have become comparatively weak and give less protection from such collisions). So the ‘‘end’’ of the solar system will prob- ably be its combining with some other system, in that pro- cess of galary condensation. By the theory of chance (used in our ignorance of the actual pertinent facts), our system is likely to last more or less as it is now for some billions of years. The human race will nearly surely be wiped out by some comparatively minute changes in climate long before any such combining takes place, as is implicitly shown in the re- mainder of this section. g. We proceed now to consider broadly the climatic variations in the solar system and galaxy; the minor varia- tions of climate—those on earth—are discussed in 8129, As $ comes around under the Milky Way (Fig. 107e), it is obvious that what chiefly determines its path is the re- action of its field with the galaxy field. I. e., S is controlled mostly by affinity there, and but little by ordinary gravity. It is further obvious that the energy variations or asymmetries of the galaxy field ether flow which S encounters furnish the general, comprehensive cause of the variations in the internal growth of S.__In general it is obvious that at first S uses its own energy (more accurately :- potential) largely (being of new-born, high potential), to screw itself along its path, in the direction opposite the flow of the galaxy field. Asa gen- eral rule, it is obvious that such a wearing out or aging of § continues until such time as 5 oscillates near the galaxy filiar 122 UNIVERSE plane (as in the last paragraph), although there could be temporary reversals of that process at any time. We see the details of that wearing out or condensation later. We may note now that in general the reactions of the fields may be considered as regulating the speed of the various difference surfaces inside the solar system. And those speeds or poten- tials determine what we know as temperature, and the gen- eral phenomena of those difference surfaces or temperatures are bunched together under the name climate. Obviously, any variation of interaction of solar and galaxy fields modifies all climates in the solar system in proper proportions. Ordi- narily of course we speak of the sun as controlling our earth climate ($122); we here merely go further back and see what controls the sun climate——in fact, makes the sun itself. We could go still further ‘back’ or **up’’ and show what con- trols and modifies the galaxy field (and so on in infinite re- gress), and say that that controls our climate; but the principle is always the same (§110cd). h. As S starts off on its dotted path we have seen that it begins to revolve about the galaxy axis PP’. Now, as the galaxy is not a perfect or symmetrical structure it immedi- ately follows that the revolution of S around PP’ is eccentric. I. e., S will approach closer to the Milky Way on one side of PP’ than it does on the opposite side. As a result of that rhythm or overrunning (analogous to the eccentric orbit of the earth, say) there will be a corresponding rhythmic varia- tion of energy of interaction of galaxy and solar fields (analo- gous to the oscillations mentioned in the last paragraph, but on a generally smaller scale), and hence of the climates of bodies in the solar system. One side of the rhythm would be a rather warm geologic age and the other side would be a cold (glacial) age. I shall here proceed to write on the quantitative guess that that rhythm has produced the observed glacial ages; but obviously, the oscillations with respect to the galaxy filiar plane would always be present in some de- gree and would be a second general cause of large climatic variations, ina rhythm superimposed on the rhythm due to eccentricity of orbit about PP’. Similarly, it is obvious that the fairly near approach of our system to another solar system (say as close asa light year) would cause an appreciable varia- ation in climate. And an irregular variation in climate could be caused by marked variations from smoothness of the Milky Way filament as S travels past them in its orbit; per- haps that is actually the most efficient cause of conventional “‘glacial ages.’’ A geologic time scale of the earth, prepared from orthodox sources by H. F. Osborn, is repro- duced from his “‘Origin of Life’’ as Appendix C (it is put in an appendix so as to be easy to find, it being a useful table). According to Sollas (““Age of the Earth,’’ 285), there are observed to be at least three general glacial ages—‘‘once at the beginning of the Cambrian; again, and more evidently, during the Permian period; and yet once again in times comparatively near our own,’’ and observations show that three times there were intervening periods with climates con- siderably warmer than now. According to Osborn’s chart the time intervals between those three general glacial ages are roughly 13 million years for one, and 16 for the other. i. If we make a guess that the diameter of the orbit of the solar system around PP’ is something like 100 light years (that is probably too low a guess; ef. §107e), and that the system moves in that orbit at an average speed of 18mi/sec (that is probably too high), then we find that the length of a glacial year that is due to eccentricity of orbit would be about 34 million years. That does not agree with the 13 and 16 millions of the last paragraph. However, there are traces in recent times of six glacial ‘‘advances’’ in North America (““Ency. Brit.,’’ xii, 59), and it is quite possible that each of 123 those is a mark of a glacia) year or revolution about PP’. If that is a good quantitative guess, then orthodox guesses at geological time (those given in Osborn’s table) have, with too much deference to Kelvin’s bad guesses as to how long the sun could stay hot (he had no correct principle on which to base guesses), been entirely too small (cf. **Ency. Brit.,”’ xi, 651ff). But we can get figures that seem discrep- ant in the other direction. According to Eddington (‘‘Stel- lar Motions,”’ 261), Charlier finds the node of the ‘‘invari- able’’ plane of the solar system on the plane of the Milky Way to have a motion of 0.35 seconds of arc per century. If we assume that such “‘invariable’’ conditions actually do give roughly that average motion through a revolution of S abont PP’, then a glacial year would be about 370 million years, giving the sun’s orbit roughly a diameter of 10,000 light years, if we take the same speed in it as before. j-k. I have included those badly discrepant guesses to show how uncertain and unguided by consistent principles present geological and stellar measures sometimes are. The obvious facts are that the revolution of S about PP’ is rather irregular, but as it takes several million years to complete a revolution the irregularities are not yet perceptible to us; and that there are other rhythms in its orbit which probably modify the glacial ages due to that revolution. Further, an oscillation of S with respect to the galaxy filiar plane would obviously make the orbit itself vary very considerably in size. And the Milky Way is itself observably irregular. And the orbit of S would have precession in the minor degree that “‘gravity’’ applied. Also, it is obvious that every time the solar system passed fairly close to another system, there would be a variation, as mentioned. Also, it is entirely pos- sible that the solar system in its orbit about PP’ is so distant from the Milky Way that whatever eccentricity there may be in the orbit makes no perceptible difference in the climate, but that some of the other causes are efficient in producing glacial ages. Out of those several possibilities of vari- ation, and some slight knowledge of geologic speeds, I intui- tively judge that the time durations given in Osborn’s table ought to be at least three times longer in the cenozoic, at least ten times as great in the mesozoic, and twenty or more times as great for the remainder, with perhaps 40 or more billion years for ages before the archean. l. The “‘existence’’ of the human race obviously de- pends primarily or truistically on climate—for climate is simply the general name that implies certain conditions of dynamic equilibrium. If conditions are too much out of equilibrium the race as we know it will of course perish (or change enormously); if conditions are sufficiently stable a man could live almost indefinitely (see §123 for that consist- ent, possible ‘“fountain of youth’’ or millennium). Any ‘‘end’’ of the race implies the entry of the solar system into an environment somewhat different from the present. Such a change could occur by our running near another system; or by running into a considerably changed part of the galaxy field (or by some analogous interna] change in the solar sys- tem with reference to our earth and its field). However, a little consideration wil] show that no such marked change can rapidly occur—we are ‘protected’ by affinity or fields, and are not naked with a lone gravity. We would obviously take on such a change almost imperceptibly, and die off slowly during several generations if it were going to become too great for the present sort of race, and intelligent astronomers could predict the approach of any such end for thousands of years. Obviously, the solar system is supported and main- tained chiefly by the galaxy field (mostly by affinity, and only slightly by gravity) in a fairly steady equilibrium that may last without perceptible disturbance for billions of years. UNIVERSE Two XII §113b So there is no need to worry about any ‘‘end’’ of the earth. As indicated, an actual end would probably be so slow as to be perceptibly painless. Also, any probable change of cli- mate for the next ten thousand years could be met, by an intelligent people, by building suitable shelter. The rain will continue for a while to descend upon the just and the unjust, and the unjust will continue to flourish except for the process of slow suicide by stupidity which they practice (as we see implicitly in XVIII, XIX). Finally, of course the solar system will combine with some other system; and the race will perish some time before that begins very percept- ibly to happen, provided we do not detach the earth from the system and sail off to a safer environment; theoretically that is easy enough to do (§123). m. It therefore follows that if the solar system has ever made a previous revolution about the Milky Way (around the galaxy filiar axis), it is likely that the climatic conditions re- sulting eliminated much “‘life’’ that may have previously flourished. Hence, it should be kept in mind that there is a possibility that this earth has previously been peopled by a human race far more conscious (i. e., intelligent and defin- itely religious) than we are. So when in this book I speak of human beings, unless otherwise indicated I mean the ones on this planet that are included in the present time sequence of history, and I neglect some possible previous race(s) on earth, and races on other planets. They are all essentially the same, of course; but historical (i. e., quantitative) facts that apply to us, obviously do not definitely apply to those others. But even if S has made only the part of a revolution about the Milky Way, as in Fig. 107e, it is most probable that on a number of occasions conditions became sufficiently stable to permit primitive “‘life’’ to start ‘“‘spon- taneously’’ (§144) and continue for possibly a million or so years, and then be wiped out by some too great change. That is all the more probable when it is considered that this earth has never had a molten interior in the conventional sense ($119, etc.); quite likely the surface has been more or less molten on occasions even after it became rather large— it is now so, locally, as in volcanoes (and the seas and air are molten). I. e., ‘geology’ very probably began all over again, so to speak, several times. | We could rather positively find out (by principles analogous to those shown with respect to meteors, 8120), and get the previous history of the earth fairly well, by digging it completely up—examining al] of it. I judge that it is not worth while to do that. But perhaps the astronomers wil] in a few years, by plotting the paths of stars, figure out our history fairly accurately for several hun- dred million years back. At any rate, it is obvious that ge- ology and astronomy have barely scratched the surface of history, and that geology can stop skimping its time. S113. a. We now begin to follow through the internal processes of our solar system. For some of the details of those processes I shall shift to a description of precisely analogous processes in Saturn, in comets, and in meteors, where the evidence is clearer. Such details will apply analo- gously to any whirl, depending on relative quantitative con- ditions. The chief new point to be considered is that im the virtually older solar system gravity is now of more importance than affinity, and we have ‘reverse whirls,’ or solid or spheri- cal whirls, like our earth. b. As soon as gravity does begin to be a rather effective force the processes become something like those asserted by the old nebular theory. That theory in effect used only a force of attraction, or gravity, explicitly. So formally it tru- istically would not work: for any positive language requires at least two parts to a machine (Part One), and Kant’s start- ing nebula was just a single condensing ball, and it was then §113b XI1 Two impossible, even as a truism of his own dualistic logic, for it ever to become anything else. As a matter of actnal fact, he tacitly did use an opposing force which be called inertia or centrifugal force. But he failed to be explicit about it, and to show definitely that it must be handled, logically at least, as this book does it. There is nothing wrong with the old nebular theory if that centrifugal force be consistently used. If it be, we sball promptly get an infinite regress, or mass varies with velocity, or an ever-varying machine of two explicit parts like our whirl and filament. For instance, Bjerknes (‘‘Fields of Force,’’ p. 10) is explicit about the same thing the nebular theory is mystic about, thus:- ** Any body which participates in the translatory motion of a fluid mass is subject to a kinetic buoyancy equal to the product of the acceleration of the translatory motion multiplied by the mass of the water [fluid] displaced by the body.’’ That is the same as saying that mass varies with velocity; and it is concretely exemplified by the doings of a whirl. So we can say that the nebular theory is quite right as religious lang- uage; the difficulty with it is lack of pluralistic positiveness. For details of nebular theory, see ‘“‘Ency. Brit.,’’ xix, 333ff. c. Several men have with rather explicit validity worked out the gravity condensation of the solar system, and showed the detailed errors of the nebular theory. Chamberlin in “The Origin of tbe Earth,’’ has perhaps done it best. Chamberlin is such a first class all-’round man that I think his book is worth reading merely from the point of view of having the pleasure of looking at such a man closely. He uses an erplicit machine, consisting of two or more celestial [spherical whirl] bodies—which of course is theoretically equivalent to Reeve’s theory (§92) if it be reduced to the ultimate. © Chamberlin does not perform that logical reduc- tion: on the contrary he tacitly takes it that the reacting bodies have fields which modify the formerly-orthodox gravity effect—and that is, in general form, equivalent to the whirl theory. The explicit astronomy in his book is definitely orthodox dualistic astronomy which he took over bodily from an astronomer who merely repeated Laplace’s dualistic logic. But Chamberlin himself twice explicitly recognizes the effect of fields under the name of electric and magnetic action (ibid., 29, 148), as modifying (and strictly speaking, repudi- ating) that old Laplace astromical Jogic—or lack of it. d. Explicit points in which the old nebular theory fails to work, and additional details of how gravity collects small bodies (planetesimals, to use Chamberlin’s felicitous name) together into spheres such as the earth, when gravity is the chief force acting (i. e., when the whirl field gets too weak to hold the bodies mostly by its strength—by “affinity’), can be found in Chamberlin’s book. Eugene Miller in “‘The Origin of Our Planetary System’’ has expressed in an easily readable form a somewhat similar, non-rigorous theory, in which he deduces the solar system from two meeting spheri- cal bodies, now the sun and Jupiter (without explaining the origin of those two). Jeans has worked out the same genera] idea mathematically—as have several astronomers. Miller makes his spheres rhythmic or elastic or overrnnning; hence, his description, which may be considered as a brief but ex- tended application of the well known tide theory of G. H. Darwin is logically equivalent to the whirl theory. But he omits explicit statement of how (mechanically or-and logically) a body can be elastic. To include that, he must explicitly solve the One and Many, and hence become formally identi- cal with this whirl description (§101f). e. The reader may get from those books detailed ac- counts of planetesima] action, if he wishes. So J shall con- dense to bare essentials the description of the planetesima] processes of the solar system. 124 UNIVERSE We have taken the solar system as a general case, having it a rather fluid whirl with a comparatively neg- ligible amount of condensation of atoms when it breaks out of the Milky Way. It is to be repeated that it might vary from that in an indefinite number of ways. It is also to be emphasized that endless variation of the Jater internal processes is possible. I claim to do nothing more than show typical reactions. On account of the numerons possibilities —millions of perceptible ones,—for brevity Iam forced to become rhetorically somewhat dogmatic. But it is requested that the reader remember vividly here that al] quantitative assertions are just guesses and approximations, even though the inaccuracy may be of the order of only a second a cen- tury. Adifference of that much in the period of the rotation of the sun may have made the difference between there being now an ultra-Neptune planet or not: the solar system is just that delicately poised quantitatively, as we shal] implicitly see. We can’t tell whether a leaf wil] fall this way or that in a wind unless we make elaborate measurements that usu- ally are impracticable in the time available. It is a quantita- tive problem: the intelligible qualitative answer is that it will move in some direction if not held. And the solar system is a living being (for proof, see XVI) that perceptibly has far more parts in intricate quantitative dynamic equilibrium than any plant with its leaves—truistically; as a plant is only a small part of the solar system. b. As the system comes out at C along the path in Fig. 107e it encounters a comparatively rapidly changing environ- ment, and itself has a youthful high potential, as we saw. Consequently, the solar filament begins to break up rapidly —to give off secondary whirls. It probably in a million or so years began to take on the aspect of the whole galaxy whirl as shown in Fig. 107e. I.e., it probably by that time had many fairly large secondaries as outer spirals (the sec- ondaries would be the ‘‘knots’’ in the spiral arms of photo- graphed nebulas), and bad numerous small whirls that had come around into its central field. The collection of whirls in the centra] field would obviously constantly increase, as we saw with reference to the galaxy; for as soon asa whirl field wears out some, losing some of its affinity factor, that secondary whirl is swept by the solar field into the central solar field. | The secondary would there finally begin to os- ciJlate up and down as we saw may now be happening to the solar system with respect to the galaxy field. But if the secondary keeps on wearing out, then it in turn will finally break up into condensations (like an old, broken-up comet; §120). Or in short, in aging the density of the inner struct- ures of a whirl becomes too great, affinity can no longer sup- port them as a fluid whirl, and by the experiments we saw and obviously as a truism of Bernoulli’s principle or of the dynamic buoyancy’’ of Bjerknes (§$113b) they are swept out, the whirl condensing then mostly by gravity. c. Thus the fields of the secondaries in the central solar field themselves become weak, and the secondaries combine, in some of the ways we have seen. Those secondaries ob- viously become more numerous and crowded as time passes, and the crowding accelerates the uniting of them, and the formation of relatively harmonious sizes of condensations (§100j). And with weakened fields, gravity bas a greater effect between whirls, pulling them together (“‘electricity”’ is markedly or quite perceptibly the quantitative opposite of that; XIV). That force of gravity ultimately in practice or with respect to actual measuring is by no theory or measures Newton’s or Laplace’s mystical mathematica] limit, but is merely what we may express as being the field reactions of touching whirls of lower orders—finally of cells (S103; Index, “‘Gravity’’). | And that is obviously merely truistic; for as S114. a. 125 soon as the whirls show signs of disintegrating, then what we eall gravity steps in (the measure of the gravity factor rises as and when the affinity factor falls; Fig. 104b), and makes them hang together in another, ‘reverse’ way. Therefore, the total universe is now seen, in the most definitely ‘‘concrete’’ aspect, to vibrate or oscillate or exhibit rhythm about a condition of mean equilibrium. And if we observed and expressed our- selves perfectly, then obviously by the principle of least action (§98m), the deviation of the ultimate parts of the universe is zero—which is the ‘physics’ or concrete form of the principle that man can not make an error (§25). Or, all things in the universe are ultimately balanced. Consequently, the ultimate ethical law, expressed in pluralistic terms, is that we should be balanced or temperate—consciously so, as we actually in ultimate fact are anyway, and are truistically partly dead, or part men, if we don’t see it, don’t ‘‘be’’ that way (XVIII). Thus we promptly revert to an inex- pressible One in a very obviously truistic fashion as soon as we put gravity and affinity explicitly together. |The keen reader can note that in all this “‘material’’ description I am constantly on the verge of the One and Many. To use the language of Cooke in his Introduction, only the austerity of the mechanics of our ether cell prevents our slumping into mysticism-—which, while highly valuable in its place (Index, **Rebirth’’), is truistically out of place when we are under- taking to talk a mutually intelligible language. d. lt can be seen to be a reasonable quantitative guess (in the absence of the mathematical establishment of a gen- eral periodic table), that, inside any collection of atoms and small whirls which constitutes what we call a molar body, gravity and affinity are about equally effective. JI. e., in an ordinary molar body there is obviously about average equi- librium, and hence that equilibrium is so hard to upset that there existed before the discovery of unbalanced radioactive substances the erroneous quantitative anthropocentric guess that only a molar body was **matter,’’ and that such matter was indestructible. On either side (Fig. 104b) of that equilib- rium which from our anthropocentric point of view is fairly stable there is a less stable condition of equilibrium:- (1) that in which the fields are directly more effective, which is the condition we have been viewing in the solar system so far, and which, e. g., occurs in electricity; and (2) that form of matter in which the fields become comparatively less effect- ive (never wholly ineffective or zero), and in which the parts are held together mostly by gravity, as, e. g., the planets in the solar system, and radioactive bodies as compared with more stable ones (all atoms are somewhat radioactive, in that all field surfaces give off some secondaries; XI). e. Consequently, whether the worn out secondary whirls be broken up and the pieces swept out of the solar central field, or whetber they unite (collide, mostly by side swiping) the result is finally identical:- the condensations or molar bodies are formed. In fact, those different ways of naming the processes are merely different points of view of the same process. KE. g., if the whirls are broken up and “swept out’ of the central field, obviously the condensing is merely delayed, and takes place elsewhere, the condensations being finally swept back into what we may cal] the central conden- sation, as we shall see. I. e., the central condensations in the solar system produce our sun; some of the secondaries which get into the central field (as now happens with comets; §120) would be swept out, and would not at once combine with the sun, but would combine with (say) Jupiter; but, if there is time enough, Jupiter itself will finally condense into the sun (if there is not ‘time enough,’ then the solar system will itself condense or coalesce with another system, so i effect and in principle Jupiter condenses into the sun). So, UNIVERSE Two XII §lléa regardless of the details, the processes of condensation con- tinue—up to a point stated in the next two paragraphs. f. However, at once the opposite effect appears (it act- ually always accompanied the condensation), thus:- | When the fields of the whirls get relatively weak, gravity becomes of greater importance and pulls the whirls closer together— two filaments may unite into one; two whirls may alternately thread through each other; or there may be slipping or roll- ing on each other: those indefinitely numerous quantitative ways of ‘condensing’ give new elements, or chemical com- pounds, or solids, liquids, gases, and various combinations and modifications of those conventional things, ad infinitum. In coming together, the whirls overrun and hence make their field surfaces more energetic, and that produces in effect a single field which envelops the whole condensation (or, the fields may be said to coalesce into one; there being no ab- solutely distinct fields anyway, the two ways of expressing it are equivalent), the condensation and its unit field thus be- coming in principle identical with an ether cell. That ether cell is a ‘reversal’ of a whirl (§98); i. e., we simply take a new point of view of it (mathematically, we emphasize the other factor of the pair in Fig. 104b we happen to be using one of, so that a numerical increase of it indiéates travel in the other or ‘reverse’ direction on the curve); or we have verbally created that new, unit field, although actually it is nothing more than the summing up of the effects of two bod- ies which start going together and which truistically would verbally or logically keep on going or condensing until they became zero or monistic unless we thus changed points of view, or the trick of naming them (this being the dynamic concrete form of the inverse square law or the explicit going from one order to another). The definite mechanics of that are given in the chapters on light and electricity. There- fore, this summed up effect, or ‘reversed field’ of a condensa- tion, by the overrunning of the gravity effects is truistically made more energetic than the weakened fields it replaces, so that for the whole condensation the affinity potential immedi- ately rises and stops gravity’s increase. E. g., the eartb does not continue ‘condensing’ (by falling into the sun), but is supported by its and the sun’s field so long as galaxy con- ditions stay fairly steady, revolving about the sun (§134j). g. That is a general statement of the fact that potential remains fairly steady or balanced (there being only a rhyth- mic variation about a mean, due directly to the fact that the original criterion V, is not fixed or exact, and can not be). Or, it is a logical proof or self-consistent statement in terms of gravity and affinity, that each factor is mutually depend- ent and cannot become either zero or infinity with respect to actual bodies; in terms of human life, no person (in tbe us- ual Many sense of person) can be absolutely born, or can ab- solutely die. And it is a little difficult to express and to understand in that general form, for the simple reason that we are in the habit of talking in terms of classical logic and the nebular theory, which explicitly tries to talk about only gravity, etc. So we may at once put the general form in terms of observed facts about the solar system. The sun and the earth are obviously existing condensations. Both are ob- served to have a unit field (itis called electrical or magnetic; ef. §§113c, 121; XIV). Obviously, those fields must modify the pull of gravity. Therefore, regardless of any relative values of those fields, it follows from immediately verifiable facts that our argument or description is self-consistent. As implied, the whole of XIV, on electricity, gives verifiable facts proving this perceptible variation of gravity and affinity about a mean, with a reversal of structure (it isa quantitative fact: not an essential change). 8115. a. We therefore have molar bodies—planetesimals §ll5a XII Two —with weak fields being pulled together in the central solar field. They keep on collecting to form the sun. There ob- viously would be no conventional “‘collisions’’ of those bod- ies, for all are protected somewhat by fields. When mostly gravity pulls two towards each other, obviously the fields as a result start speeding up the spherical difference surface that then forms for each; and that truistically is an increase of the surface temperatures of tbe two bodies (that is merely the ultimate and consistent mechanics of the com- mon fact that compression of a substance usually makes it hotter). So it is obvious that the suzfaces of the planetesi- mals will be comparatively hot, but their fields, and insides, will be colder. Consequently, the surface of the sun will always be kept relatively bot simply as the result of the re- actions of the solar whirl with the galaxy freld. I. e.,so long as our solar system has a certain proportional amount of en- ergy (relative to the galaxy field), then that long will the main bulk of the solar system (which is the sun—the rest of it now amounting ronghly to less than 1/700 of the mass of the sun) have a surface hot enough to have a general /j. The sun simply is kept superficially hot by the whole gal- axy (and similarly the surfaces of the planets, etc., in their proper proportion). If the solar system tends to accumulate an excess of either affinity or gravity, so that the sun, with its certain relative size, cools or heats proportionally, then, just as in the last section, the solar system itself will con- dense or expand, and keep up the relative proportions and truistically restore and steady temperatures—up to a certain quantitatively critical point, at which the system will change order of structure. Obviously, that is merely another way of stating that the solar system is mostly supported in its spiral patb by the galaxy field. So only as the galaxy field around the solar system varies considerably in energy can the temperature of the sun’s surface vary much. In short, as the galaxy field as a whole is fairly balanced, espec- ially with reference to smal] whirls like the solar system, all the bodies in our galaxy, of a size perhaps slightly larger than Jupiter as a minimum, usually have a surface tempera- ture high enough to make their surface atoms visible—i. e., witbin 7}. And that is the quantitative basis on which this description of the universe was started; hence, the descrip- tion su far is in general self-consistent, as we have circularly come back to that fact. And a direct proof of this paragraph is Adams’s observation (I quote from a letter in which he refers to an article in ““Astrophysical Journal,’ 45, 1917) that the smaller and less massive stars move more rap- idly than the larger and more massive ones, the comparison being made between stars having similar physical conditions. And that is merely one form of the Jaw that mass varies with velocity, or the astronomical aspect of Bernoulli’s principle; or, as Adams puts it, the fact exhibits the principle of equi- partition of energy. b. And all that is obviously merely a particular way of asserting our original observation that everything is interre- lated. | We have seen that the sun’s heat is thus sustained by the whole galaxy; so there is no fear of the sun’s cooling off very soon. The conventional theories of the sun’s heat (‘“‘Ency. Brit.,’’ Art. ““Sun’’) obviously imply the foregoing explicit description; but they get somewhat confused by lay- ing the explicit stress wholly on gravity——thus fancying that the inside of the sun is hot so that the sun itself is directly a reservoir of heat. We see additional detailed facts confirming this section as we proceed. 8116. a. As the solar whirl S travels along its path in Fig. 107e the condensation of the sun continues. Obviously, the central field of the solar whirl is, dynamically, somewhat cylindrical, as the virtually younger Saturn is observed to be UNIVERSE 126 now in perceptible measure (‘‘Ency. Brit. gat ‘*Saturn’’). That same modification of the figure of the sun, earth, ete., would still apply in slight degree. The exact figure of the earth or any other actual celestial body is not known, and is not exactly soluble. That figure approaches geomet- rical sphericity somewhat; so I roughly speak of spherical whirls. For the conventional mechanics of those figures, see ‘“Eney. Brit.,’’ Art. ‘“Earth, Figure of.”’ b. Obviously, that general mechanics of condensation agrees with the fact that observed spiral nebulas have conden- sations in the center. Also, in our galaxy the condensation has not proceeded so far as to form any perceptible central sun or visible beginning of one; but most likely the center of our galaxy, on account of the comparatively numerous bod- ies there, looks, from other galaxies, as if there were the usual thick nebulous center—but possibly not; possibly our galaxy it too young yet. Our mechanics obviously not only consistently describe the formation of the sun, but they also agree explicitly with the observed distribution of stars with reference to the Milky Way:- they are thinly distributed at the galactic poles (P and P’, Fig. 107e), becoming more thickly sprinkled towards the Milky Way, as observed irom our position near the center (‘‘Ency. Brit., ‘“Star’’). Also, our mechanics obviously furnish an explanation of the various observed star drifts (same Art. ‘‘Star’’). c. It is observed that the ‘‘surface’’ of the sun (which is fluid) rotates faster at the sun’s equator and gradually goes slower as the poles are approached (the equatorial sur- face rotates once in about 25 days, and the polar surface in about 6 days longer). The same condition seems to have been observed on Saturn, and there is considerable evidence that our atmosphere acts in the same way (as we shall see, the sun [ete.] has a ‘“‘solid’’ surface like the earth, as it is cold inside: but just as we do not see the floor of the ocean, we do not see that solid surface, except perhaps dimly in the middle of sun spots, and we do not know its rotation time). In the sun, the upper layers of the ‘‘surface’’ we see (i. e., hydrogen layers; ““Ency. Brit.,’’ ““Sun’’), rotate faster than the lower ones, and the extreme perceptible outer layer seems to retain its angular velocity as the poles are approached. Obviously, all those otherwise unexplained phenomena are directly consistent with our description of spherical whirls— or follow directly from Bernoulli’s principle applied to ether cells. Also, that explanation is obviously equivalent to the discussion of temperature in the last section. 8117. a. The sun when condensing as described would obviously not only acqnire a rotation ahout its axis, of the nature just decribed, but the sun as a whole, by the principle of asymmetry, would form somewhat away from the center of the solar whirl field (i. e., the axis of the sun would not correspond with the solar main axis). Hence, the sun itself would revolve about the solar main axis (about NS’ in Fig. 107e, although the center of the sun would be close to NS), and the primary result of that would be that there would be an accumulated asymmetry which tended to make what was left of the solar filament finally split into practically two large secondary whirls (which process or stage of splitting would correspond to conventional “‘dumbbell’’ nebulas). Or, we can equally correctly say that the general unbalance of con- ditions due to the traveling of the solar whirl] asymmetrically in the galaxy field (i. e., the start of the solar path in Fig. 107e obviously is asymmetrical with respect to the main axis PP’), would tend to give such a double splitting, while at the same time the same general asymmetry caused the sun to form with its center of gravity off to one side of the solar main axis. Both ways of stating the condition obviously give the same result, being merely different points of view. 127 And it can be observed in experimental soapy water whirls that the inevitable asymmetry even in a basin of water that is apparently still has a tendency to accumulate and produce such dumbbell or two-part splitting. b. Parenthetically it may be noted that the infant sun would revolve in an elliptical orbit about the solar main axis. Also, the very young sun would itself at first be composed of many small condensations revolving more or less about each other in orbits controlled largely by gravity; the sun in that condition is a miniature star cluster. But that star cluster would be comparatively small, and hence would condense rapidly (say in a few million years) and form a structure with chondrules as in meteorites ($120). And the ellipticity of the orbit of the sun and also the ellipticity of the orbits of its parts before it was quite condensed into a more or less in- fant sun, would cause the condensations to sweep out consid- erable space; also, the oscillations of those orbits up and down near the solar filiar plane (roughly the ecliptic) would sweep out a further space; and all those reactions would ac- celerate the formation of the sun. For the details of that roughly described planetesimal condensation see Chamber- lin’s “‘Origin of the Earth.’? The essential point of the process is that the reactions tend towards the same result. ec. To take up again the probable dumbbell splitting, we can see that at about the time the sun begins to be a more or less dense cluster the solar whirl has a strong ten- dency to become a spiral nebula with two rather definite arms. Of course there could have been a number of smaller arms (secondaries and their debris, tertiaries, etc.) previously formed; also, instead of two arms, the whirl could have completely split into a number of secondaries, forming as many arms. Spiral nebulas of those varying characteristics are actually observed in the skies. And when the solar filament is thus nearly all dissipated as secondaries, ob- viously the filament is also comparatively much weakened so that the secondary fields are weak, and the gravity factor be- comes locally more effective. That gravity factor then ac- celerates the condensing into spherical whirls, which whirls relatively have an effective strong difference surface (e. g., the hot or high potential surface of the sun), and those re- versed whirls thus bring the affinity of the whole solar system up again, balancing the system with the galaxy whirl (S$114c). Thus we again see the rhythm of structure about the One line of no resistance. d. With that increase of gravity action there would be rapidly formed in the central field of each secondary a nucleus similar to the infant sun. § Those condensations would form more or less in the solar filiar plane (which is roughly the same plane still:- the ecliptic; for that data, and for author- ity for other facts ] use about the planets, etc., see *“Eney. Brit.,’’ Arts. ‘““Sun,’’ ‘‘Planet,’’ ‘“Planets, Minor,”’ “*Jupi- ter,’’ ete.; for brevity I omit frequent citation of authority). However, a good many of those condensations, especially while they were in the rather sparse cluster stage, would ob- viously have their general outer field get comparatively so weak that the remains of the solar whirl field would sweep them out of the ecliptic, around the filiar axis, into the cen- tral solar field and likely into the sun (cf. §112a), ‘In the past it is very probable that large planets (at least infant planets) have been thus swept into the sun; in the future when we get into the proper galaxy environment for it, other outer planets will be thus swept into the sun; comets now are obviously minor condensations which have had such a history ($120). It is most likely that novas or new stars which suddenly blaze up in a few days much brighter than they were before (and then more or less slowly grow dim) are stars which have thus been hit by one of their outer UNIVERSE Two Xll §l17f planets. The general disturbance caused by the reaction of the fields as the planet is falling could account for the minor preliminary increase of brightness sometimes observed in novas. One conventional explanation of new stars is that they are caused by ordinary stars’ running into dark nebulas. The objection to that is that the various fields would prevent such a collision, and that the fields would in any partial col- lision be so strong that only very gradual results could occur. If Neptune swung around into the sun it obviously would make the sun blaze up quite a bit, and probably would burn up most of us humans; but it would not smash the sun ap- preciably, but would be superficially spectacular, like novas. It is therefore obvious that it is possible that the former popu- lar fear of comets was a racial memory from the former days when some comets did do a lot of local damage. Neptune would make a rather large and dangerous comet. But no one need get frightened, as intelligent astronomers could predict such occurrences hundreds of years ahead. e. If the solar whirl started ont as a fluid whirl, it is likely that the larger secondary whirl of that possible dumb- bell splitting was the beginning of what is now Jupiter, our giant planet. It is possible, of course, that the sun and Jupiter were two solar systems which approached each other and pulled each other into a gravity spiral nebula, as is tac- itly asserted possible by Chamberlin and others. It is im- probable, however. Certainly it is practically impossible that there were two /one stars, Sun and Jupiter, in the same neighborhood in the galaxy field; and the combination of the more probable Sun cluster and Jupiter cluster except by extremely improbable chances would have produced a more complicated solar system than ours is observed to be. _It is likely that tbe astronomers already have enough data to de- termine at once the probable actual history as regards that possibility. The actual fact is, of course, that tbe solar sys- tem was never (except by one chance in infinity) a whirl so perfectly fluid as to contain no structures higher in order than ether cells: always it would start with some “condensations.’ Analogously, neither could it be a whirl or nebula produced by just two sharp and distinct bodies or condensations. Al- ways there would be fields (affinity) to those bodies, and more or less of a cluster condition which would produce some- thing of a fluid whirl. Chamberlin in effect asserts that; so there is logical identity between Chamberlin’s planetesimal processes, and these whirl mechanics in which for rhetorical needs ] am deliberately emphasizing affinity. f. The solar system now, so far as has been observed, consists of the sun with four planets (respectively Mercury, Venus, Earth, Mars), then a gap in which there have been seen over a thousand smal] planets or asteroids (those asteroids often depart considerably from the ecliptic), then the four outer planets (respectively Jupiter, Saturn, Uranus, and Neptune), with various moons, comets, meteor trains, and gases, It is likely that the asteroids form most of what is left of the original solar filament (compare with the “‘dirt”’ in Northrup’s filaments; §102d); there probably still re- mains a slight fluid motion of ether asa filament there, but its spiral has probably become nearly wholly a revolution about the main solar axis; some such motion might be de- tected by close observation of the orbits of asteroids. When the solar whirl became a rather well defined spiral it is obvious that most likely a number of comparatively small secondaries traveled around the solar filament into the cen- tral solar field. ©The sun by that time would have been at least a considerably condensed cluster, so that there would have been considerable space around the sun in which there was room for those whirls to survive, and to condense to- gether in a proportionate way, thus sweeping out all that S117f XII Two space pretty cleanly. That would produce the four inner planets; it might have produced forty except that the quan- tities happened to be so related by the principles of harmonic periodicity (or here, by the principles of Bode’s law; cf. next paragraph, §128, etc.) that there were four. Probably the other and smaller part of the original dumbbell splitting (if there was such a splitting) was Saturn. It would be pro- tected by Jupiter; i. e., Jupiter would sweep out its space pretty cleanly, and would more or less break up the original solar field, so that Saturn lived in a fairly steady and weak- ened solar field, and hence lived very slowly and is now virt- ually quite young—compared with the earth; middle aged compared with the galaxy whirl. The two known planets now remaining still further out, Uranus and Neptune, are obviously condensations made up of other whirls left in the outer space. There may be a number of outer planets yet undiscovered ; it is a quantitative problem not exactly soluble. There are surely some smal] condensations out there. g. Now, all of those planets (including the asteroids as the averaged equivalent of one planet) may obviously truis- tically be considered to have field surfaces substantially equal in potential—in energeticness. In short, the reason Newton got his form of illogical law is that the planet field surfaces are rather weak and about equal. It therefore theoretically follows directly that, as their orbits are approximately in the plane of the ecliptic (roughly, are 2-dimensioned), then the proper harmonic periods for the space distribution of the planets would be with radii of orbits related approximately by the ratio 2—which by the theory of areas of circles (Area= 4rr2), dynamically balances the structure and verbally bal- ances the inverse square law. If we take the number 0.15 and form a geometrical series by multiplying it by 2, we have 0.15, 0.3, 0.6, etc. If we arbitrarily add 0.4 to each number, we have 0.55, 0.7, 1.0, 1.6, 2.8, 5.2, 10.0, 19.6, 38.8. The radii of the planets’ orbits (the earth’s being taken as 1.0; and roughly averaging the planetoids’) are re- spectively :- 0.39, 0.7, 1.0, 1.5, (2.8), 5.2, 9.5, 19.2, 30.1. Obviously those radii are approximately equal to the modi- fied geometrical] series. That coincidence or empirical rule is known as Bode’s law (‘‘Ency. Brit.,’? ““Bode’’). Obviously, if Newton’s law were accurate and logical we would not have those discrepancies, and would not have had to use the 0.4 (the use of which corresponds to the actual fact that the bodies are of finite size, and not zero or geomet- rieal points as in Newton’s law). But because there are fields, and bodies of finite size, the harmonic space distribu- tion of the planets (including their satellites) requires first a general modification of the series in more or less equal degree for each member—that being accomplished by the 0.4. Then, there are two considerable discrepancies :- in the dist- ance of Mercury, and the distance of Neptune. The spheri- cal field of the sun is comparatively strong; hence the field of Mercury would be considerably modified, compared with most fields in the solar system, and would have its gravity pull considerably modified; and that principle properly ex- hibits itself in the discrepancy noted. (It is also definitely known from astronomical observations that Mercury percept- ibly departs from Newton’s law.) Neptune is exposed to the solar whirl field and hence like Mercury is pulled in closer by gravity and thus speeded up, bringing its field to equilibrium. In short, Bode’s law is a series of numbers which roughly exhibits relative values of W... XA... in the solar system. If Newton’s law were correct, Bode’s law would be a series using 2 as a precise ratio: a perfect gas, where all space sizes are formally 0 or ©, is sucha monism. Bode’s law, logically interpreted, is equivalent to Moseley’s law, if Moseley’s law is made to agree with the general law that 128 UNIVERSE there is no exact science, so that therefore Moseley’s ratios are not considered ultimately exact, any more than Bode's are exact ($128). That identifies or unites the total solar system concretely with one wave Or corpuscle of light, as is made implicitly obvious in the chapter on light (XIII). §118. a. While the solar whirl was thus forming the sun, with planets revolving about it, each planet as a smaller or lower order whirl would obviously by the logic of identity and the mechanics of whirls be following precisely the same process, and we may observe in a rough way the various stages in the history of the solar system by observing the planets as they now are. Except for being of smaller size, and hence generally less energetic, Saturn is obviously now in the stage the solar system was, shortly after the sun had somewhat condensed from the central cluster of planetesi- mals—say 20 to 30 billion years ago. | We may briefly ob- serve some of the numerous details that are seen in Saturn. b. Saturn has rings thatare slightly tilted from the plane of its orbit (just as the ring of planets about the snn theoret- ically is tilted from the plane of the sun’s orbit about PP’), Conventional theories are not definite as to the composition and mechanics of those rings (““Eney. Brit.,’’ **Saturn’’), It is mathematically established that Newtonian gravity alone would not support a fluid ring, and it is therefore ortho- doxly assumed that gravity solely acts upon small bodies, keeping them in revolution and forming Saturn’s rings. The obvious defects in that assumption are :- (1) only by one chance in infinity would the thin rings then be formed, or be capable of remaining in the same plane if once formed (i. e., the sole-gravity idea—or rather absence of idea—gives no fields to support or control the rings in that plane: the ordi- nary sole-gravity hypothesis of the general ring or plane of planets suffers from the same defect): (2) the rings are in some places practically opaque; they are clearly visible; and they cast a shadow on the body of Saturn; and those condi- tions obviously could not exist with rings of scattered par- ticles (and have them sum only to the actual small] weight of the ring), unless the particles were rather close together and mostly of smal] size, and hence were, by the electron theory, in effect a fluid (and that contradicts the original orthodox premise): (3) the whole ring has dark bands (or is split into concentric ‘‘rings’’) which apparently vary, aud in effect the whole ring has six outer concentric rings that are six moons (there are four more known moons farther out, not quite in the ring plane); and the orthodox sole-gravity theory is helpless in stating why such conditions happened, or even why they persist, having started. ce. Clearly, if we consider the ring to be the vestiges of the filament of the Saturn whirl every one of those outstand- ing characteristics of Saturn is directly consistently estab- lished as a mechanical truism, similar to the explanation of the solar system, and the conditions of the ring are direct evidences of the truth of the whirl theory. d. The ninth satellite or moon of Saturn has a retrograde motion. The pure-gravity or nebular theory can not account consistently for that retrograde revolution (which also applies to the two outer moons of Jupiter and to the moon of Nep- tune ;— incidentally, IJ am not certain as to numbers of vari- ous sets of moons, for new ones have been recently found and I am depending on casual memory for these comparatively trivial facts). Obviously, the whirl theory would require, as being quantitatively most probable, that most of the inner condensations should revolve about the center of their whirl in the same sense as the revolution component of the spiral in the original filament. But outer secondary whirls obviously could easily get capsized, being exposed to the environment, and would then revolve ina retrograde’’ direction; in fact, 129 such capsizing obviously establishes more stable equilibrium in the weak outer field (Chamberlin’s planetesimal theory, in using defective astronomy, omits showing definitely any simi- lar strengthening of equilibrium that amounts to a check on the gravity process; and the theory thus more or less fails to locate positively the probable place for retrograde motion). e. I shall be more explicit as to the ““dark’’ bands, and the orbits of the six inner moons that are in the ring plane, and are hence in effect equivalent to six more bright rings— or, are equivalent to more or less definite electrons in an atom :- The combination of the two forces W...X*4A... would obviously, by our theory of harmonic periodicity, sort out or sift out condensations of the same spherical field sur- face intensity, arranging those of the same intensity ata properly or harmoniously proportioned radial distance from Saturn, thus arranging those of the same intensity in a ring concentric with the rings in which were those of other inten- sities—the least effective intensity being outward, and hence truistically becoming distinct moons, in which and in the for- mation of which obviously gravity is stronger than affinity (than field surface). When the field surfaces of the conden- sations become stil] weaker, they are obviously then not able to hold the moons in the plane; and the stronger gravity dis- turbances among themselves and other bodies throw them somewhat out of the plane (enough out to strengthen their field surfaces, and establish harmonic equilibrium with other planets, etc.). So obviously, if we were observing the six inner moons from afar and had retinal persistence enough so that they remained perceptible streaks of light al] around their orbits, they would appear as such streaks or rings located in harmonious proportions or as a spectrum (XJI1); and the irregular outer moons (irregular in the sense that for them there is not a nearly complete balance of W and 4 relative to just the Saturn structure) would be bright bands of per- ceptible width—that might be bright enough over a wide enough radia] distance to be a “‘continuous’’ spectrum. In short, the Saturn rings, by exhibiting directly the varying proportions or effects of W and A exbibit what we might cal] a molar spectrum; also, they show a sifting out or “concrete periodic table.” | Obviously, therefore, the dark rings would be due to the fact that at certain places in the varying bal- ancing of W and A, conditions Jacking equilibrium arose, and the ‘atoms’ were pulled to one side or the other of the circle in the whole ring which would have been their Jo- cation had they been stable there (being thus changed or ‘condensed’ into the more stable-sized bodies away from that circle): so in the neighborhood of the circle there would be few if any surviving condensations of the particular size that would balance there, and hence too few reflectors or givers of light; and therefore ““darkness.’’ That is identically what happens, with direct reference to harmonic proportions or ‘periods’ of comparative equilibrium, in the formation of the periodic table. Obviously, there could exist a band in the ring in which over a comparatively considerable radial dist- ance there is such a proportionality of Wand A that there is practically continuous equilibrium, and hence no percept- ible trace of dark rings or gaps, but a thicker collection of condensations: and a precisely analogous condition occurs in the chemica] periodic table, with respect to the so-called ‘“‘break’’ containing the rare earths, which break corresponds to one of the brighter, wider bands in Saturn’s ring (App. A, atoms 57 to 72), and in the solar system as the rather con- tinuous band of asteroids. It it not a ‘“break,’’ but the ab- sence of a break—the actual breaks (where we may say that the rhythms of various—several—properties get out of step) or dark rings occur between the ordinary ‘felements.’’? And a secondary and hence more pronounced rhythm of such lack UNIVERSE Two XII §119a of breaks is evidenced by the groups in column VIII of the periodic table. There is in the table a considerable ‘dark band’ between H and He. It is obvious that in that space other “‘elementary’’ atoms could exist temporarily, but not very stably; and Thomson (in experiments on canal rays) made some of those atoms that existed for perhaps a short time. This paragraph could profitably to physicists be expanded to a volume. 1 haven’t gone far into the sub- ject— which is why the paragraph is vague and ambiguous. $119. a. Further, depending mostly upon the ener- getic condition of the main solar field, it is obvious that ad- ditional outer moons of Saturn might be held in the plane of the ring. If the solar field were energetic, and the Saturn filament were young enough to take up some of that energy or were conditioned so as to balance with it, then the Saturn field would hold additional moons in its ring, and tbe ring would be wider. And in the same circumstances, the small- condensations part of the ring would extend farther out, be- fore those condensations would collect into moons of weaker affinity. So as a truism, in such circumstances Saturn would be ‘‘heavier,’? or would have a higher ‘atomic weight.’ Therefore, if on earth we subject atoms to considerably heav- ier pressure for a long time (other conditions being fairly steady—as would reasonably be the case deep inside the earth), then that would be equivalent to giving them a wider ring and increasing their atomic weights. It therefore fol- lows that inside the earth there are most probably (in prin- ciple absolutely are, {f the quantitative conditions are right) atoms of higher atomic weights than any we have yet ob- served—Just as there seem to he, by the same principle ap- plied to opposite quantitative conditions, elements in nebulas (where the pressure is light: where there is plenty of room) that are lighter than any we have got hold of on earth. So if any of the heavier internal atoms got extruded by volcanoes ($122), they would begin to have their “outer moons’ grow more loose and unstable. And under proper quantitative conditions (especially is time enough needed for the results to accumulate) some of those outer moons would break loose from the atom, and we would have the phenomena of radio- activity—identical in principle with ordinary secondary whirl formation described in XI, but quantitatively probably in- volving considerable heavy condensations as just described. In the solar system comets represent radioactivity with respect to the internal parts of the system; i. e., comets nowadays are a very mild degree of interna] radioactivity which would cor- respond to internal electron formation with respect to atoms —a breaking up so mild in degree as usually not tobe called *‘radioactivity.”’ To get conventional radioactivity as ex- hibited externally by ordinary atoms, we would have to bave the solar system as a whole react percepitbly with other sys- tems, and it happens that at present there seems to be no such perceptible reaction, in which pieces break out of our solar field and go as a comet to other systems—as a rather large secondary. But obviously, the principles are consist- ent and simple, as shown. Clearly, there could be a long series (really in infinite regress) of ‘periodic rhythms’ of new and heavier atoms under long-continued heavier pressures. Obviously, in steady conditions of pressure the atoms would not perceptibly change any more than the solar system as a whole is doing. Therefore, inside (say) the earth where the conditions are fairly steady there would be no perceptible breaking up of the atoms (no ‘‘radioactivity’’), and hence no appreciable heating from that cause: there may be a com- parative trifle of heating effect from radioactivity in the sur- face layers of the earth. So from that point of view also, the insides of the planets, etc., must be cold (see also §122i); only their surfaces have sufficient disturbances of equilibrium ‘ §119a XII Two to produce much heat. There would be breaks in the rhythm of those heavier elements, similar to those in our periodic table. And the atomic weights would keep on go- ing “‘up,’’ or the periodic table keep on extending itself, to some variable limit in a given planet. The principle defining that limit is truistically this:- if a whirl happens to be en- ergetic enough to form an atom of a weight beyond the har- monious limit, it will be unstable and break up. b. Similarly in the other direction, towards the H end of the periodic table, there is a lower limit of atoms for our average conditions. At that limit there is a gap in our ‘mo- lar spectrum’ which is equivalent to the change in order of whirls from atoms to electrons. But that gap itself in differ- ent quantitative conditions is subject to variation (ef. the dis- cussion of spectrum in XJII). So obviously, this is merely a repetition of the infinite regress of harmonic periodicity given at length in a general way in §101. The way to get a defin- ite and applicable numerical and rigorous statement of the theory is to determine the structures of atoms in ways to be shown, then tabulate the rhythms of their properties as Richards does in his Faraday lecture, and combine the two. ec. Furthermore, it is directly obvious that although the harmony or rhythm of proportion of al] whirls or atoms (based on Y\—or on any other given criterion) would remain steady, so that relatively to its environment C always has the same properties roughly, yet an atom of C in one environ- ment by no means necessarily contains (and by only one chance in infinity could contain) the same quantity of ether cells, as a C atom in another environment. For it is obvious that all of the condensations in the Saturn rings which are of a fairly stable size and which as a sum form a ring of certain radius, and which condensations we may say are analogous to C atoms, would have to contain a different amount of ‘“substance’’ (really, of a fixed verbal or logical space and time; cf. Part One) in order to occupy the same relative ring (of relative properties) ina system otber than the Saturn sys- tem. Yet in both systems those condensations at similar relative locations would be C. For obviously, if the two then differently weighing C’s (referred to a fixed standard quantity of ether cells) were not both the same consistently named C, then we would get a practically identical spectrum (with reference to its most perceptible portion) from “‘different’’ elements. In brief, WW is only one factor, and irrational alone, and there can be no constant atomic weights. Or in familiar Janguage, circumstances alter cases—that quantita- tive truism implying that the relations or principles stay steady. Therefore, because of different past history two atoms may apparently be built the same with respect to easily perceptible properties of a certain sort (suchas roughly having the same spectrum; or roughly having apparently the same ‘‘chemica]’’ reactions), and still have perceptible differences in weight. As a matter of truisms, of course those different past histories have made the two atoms some- what different in every characteristic or property. (And as it is truistic that no two things can occupy the same space sim- ultaneously, therefore each thing in the universe has had a history, and hence has properties, different from every other thing.) It merely happens that in the genera] theory of harmonic proportions the weight of the two varied appreci- ably more than some other properties: theoretically, there is no reason why the reverse should not occur (that the weight of two atoms should be practically the same while the two differed appreciably in other properties); and allotropic forms are actual] examples. d. And obviously, any interaction of the Saturn whirl] with any other whirl (planet) wil] make the orbits of the moons (and everything else in the whirl) get smaller or UNIVERSE 130 larger. Any sort of atoms are therefore directly compress- ible, in complete agreement with Richards’s theory (§82). e, It would be easy to go on for volumes giving the general principles of atomic structures, as they are directly evidenced by the structure of Saturn. Those volumes are omitted for several reasons:- (1) The reader who is inter- ested can work them out readily, and will find it more profit- able and enjoyable to do it for himself. (2) The volumes are actually rather useless until they are expressed in ob- served measures with some fair numerical precision. And that is an enormous work I have scarcely touched, and of which I am mostly in ignorance. Quite probably [ have con- sequently made silly quantitative errors in the foregoing, and it is better to stop before I make those errors worse. f. It is possible, by further using Saturn as evidence, or by using other facts about the solar system, to go on and show in considerable rough detail why the sun and various planets should have their actually observed densities, masses, tilts of axes, speeds of axial rotation, virtual ages, ete. Ob- viously, all those properties are completely related by W...X A,.., and we can readily get rough verbal] statements of the relationships out to a considerable number of dots, even in the absence of the more precise mathematical expression. (The chief reason we can so readily get consistent expression of those relationships here is because we are working in the actual three dimensions; that verbally compels a statement of rea] structure.) But probably most readers would find such a necessarily lengthy statement of technica] astronomical] detail both confusing (for this first general view of the uni- verse), and also tiresome. It is not actually needed by the intelligent reader, as it is merely a detailed application of principles already seen in general working. So I shall end this astronomical chapter by giving some odds and ends of details that are illuminating, and also perhaps interesting. 8120. a. We briefly consider comets (for authority for observed facts used, see ““Ency. Brit.,’’ Art. ‘“Comet’’). b. We have seen that any whirl would have some con- densations. ‘There would be numeyous condensations in the older spiral nebulas snch as the solar system, or even in the considerably younger Saturn. In the virtually very old spir- al nebulas such as the earth-moon system, those condensa- tions, especially the larger ones, seem to be rather cleanly swept out by the planetesima] process. However, even in the case of the earth-moon there is considerable evidence of the existence still of lighter condensed whirls (§121¢). For verbal simplicity and brevity let us explicitly consider only the condensations which are scattered in the outer parts of the solar whirl field. The nearest star to us so far as known is nearly four light years distant (if I remember correctly: it was discovered two or three years ago). So it is probable that the field difference surface of the solar whirl is, in the plane of the planets, at least one light year distant from the sun—about-60,000 times the distance of the earth from the sun or 2000 that of Neptune from the sun. Hence, com- paratively there would be considerable room for condensa- tions beyond Neptune. Possibly there are some fair sized planets out there—probably retrograde. But at any rate there would be some smal] whirls there that are more or less aged into clusters. Also, in that weak outer solar field there would be a tendency for the gravity of the scattered clusters to become relatively strong enough to pull them into larger clusters; and the process of forming those clusters would create a sufficiently strong field (increase iis A) so that there would be a stronger reaction of cluster field and solar field, and the cluster would get swept out of the ecliptic, around through the solar field into the central field where the sun is. Also, precisely the same thing would obviously tend to occur 13] UNIVERSE as the result of any disturbance of the solar field if the whirl ran into a somewhat different environment—if our whirl came close to another system, say. Those are merely additional details showing again how outer fields are cleaned out. c. Those clusters (or virtually old secondaries, or what- ever else we name the possible variations) as they sweep around into the central solar field are comets. | There is no very complete orthodox explanation of comets and their phe- uomena; butas we shall see, this whirl description completes the orthodox explanations with obvious consistency, and shows in even more detail] that the whirl theory is universally consistent. Of course, those comets could be born from practically any part of the solar system; or a planetary whirl could give birth to a comet into the solar whirl field; but only briefly in pars. gh shall we consider those variations. d. Those clusters would have sucha comparatively weak field that the sun’s gravity pull would act rather strongly on them to pull them towards the sun when they got started in their swings around. That increased speed would truistically give more intense reactions of solar field and comet field, and the comet field would therefore do two general things to the comet cluster:- (1) the cluster would form into a rather defi- nite whirl which comparatively very rapidly started condens- ing into a central nuclens (central “sun’); (2) the comet field rubbing energetically on the little fields inside would make them heat up the surfaces of the condensations. And both of those mechanical results give subsequent phenomena pre- cisely as are observed in comets. In general those phenom- ena are these:- (1) As the comet gets near the sun the nucleus could be either a cluster or an actual condensation into an infant sun (or of course any intermediate stage). Ob- servations of comets have not definitely determined whether the nucleus is an opaque condensation, or a cluster that we ean see through pretty well; clearly, our theory would give both possibilities, and that will make plain all the ques- tions as to the mass and densities of comets, and of their ob- served breaking up. (2) And the spherical surfaces could heat to incandescence without much affecting the parts inside of those fairly thin glowing surfaces (for direct proof, see par. k). (3) Those surfaces could vaporize into more or less fluid atoms or molecules, and all the visible phenomena of comets would follow, as is readily obvious, but as will be stated in slight detail below. e. As the comet came nearer the sun and its speed in- creased its spherical surfaces would gradually get hotter, and would finally vaporize some. (That vaporization is obviously itself a giving off of secondary whirls: a less degree of the same phenomenon gives sun-spots, volcanoes, storms, etc. ; §122.) That vapor or collection of atomic secondaries would fill the field of the comet with visible whirls, and so we see the whirl field in photographs of comets. Also, the rapid speed of the comet causes numerous births of secondaries from the outer field surface of the comet, so that the atoms get ‘outside,’ into the solar field. Then partly due to the pressure of light, and partly due to the fact that those field difference surface secondaries have reactions of their own which cause them to screw themselves rapidly through the solar field in a direction away from the sun, the tail would form. Obviously, the lighting-up of the comet and the for- mation of the tail would take place gradually as the sun is approached, and die away as the comet recedes (and both are clearly functions of the comet’s mass, speed, etc.,—or, in general, of the comet’s balance of W and A). f. Also, certain sizes of those tail secondaries would ob- viously not be in the necessary harmony of proportion to sur- vive. Sothere would be a preponderance of certain elements in the tail. Also, there would be a 3-dimension balancing of Two XII §120h elements in the tail, (1) in the direction of the axis of the tail; and (2) because of the swinging of the tail, markedly in the two dimensions at right angles or radially from that axis. In Saturn the balancing of the condensations in the ring was practically perceptible in twodimensions:- radially from Sat- urn in the plane of the ring, forming concentric rings. Be- cause Saturn moves in an orbit tilted with respect to its rings there would theoretically actually be a component of balanc- ing across the thickness of those rings. Such has not been noticed: there is a remote possibility that it might he per- ceptible if looked for. Consequently, we have the ‘elements’ of the tail being periodically separated or sifted out in 3-dimension “‘fans’’ and “‘knobs’’ and ‘‘kinks,’’ etc. And such phenomena are actually observed. A comet’s tail is therefore obviously a 3-dimension ‘molar’ or ‘chemical’ spectrum; or, the tail gives an automatic ‘‘analysis’’ of the whirls which can survive. So the description of comets’ tails requires volumes, omitted at this point and practically un- known to me. As a matter of rather obvious fact, the greater part of the volumes J mention omitting is unknown to me. g. Obviously, if the field of Saturn were in some way rudely disturbed in the proper direction, the field would give birth to a secondary that would be, with nearly certain prob- ability, a small comet. Also, it would partake of the com- ponents of motion of the Saturn whirl. Hence, usually it would not be in harmony, either in size or orbit, with comets formed in the outer solar field. So except in rare cases a Saturn comet would not survive long, but would most prob- ably be swallowed up by Saturn on the passing of the dis- turbance. That shows that the tendency in the solar system, so far as its internal processes are concerned (and if not “in- terferred with’ by outside systems), is to keep on in the one direction of ‘condensing’; for a large whirl in it can reverse (as Saturn was there seen to do hypothetically), but does not do so except temporarily. Hence, most of the comets prob- ably come from beyond Neptune; possibly some are born in the vestiges of the solar filament, and a few small weak ones may come from the Saturn or the Jupiter whirl. h. A comet may be bom at the solar field difference surface, either into the solar system or out of it—any asym- metry there obviously forming a comet or secondary (§98w). But when comets are born into the solar system, in precisely the same way as seen in the last paragraph (by the theory of periodicity) only comets of some certain sizes could survive very long—others being quickly assimilated. (And as an obvious incidental fact, the formation of comets of any ap- preciable size would mostly take place into the equatorial parts of the solar whirl field, because the flat polar parts of the field are more stable.) As those field surface comets are obviously directly analogous to electrons, it becomes obvious why electrons (i. e., electrons in an explicitly conventional sense:- those given aff by “‘atoms’’) are roughly of a certain proportional size, and why any disturbance of atoms produces electrons. We see at once, again in complete agreement with the last paragraph, that a comet born zzto the solar sys- tem would have practically no chance of traveling very far into the solar system in its original form. It would be mak- ing a considerable disturbance of equilibrium along its path, and unless the solar system had received a severe jolt (which seems to be improbable in its present rather isolated loca- tion), the comet nearly surely would not be large enough to get far without being assimilated. And that agrees with the observed fact that no comet yet measured seems to have come from outside the solar system; it also agrees with num- erous facts about electrons. The comet from outside quite likely stirs up the solar system more or less to start a comet in the regular way; and that is equivalent to saying that the §120h XII Two comet from outside does swing around the sun, but that it has changed its quantitative character and thereafter is a solar system comet—has been ‘assimilated’ in that way. And quite possibly such a comet, in being assimilated, starts a series of reactions which wil] in turn cause the solar system to give owt a comet—so that an observer outside might think he saw a comet pass through the solar system, whereas the electron or comet that came out was composed of quite dif- ferent materials, and was variously different otherwise. We may observe that the way our own physiological cells ‘‘assimi- late’’ food, or “‘eat,’’ is quite analogous to this comet or electron formation. The cell and its molecules will turn the food into its ‘‘own substance,’’ just as comets are finally to some extent assimilated by the sun; and part of the food will necessarily (it is necessary or truistic because ultimately there is no symmetry or commensurability in any part) start some series of reactions that will cause a ‘comet’ to be given off by (say) some molecule, which rejected part is ‘‘not wanted’’ or a poison (XVI). It is obviously all a matter of quantitative variations in sizes, etc.; the principles are the same: for when we consider that process of assimilation with respect to a biologic cell, molecules of various sorts are taken in, instead of electrons, and then molecules of different sorts from those taken in are observed to be rejected—show- ing in another way that the electron absorbed by an atom is different from the one given out. i. So it is obvious that perhaps most of the comets would come swinging in to the sun on orbits considerably elongated; in fact, in practice it is difficult to distinguish some from parabolas. And because of the obvious theoreti- ca] interference of fields, and to the gravity pulls of planets, numbers of comets are likely to be slowed into short orbits— and such is the orbserved fact (incidentally there is a per- ceptible harmonic periodicity to the sizes of comets’ orbits). The comet with the shortest orbit yet observed is Encke’s, with a period of about 3.29 years. And that comet percept- ibly fails to obey Newton’s law. We have now seen why. Another fact of the same general sort about comets, which shows directly that we must consider fields as well as ordi- nary gravity is the observation that the long axes of their or- bits tend to trail out in the wake of the solar system as it moves in its own orbit about PP’; only the reactions of fields —of A—could produce that phenomena. je Comets are of a comparative size that is unstable. Obviously by our theory, and by direct observation, they break up, and the sun and planets begin to sweep up plan- etesimally the pieces which have thus been transported from the outer parts of the solar system, and from outside the sys- tem. The pieces are called meteors or meteorites (I shall not make the usual minor distinction; see ‘“Ency. Brit.,”’ **Meteor,’’ ‘“Meteorites,’’ for definitions and for details of the observed facts I use). The earth sweeps up many mete- ors, and we can observe them in flight as shooting stars and fireballs, and examine the occasional ones which survive until they reach the earth and are found. It has been estimated by astronomers that 400 million meteors telescopically visible fall on the earth each 24 honrs. k. Some of those meteors fall as fireballs, which, accord- ing to the vague observations available, seem to be clusters of condensations (minature systems) that definitely form whirls in our atmosphere—seem to be definitely comets in our atmosphere. The meteors which reach the earth show only two definite molar structural formations:- (1) tbere is evidence of their surfaces having been heated; and (2) often these are chondrules or spherules (roundish grains varying in size from microscopic to that of a walnut) imbedded in a rock matrix. The obvions explanation of those chondrules is that UNIVERSE 132 they are planetesimal condensations with hot surfaces and hence rounded forms that rain down upon a hot-surface nu- cleus in a comet, and are imbedded there—sometimes the nucleus afterwards being broken up by some large unbalance. A reference to the Art. ““Meteorite’’ will show that no other explanation is probable. So we have here direct experi- mental evidence of the whirl theory or some equivalent one, and of the fact that heavenly bodies are relatively cold in- side. A comet exhibiting chendrules would probably be of average size, whatever that may be; for obviously, larger ones would melt the rain of planetesimals more or less homo- geneously into the remainder of the nuclear substance, and small ones would not be hot enough to imbed chondrules. 8121. a. It has been repeatedly seen tbat there can be no perfectly fluid whirls, or on the other hand perfect spheri- cal condensations which would exhibit Newton’s monistic gravity. Always by consistent mechanics there must be dif- ference surfaces giving off an infinite regress of secondaries— or any actual body must be in some intermediate stage of being a nebula of which the zero-infinity limits are (1) a nnit fluid perfect whirl with no secondaries, and (2) a unit perfect solid sphere with no interacting body. That sentence sum- marizes this chapter in concrete terms of the One and Many. b. It therefore follows that the sun, earth, moon, Jupi- ter, comets, etc., would each severally, and all as a sum, have in some degree an accompanying nebulosity. Comets have that nebulosity in marked degree—being often accom- panied by its extension into a tail. Also, in full agreement with our verbal truisms of description, the sun, and earth, and probably the moon, have nebnlosity which is visually perceptible to us. And we shall see implicitly in electricity (XIV) that any body has electrical fields, which are always experimentally perceptible if its relative motion is sufficiently great; and those fields are equivalent to nebulosity. The nebulosity of the other planets is too far off and tenuous to have been noticed yet, except for that of the young Saturn. ce. That nebulosity which surrounds the sun is faintly visible to us as the zodiacal light. The similar nebulosity of the earth is named the Gegenschein (for description and more detailed observations, see ‘‘Ency. Brit.,’’ ‘’Zodiacal Light’’). The nebulosity of the moon has not with positive certainty been observed, and it has not been named; obviously its visibility would be interferred with by those other two nebu- losities. | Such nebulosities would probably be somewhat self-luminous (agreeing with Angstrom’s observations in the article cited :—and in spite of the fact that they are in space usually held to be at nearly absolute zero); also, they would be luminous by diffused and reflected light (as our atmos- phere is—they being obviously composed largely of thin gases that are known to exist in the ‘‘free’’ space about us). The nebulosities have probably been observed to vary in po- sition, and perhaps to exhibit some traces of tails: they seem to have a variable tilt, and seem to react mutually, Allsuch observations obviously agree with whirl mechanics. 8122. a. It has been seen (§112g-1) that the reaction of the solar whirl] field and galaxy field gives our general clim- ate. We shall now see that the whirl theory consistently gives minor climatic variations by the same principles—see- ing it by considering the reactions of the sun’s spherical field with the earth’s spherical or magnetic field. Also it follows implicitly, but of course in far less quantitative ae ae at eee a moon’s field on ours modify phases is ae whol] en see ne hale 4 nae Seer his rules of thumb ae ae Pige pecuen pean merely racial Sane tiie eee puget when the earth and moon eee pe tne ee days were in a younger whirl, and their 133 mutual field reactions were much stronger. Even the old astrology is not completely stupid; for millions of years ago when (say) Jupiter swept near the earth spiral, it probably knocked off an earth satellite which plunged into the earth in a way somewhat disconcerting to live things in those days. Astrology was perhaps perceptibly justified in some measure. Of course the intellectual] grafters exaggerated it and ritual- ized it until it became silly; they will do the same for this book unless men take the trouble to observe for themselves. Those grafters were not deep-dyed villains; they merely de- sired to give their clients their money’s worth, and hence “‘improved’’ their yarns to give them sufficient violence— pep and punch and heart interest—to jolt even the weak brains of their stupid dupes, and thus give them a sensation to vary the ‘‘monotony’’ that is another name for an inactive mind. Also, the dupes wouldn’t rely on themselves, but relied too much on ‘‘experts’’—with the usual result that both they and the experts (named astrologers then) came to grief. All too specialized specialists are dangerous. b. The chief cause of those minor disturbances of the sun’s spherical field, and hence of the earth’s field and hence climate, is obviously the eccentric revolution of various bodies around the sun. Possibly the most intense of those variations are the passages through perihelion of comets, or the remains of comets; obviously those comets then stir np the sun’s spherical] field sharply. c. When one of those sharp knocks on the sun’s field occurs, obviously there would shortly be secondary whirl] for- mation at the sun’s difference surface, which ‘surface’ is con- ventionally divided into chromosphere (at the bottom), photosphere, corona, and zodiacal light (““Ency. Brit.,’’ Art. *‘Sun’’). Similar knocks on the earth’s field would also pro- duce secondary whirls here; those whirls are directly per- ceptible to us as cyclones and anti-cyclones in the atmosphere (which is part of the difference surface of the earth). < Owners... is States... < Government... (named “‘states’ rights’’). The problem of plain slavery was too easy to solve if kept in the simple buman terms Slaves... Owners...: many aristocrats could not blind themselves to the fact that there were not many perceptible *“blessings of liberty’’ for tbe slaves. | So those exploiters evaded in tbe age-old way—putting the problem into larger or wider terms to confuse the issue, and in some degree to hide their own wrongness from themselves (a sort of reverse make believe). (I speak with no animus against former slave owners, but sympathetically give simply the obvious facts: my own fam- ily on both sides lost their slaves by the Civil war.) Clearly the problem of slaves and the problem of states’ rights are identical in principle. To assert that states have a right to withdraw from the union is equivalent to asserting that there exists a right for men to try to separate and hecome fixedly apart, just as slaves and owner are (nominally ; but impossibly in fact). Such an assertion is also in direct contradiction of the contract made in the Constitution, which requires the as- sentof both parties to terminate. No such assertion will ever be true (except ina quantitative sense, when men degenerate and are quantitatively unable to hold together in as large a union as now; cf. 8176). Always exploiters will try to put §173f XIX Three that same simple principle of the Constitution—balanced co- operation—into wider terms. But with a rigorous solution of the One and Many we shall be very stupid if we get confused and exploited. Quite often in history the Monroe doctrine has been given an imperialistic, aristocratic interpretation by the dualists; but as the reader may readily see that by writing a few formulas we will not go intoit; also, see footnote I172c. g. The Constitution thus made first a balance between government officials and the remainder of the people; and then a balance between all the parts into which the people were arbitrarily or conveniently divided. In short, it explic- itly abolished privilege, or aristocracy, or unearned power or other unearned perquisites. And it did not do that in any sweet, sentimental, vague way: it got right down to definite measures, to L and T science, to ““brass tacks,’’ with such precision that it worked pretty well. The Constitution is science of the highest order. And as it was made by the whole people it is another indication of the fact that the im- portant average or majority judgments of men are sound. h. Then the Constitution proceeds to the details of the government officials. It makes a balance of executive and of legislative branches, relating them by the judiciary, thus :- Legislature...(<-Judiciary, or Jurisprudence— )Executive...= Government. The Constitution, in the absence of its makers’ specific knowledge as to relationship terms, is a trifle vague verbally or formally as to the judiciary; but it obviously as- serts that formula, which implies all the sound principles. The judiciary in reality has no power in the usual sense, but is merely a connecting link or relationship that interprets, or makes each branch ‘perceptible’ to the other. The judiciary is the sociological governmental Holy Ghost (in wider sense, ‘“public opinion’’ is—represented mostly by the press). The judiciary, having no power, is hence, so long as it attends to its legitimate and constitutionally allowed business, and keeps away from holding the lawyers’ law, truistically in no danger of becoming power-mad; so with implicit recognition of that, the framers did not put a definite time limit on the terms of judges. Obviously, the business of the judiciary is to say what is truth; the truth has what is commonly ac- cepted as one form of power, that of “‘prevailing’’—i. e., of simply being, or existing:- as the ultimate relationship of identity (§28bh). The press has ““power’’ only as it tells the truth. The judiciary and the writers as such truistically have no power: insofar as they are diligent in finding truth and honest and skillful and courageous in giving it to others they are good workmen and deserve high payment—aznd that pay which is then theirs to spend is their power. but, as we see below, by unconstitutional lawyers’ law the judiciary is the agent of a superior sovereign, andas such has power (both delegated power, which ultimately is the only sort anybody can have, and the nominally first-hand power of in effect leg- islating). If the lawyers do not agree that all that is true, then they automatically assert that the Judiciary should be given a term limited in time or else terminable at will without cause by the sovereign (and they also automatically assert that their job is not to find the truth and state it, etc.). I am quite aware that Marshall in effect disagreed with the view that the judiciary has no actual power constitutionally ; by so doing he proved himself a poor thinker and incompe- tent judge. To give crucial evidence of Marshall’s errors :- He (together with the notoriously aristocratic imperialist Hamilton) held that a state is sovereign in a lawyers’ dual- istic sense, and can not be sued without its consent (Bryce, ‘““American Commonwealth,’’ New York, 1908, p. 235). That view truistically makes the judiciary the agent of the sovereign and thus gives it power (which as a matter of hist- tory and common law—which common law the Constitution UNIVERSE 236 in direct effect enunciates as law—was long ago in England forcibly taken away from the judiciary). And in general proof of all that, in direct legal terms, the Su- preme court, before Marshall was on it, with ordinary com- monsense and reason, decided that the Constitution did not hold a state to be thus sovereign (Bryce, ibid., 235). Asa result of that, and probably of Marshall’s and the lawyers’ and exploiters’ dualistic views, Amend. XI was added in 1798 (‘the judicial power of the United States shall not be con- strued to extend to any suit in law or equity commenced or prosecuted against any one of the United States, by citizens of another State, or by citizens or subjects of any foreign State’). By that states have in practice repudiated their debts, and otherwise acted as a capricious ‘‘sovereign’’ in an immoral and unbusiness-like way—like a robber baron, or a dead-beat kaiser or panper. According to its practical and to its customary legal interpretation, that Amendment is the one blot or error in the Constitution. By the Constitution (strictly interpreted: see below), and by all natural law, no state is absolutely sovereign; neither is the Federal govern- ment; and so constitutionally all are liable for damages for any mistakes, and subject to suits. (To admit that would be simple 17h That interpretation (that he considered the judiciary the agent of the ‘‘sovereign’’) is the most charitable opinion to take of Marshall’s views; and J have adopted it because I haven’t bothered to read munch of Marshall’s autocratic dictums. J am inclined to be- lieve that the historic fact is that Marshall was much more unintelli- gent and irresponsibly lacking in knowledge of jurisprudence and its history than that mild opinion indicates. I am inclined to think that he was, with customary irresponsible, aristocratic power-madness, trying to make the judiciary into the orthodox lawyers’ ‘‘sover- eign.’’ And that seems to be the customary view of Marshall’s ex- ploits. That ‘‘sovereign’’ status of the judiciary was historically nearly an invariable phenomenon in all races of the Western world, where aristocracies which claimed to be the depositary and adminis- trators of the law sncceed ‘‘sacred’’ kings (we call that the buying np and capturing of the courts by the rich). And they all regularly failed to work and broke down (Maine, ‘‘An. Law,’’ I), the people demanding that the law be written in codes. And that dualistic and naturally unworkable pseudo judiciary is explicitly provided against in the Constitutiuion, which gives the legislature the duty of enunci- ating laws (so that it is none of the judiciary’s business to legislate), and the executive the duty of examining them and sending them back for reconsideration (if thonght needed), and of executing them. So obviously, all that is left for the judiciary to do is to discover and state the truth (so far as it can) regarding those varions matters (un- fortunately, the Constitution speaks of judicial ‘‘power’’; but obvi- ously, no meaning other than ‘duty to speak truth’ can consistently be got from that carelessly used word). Marshall could have discovered that legal history if he had tried; and a trifle of intelli- gence would have made it clear to him that this present statement of the nature of the judiciary as a truth-stater is the constitutional one. But actually Marshall wasn’t a judge at all: he was a grabber after power—essentially a robber baron, a kaiser, a bar-room bully. So by direct implication—by directly assigning the power elsewhere,—the Constitution prohibits the judiciary (practically, the Supreme court) from issuing any binding or compulsory interpreta- tion or fiat as to a law’s constitutionality. The judiciary can merely try to show the congress and executive that a given law contradicts the Constitution in principle, if it thinks the law does. As we have seen, any matter of principle can be shown rigorously, and so clearly that a child can see it. So if the jndiciary can not show congress and the executive that the Jaw is wrong, and have them repudiate it of their volition, then the law isa law. (Of course, if there is a fre- quent conflict of opinion in such matters, and recalcitration, the gov- ernment would come to a standstill; but the practical solntion is obviously for the people to throw out all its officials, inclnding im- peaching the Supreme court, and get some representatives who haven’t gone power-mad.) Lincoln clearly saw the substance of all that, and stated it at his first inangural (quoted in J. T. Rich- ards’s ‘‘Abraham Lincoln, the Lawyer-Statesman,’’ 170):- ‘‘If the policy of the government upon vital questions affecting the whole people is to be irrevocably fixed by decisions of the Supreme Court *** the people will have ceased to be their own rulers, having to that extent resigned their government into the hands of that emi- nent tribunal.”’ 237 UNIVERSE good business and elementary morality and constitutional law.) Now, by referring to the wording of that Amendment it is at once obvious that the aristocrats did not state openly or definitely what they apparently were trying to get:- the legal right for a state, as absolute sovereign, to repudiate, shirk, any of its acts or contracts (the Constitution repeatedly interdicts that lawyers’ pseudo principle that ““the king can do no wrong,’’ or the pope is infallible, ete.). The Amend- ment does not give or state such a legal! right by its words, but is merely a legal evasive statement of such probable in- tention on the part of the grafters, but undoubtedly not the intention of the majority the grafters pretended to represent. So it is not necessary to repeal that Amendment, for it can obviously be interpreted justly thus:- upon the request to the Federal government of any person who has been refused redress by a state acting on that pseudo principle, the Fed- eral government may, in strict accord with this Amendment, and must, by the rest of the Constitution (and by all natural law and morality), institute a new, separate, and distinct suit of its own against the contract-breaking state for damages to the public welfare, etc. By such good Constitutional law those repudiating states would undergo on their own motion a quick and permanent change of heart, and pay what they still owe. Also, such practice would educate lawyers as to what the Constitution both says and means. i. The expansion of details of the last paragraph must be omitted. We can merely note the most essential fact:- that the Constitution explicitly provides a democratic or balanced-cooperative government or organization of officials, and not the line organization that we saw was flatly wrong in principle (S§37f, 167). The next section implicitly shows the meaning of that. Another important explicit agree- ment of the Constitution with natural law is that Amend. XVI allowing graded income taxes is a definite recognition of the democratic or moral principle (§8167-8) that men are not equa] in a quantitative sense. That same principle is obvi- ously implicitly recognized by every definitely quantitative statement in the Constitution. And that Amendment is ob- viously also competent practically to stop inheritance of un- earned wealth (§168mn), if a definite basic law is needed. j. That makes the Constitution an enactment of al] nat- ural law and moral Jaw—except perhaps it does not definitely assert the morality of economy of time (although the whole of it does promote economy of time, as is implied in the next section), and except that Amend. XI is practically a blot and should be eliminated. $174. a. Many people hold that in practice democracy or the Constitution does not work well. E. g., Faguet thinks so, and gives such views emphatically (and what he fancies is proof of them) in a book called ‘“The Cult of Incompetence’’ —his name for democracy. Many hold that the Prussian autocratic type of organization gets things done, while democ- racy can not—that democracy muddles along in a chuckle- headed way, and wastes, and wastes, and wastes. We have seen that theoretically autocracy, or the line or king or sanc- tion type of organization is absolutely wrong and can not possibly exist in reality. | For, autocracy requires theoreti- cally an absolute superior to hand down orders without there being areverse, equal reaction (“Theirs not to make reply’’). Autocracy tries to go to infinity—claims in theory that it does. Socialism goes in the opposite direction from autocracy—to zero, in its impossible dualistic or equally aristocratic theory ; i. e., (as we see in §175) it theoretically has nobody giving orders (or as everybody is explicitly a government official, the government is 0 or ©, just as we choose to say). Obvi- ously, in a strict theoretical sense both socialism and autocracy are impossible (Part One; specifically, Index, Increase of Three XIX §174¢ entropy’’); and the two are essentially identical (as 0 and ~ logically are the same), merely going in opposite directions. But if we take the two in a quantitative sense, as species of actually existing organizations which therefore truistically do not strictly go to those extreme limits that in a Many or act- ual sense are impossible, then necessarily the two are merely attempis to depart, in the two respective directions, from the balance; see Figs. 104b, 163b. So both are persistent in- temperances or aristocratic, and both are immoral and kill. Democracy is obviously simply the temperate mean hetween the two. We shall look at some of the practical details of that very simple principle—that of That... This... or of Social- ism...(<—Democratie reactions—)Autocracy... (cf. Fig. 104b). A more or less autocratic ruler (no absolute one is pos- sible) will usually get a thing done in a shorter time than a democracy will (if he gets it done at all). But it is not done so well or so completely. Ifhe keeps on for a while getting the same thing done, its accumulated deficiencies in com- pleteness of being done (in L, formally) will amount to its not being done. Or, the autocracy will blow up, go to pieces, change iuto another sort of structure (cf. recent hist- ory; and change of structure in Part Two resulting from any persistent accumulation of potential). b. g, Education worthy the name is truistically an all- ’round’’ education (one that at least in effect recognizes the infinite regress) which finally gives ability to estimate the meas- ures of men, and hence to react cooperatively with them. Aristo- cratic ideas of education considerably neglect that summing up, erroneously emphasizing the need of an accumulation of facts. Just an accumulation of facts is not education—a tru- ism so obvious that I shall not waste the reader’s time with a proof of it. Democracy gives balanced education, as seen; so circularly, valid education gives democracy. So truistically, a sound education gives ability to be useful to others. It is not a private affair in which the scholar stuffs himself with more or less dead and rather useless classics and then fancies that he feels pleased because he has spent so much time prinking his brain, and is superior in knowing UNIVERSE Three XIX §175c rather duhiously applicable stuff. All facts can be useful, of course (just as the kaiser is beautiful; §25c). So education is measured by its practical or Many usefulness—which is the same as saying that we must apply to it the theory of value ($168). The most definite measure of usefulness is money. So Taylor’s principles of educating or management, which insist that at least some money measurement be required, soundly formulate a democratic measuring rod that had been increasingly used by men as they have developed in keen- ness, delicacy, and definiteness of perception or living. $175. a. As noted in §174a, socialism is essentially the same aristocracy as autocracy: it merely would strive to be intemperate by going in the other direction from the balance (Figs. 163b, 104b). Autocracy would go to the extreme Many limit of having one man give all orders, with no reac- tion: socialism would go to the opposite extreme of having everybody “‘equal’’ in the government, so that again there is no reaction. There is little agreement as to what “‘socialism’’ means. I shall give a consistent statement of its possible meanings, assuming that it is different in some way from democracy and autocracy; and if people who cal] themselves socialists can not find their beliefs included in those meanings, then they are in some degree either demo- crats or autocrats, and would be more intelligible if they named themselves conventionally. b. Numbers of high-minded and generally admirable men view the race as being very emphatically an organism, or a One. It is, of course. Then they call that One socialism. Or, they name the universal) relationship of identity or *“brotherhood,”’ socialism. Obviously, as a One word, or as a relationship or Holy Ghost word, socialism is permissible and sound. But sociology, or some such phrase as communion of saints or human equality or brotherhood of man, is the more conventional One name or relationship name. In that sense socialism is of course a synonym for democracy, or for any other of the numerous One words or relationship words—and is of course absolutely ineffable, meaning nothing definite nntil it is put in positive That... x This... terms. Many of those admirable One socialists admit that they can not give such a statement. They simply mean that they prefer to be religious in terms of human beings:- Other men... X Us...= Socialism, or Human equality (i. e., 1pENTITY), or Religion. Us- ually those men begin to describe democracy as well as they can when they shift to positive Many words; in practice they are democrats, with a tendency to have more faith than the average in the capabilities of government officials —which of course makes them better men than those who have a faith less than the actual facts warrant. The objection to such high-minded or religious socialism is that it does not say what it means very well, and sois a cat’s-paw for scoundrels. c. The socialist who expresses himself in Many terms, especially the extreme socialist, usually definitely states his aristocratic belief in fixed classes—and their antagonism. In practice at any rate, his difference from the autocrat is that he believes that jis class, the proletariat or ‘“working’’ class, is the **superior,’”’ and should rule—and should, as the mildest view, seize all property and distribute it ““equally,’’ what- ever that may mean. The justification for that is that autoc- racy doesn’t work, and is unjust [that is true; but it does not justify the same methods by a different set of men|. Such definite socialism was mostly made in Germany, largely by Marx—although the idea and practice of socialism is older than the race (see next paragraph). (The technical logical objection to Marxian and Many socialism is that it is materi- alistic—a dualism so obvious that I won’t waste the reader’s time with formal statement of it.) The reason is ob- vious why the socialist should fancy himself the opposite of §175c XIX Three the autocrat in principle, whereas he is merely opposite in direction and is also an aristocrat:- The autocrat does have a perception of the natural relationship or ultimate identity of men. So he vigorously does something about it: he pro- ceeds to organize men, so that they percepiiby to themselves get that religion in terms of humanity—and along with that fuller mental life truistically get a higher material standard of living. The autocrat naturally exaggerates that idea and doing, in order to pound it into the duller people, and he shortly reaches the limit of zs capacity and begins to fancy that he personifies the relationship—that being the divine right of kings (and the weak ones he lifted out of animal sav- agery also highly appraise that great work). The autocrat does act by the idea that if a little is good more is better: but I have trouble myself seeing in practice that that isn’t so past the point of balance, and nobody can judge exactly where that point comes. A socialist sees that relationship of man, and he sees the autocrat’s mistake of going too far. So the socialist thinks he can personify that relationship by talking about itand keeping everybody from the intemperance of the other or more material sort of doing into which the autocrat fell. And the socialist promptly falls into talking intemper- ately—personifying himself more or less as a sort of abstract mouthpiece of the divine human race. And his verbal intem- perance is usually atrocious. As seen, democrats try to balance “‘talking’’ and ‘‘doing’’—in practice act on the fact that mind zs matter. So truistically they are conscious that ultimate relationship, unfailing cause and effect, does exist, and that there is no need to exaggerate either aspect. So democrats do not have to symbolize the divine right of the autocrat or the socialist by a lot of fuss and feathers, a special ship and entourage to get to Paris, glittering uni- forms, high masses, the dirty collar and hair of the ““high’’ thinker, etc. The objection to those symbols (more import- ant than the time and money they waste) is that we are prone to forget that they are symbols, and take the idol for the re- ality. Indemocracy the real boss or acting person constantly changes, the person who gives the reaction becoming the boss or acting person. (Of course a moderate amount of sym- bolization of the person who is expected to do certain acting is convenient.) The essential thing that makes red tape be red tape is that a Many formality is erroneously substituted for an existing relationship: red tape is idolatry in trivial things for trivial people. d. Socialism therefore truistically means in theory abso- lute government ownership, everybody a government official, and no division of labor. So there is nothing novel about the practice of socialism. It is simply a new name for the way in which ‘‘solitary’? wild animals live:- | Each member of the species (except when nature forces some democracy upon him in the form of temporary family: perfect socialism is im- possible) takes what he wants when he wants it (or else fights for it, if another animal disputes the want). He does every- thing especially for himself, and hence gets all he produces. I. e., property is common; and there is substantially no spec- ialization of work with its necessary reactions or ‘law’ or ‘ordering’ between individuals. Each animal is in the “gov- ernment,’’ holding an office equal to any other (except for unavoidable natural sex, etc.), with natural result that there is no government in any ordinary sense. Clearly, perfect socialism implies (1) an impossible quantitative equality, or (2) the impossibility that two finite beings can not interfere in finite space. But the sincere socialists can join (if I may say ‘join’) the solitary animals and at once have their Utopia as closely as nature permits. Thus socialism practically is extreme savagery. Most savage tribes of men are on the up- ward path to democracy via a violent autocratic reaction from UNIVERSE 240 that worse savagery. —— Ina One sense we all are in the government, and we all are equal (to the universe or God or infinity——which ought to be enongh to satisfy a reasonable person), and all property is under the government (even the common law asserts that). e. Possibly no socialist would urge going tothe extreme of animal savagery. But it has become obvious that both the socialist and the autocrat are aristocratically fancying that they should (in opposite directions) get a government with fixed classes—with of course jixed superiority (and its ma- terial symbol or measure:- money or property) for his re- spective class. Both being contrary verbally to natural law, each fancies he is fighting the other: actually, the two are naturally interacting, but doing it somewhat violently and painfully—nature’s method of pounding sense through to their consciousness. The democrat is the man with sufficient intelligence to see the actual principle, and to desire a bal- anced cooperation of Citizens and their property... X Official government and its property..., or Labor... Capital... .*"° Me Ultimately, all the unbalanced theories of the socialists and of the autocrats are simply a demand for more life, more activity, more ‘‘good.’’ Those unbalanced theories are-is a selfish demand— an excessive demand—of ignorant persons for the right to live—for self-preservation. And that demand usually practically takes the form of a demand for the ownership of property—regardless of the disguises it may wear. We saw (§164d) that it is a fundamental law that all of us, as a payment for existing ourselves, must allow others the “‘right’’ to exist. So far we mostly have discussed that ‘‘right’’ in terms of people—giving democratic reactions between people. But it was definitely stated that the right to exist trnistically involves the need or ‘‘right’’ to react with so-called material things. And such things are property, as we shall now see (money is the general repre- sentative or measure of property; §168h). Mostly 1 have discussed relations with people because people are perceptibly moving and vari- able, so that the balancing of reactions with them is more difficult than a balancing with property, which is less variable and exacting than people:- land will not usually move away, or actively hit back; and a cow is not so difficult to react with as a sponse. __ So it is com- paratively easy to get the principles of property and keep balanced with property. But that does not lower the intrinsic importance of property in human life. In any normal life it is just as imperative that property be temperately owned and handled as it is that we be temperate in other things. 1 mnst omit volumes of details of prop- erty: but such details are important, and must in actual life be given an equal place with personal or so-called spiritual democracy. Clearly, if by agreement we allow the ‘‘right’’ of existence to each normal man, we trnistically allow some similar quantitative right to the ‘‘material’’ means of existence:- food, shelter, clothing, etc. Thus we allow a right to property:- for if anyone deprives a man of material air or materia] water, the man will die; and the same prin- ciple applies to all other property in varying quantitative degree. Volumes on that variation in degree must be omitted (e. g., just what does a stockholder in a holding company own?). But we may here summarize, and consider the essential part of the right to property :- which is the indispensable right to ‘‘own’?’ (i. c., as surely and posi- tively control, or anticipate-all-the-reactions-of, as is humanly pos- sible in such a quantitative matter) land, that is possessed by cach person, and includes the eqnally indispensable right to some water, air, and produce, that goes with the land. The principle of each per- son’s right to such property is that truistically he has the right in proportion to his own reactive or cooperative measure of worth as a person (with proper distribution as to 7 during his life-time—a huge quantitative subject of pensions, minors, ete., which | omit). If his reactions with other men havea given value or quantity, then as a simple truism he hasa right to control or own an amount of land which is the same fraction of the total land (measured by its useful- ness or desirability) as his work is of the total of all men’s work (measured the same way). So obviously, as the next inevitable tru- ism, socialistic talk about dividing property equally is glaringly im- moral, as men are not quantitatively equal. That principle of ownership needs volumes of expansion into practical details. The chief need in that expansion is to consider the matter dynamically. One of the gravest troubles men have had has been in more or less accepting the static, dnalistic proposition that if a man once gets legal possession that possession becomes a jixed, unchangeable fact, an eternal aristocratic ‘‘privilege’’—so that property accumulates by inheritance in the hands of a privileged few who neither earned it in 241 f. Men ordinarily are normally at a given time some- what slightly unbalanced pleasurably either towards more centralization or autocracy in official government, or else to- wards more socialism. Those varying classes form two nat- ural parties; but it is not possible to give steady names to the two, for as soon as a party becomes too violently auto- cratic (e. g., the Wilson administration) it automatically flops over or reverses to a dangerously exaggerated socialism. And as both extremes are radical, names of parties tend to reverse——as has occurred several] times in our history (and during the confusion a substantial third party arises tempor- arily). So truistically the most highly moral or balanced man will change from one party to another, remaining always in opposition to the party which is most unbalanced. The in- telligent men thus hold the balance of power in a democracy. g. Asa practical fact, Marxian and similar socialists are rather ignorant persons, and fail to see the difficulties of man- aging a large organization, and particularly of getting one made. They rather fancy that simply to name a man gen- eral manager will automatically enable him to run the largest railroad properly—will make him zn facta general manager— overlooking the truth that actually generations of toughening and sharpening of nerve fiber is needed as an educative pre- liminary to prepare a man to begin to ‘see’ a railroad system. So the ignorant and sentimentalists tend to want government ownership expanded. And there are many selfish persons calling themselves socialists who think that they can manage to grab an easy job if there are enough available—thereby in effect admitting that they expect to see socialism fail. Those socialists are in principle identical with the autocratic politic- ian who in bis heart believes that ‘‘to the victor belong the spoils.’” On the other hand, the autocrats, with a stupidity going in the opposite direction, exaggerate the dif- ficulties of that job; but by then inconsistently fancying that they personally can measure up to it, at least in prestige, *‘pull,’’ ete., they insist that it be quietly given to them to be run by divine right. The democrat has to estimate men in fair agreement with the facts, and steer between those aristocratic exaggerations. Being a democrat is a hard job. 8176. a. So the success of any human organization de- pends upon the size of men. The limit of tbe organization here is one man reacting democratically with all the other people in the world, as a perceptible organic whole, or as a world state or league. b. That single organization would, from the human fact nor pay for its continued possession (except by personal deteri- oration and crippling; §168d). Socialism is the natural reaction against that erroneous static view; socialism usually exaggerates equally in the opposite direction. But at the same time even the autocrats usually accepted theoretically the principle which annulled or compensated for that exaggerated static practice:- that the legal owner of property owed continued proportional pay to other peo- ple in return, usually called a tax. And as we shall see (footnote 176d), owners paid too much as taxes (bnt apart from that brief note I must omit that vast dynamic expansion). The compensation made for their error by the socialists is their personal discomfort and all- ‘ound fajlure and more or Jess approach to animal-like squalor, that gives us the valuable evidence that we do not want socialism (as a well known practical fact, as soon as socialists bestir themselves todo something more than talk, the primitive savagery they begin to exper- ience is ample Jesson for them, and they reverse to a rather extreme autocracy). My general guess about property is that there has been and is now an astonishingly just perceptible distribution of wealth; but people’s statements of the principles on which they fancied they accomplished that distribution are just as astonishingly contradictory—being one long series of emphatic the simple fact that as both socialism and au- tocracy in practice say they will take your property if they can, it is the part of wisdom—except in democracies, where the reverse holds —to conceal what you have, bow you got it and where, and what you are going to do with it, etc.). wrong and self- make believes (due to UNIVERSE Three XIX §176b point of view, chiefly require a man of so much strength that he would not go power-mad; and of such keenness of vision for details that he would not be afraid of too many unknowns and as a result be the opposite of power-mad, and so worry himself into uselessness and red-tape (all autocrats, circularly, have attacks of timid red-tape; ef. §169h). Or, the nominal head of the people of the world could be a commit- tee of some sort—a collection of men. However, one man (by the principle that no two men are quantitatively equal) would actually at any given time lead the committee and be the head of the world. But, in the usual committee the men are so nearly equal that no one man can in fact lead for long; so the responsibility is practically divided, with the truistic result that the committee is a socialism, and dawdles along not doing much; and even worse, when the committee is so large as to be called a congress, the nearly-equal mem- bers are liable to spend time in childish bickering, irrelevant to their duties, in what is actually a comparison of strength —unless some man is strong enough to sit on them. The advantage of a committee is that if the strongly-working real manager of it goes power-mad he grows weak, and another man in the committee is in duty bound to replace him: the committee-scheme automatically puts the proper time limit on its members. A committee is also a device that allows the person or persons who select it to have several guesses as to who is the man able to do the work. Soa committee, or triumvirate, or legislature, etc., is ise/f in principle a rather unconscious or slow-moving democracy, which inclines toward being a socialism if the members are mediocre and about equal, and toward autocracy if it has strong members who begin to go power-mad. And from the point of view of environment, that world state, if it is to be a fairly per- ceptible democracy (is to exist in fact), requires that there be sufficient celerity and explicitness of communication, both mental and material, between that one man and the others to enable him and them to act and react perceptibly (and similarly, but in varying degree, between any and all other combinations of men). E. g., if some men steadily insisted on departing from the democratic balance, then that one man must have that fact communicated to him soon enough to en- able him to react (before they went far enough to damage themselves or others much)—that being an effort to educate them into a desire to go towards the balance. Then if after reasonable reaction of that sort they continued to act so as to break up the democracy, the communication should be suffic- iently good to enable others to see that the recalcitrant or ““lawless’’ ones were defective in some degree, and to have them either restrained, or killed, as expedient. Evidently, communication inside the United States is such as to enable the Constitutional government and the people (who have been trained into sense enough to use it) to do precisely that —and do it rather definitely, although slowly in come diff- cult cases. But I think it is obvious that it could not have been done here two centuries ago. So from the point of view of communication, a world state at present will work with some perceptible defects. | The principles of harmonic periodicity will apply to it: and so it is quantitatively pos- sible that a world state would be of such a size that if nomi- nally formed it might be out of harmony with other world quantities and break down—with disastrous damage in the exploding. | On the other hand, communication is now so good that we already have considerable of the opposite de- fect:- of being pained because we have messages or things we can send and want to send to others, and there is no or- ganized (definite) agreement that those others will take them. If we arbitrarily get in the way of a world state that by the same principles of periodicity is about to form ‘‘naturally,’’ §176b XIX Three we also shall get hurt, justas if we stood in front of a moving train. And as communication (under a steady climate) is constantly improving, that pain is constantly increasing; and we shall be forced sooner or later definitely to organize the communications (establish a world state), just as the thirteen colonies bad so much trouble that they substantially had to make the Constitution. It is a question of quantitative judgment as to what we ought to do now. c. So if we think we can steadily get a man who is of sufficient size (replacing him fast enough to keep him from going power-mad or the opposite, and at the same time be- ing able to leave him in office long enough to learn the job), and if we also think that communication is good enough, and if we think that the varions peoples have sense enough to try to react democratically a little (to “‘hold up their end’’), it follows that we shall be consciously conforming with natural law to establish a world state. We of course are already more or less in a world state—in a universal state, for that matter (with gravity reactions, etc.). If we had a more conscious, more explicitly organized state, it would truistic- ally give a more abundant life, in terms of cash and every- thing else. But if we pretend to run a world state and in fact do not, we destroy some of our life (unless we have the strength to pay highly for a while for the education, and are able to survive the violent civil war explosions). So if we fail to start a world state at once it is because we are afraid to tackle the unknown and do not amount to much as men, unless there is fair quantitative evidence that it would fail, in which case to start it would be reckless stupidity. In that latter case the part of wisdom is to build up a world state gradually for a while longer by more definite treaties, postal and similar conventions, international courts, etc. (which is precisely what the thirteen colonies did for some years, un- consciously acquiring education for the final definite crystal- lization). It is a quantitative problem. No man can be absolutely sure which way it should be decided. I omit my opinion in the matter (see footnote 172c). d. If itbe decided to start a world state, the determina- tion of the principles of the organization is easy. They are in our Constitution, and are simply the principles of democ- racy, or of That... X This.... There being no exact science, the application of those principles truistically will not work perfectly. No man, from his personal or imperfect Many point of view can be satisfied with a fairly just democ- racy or balance; from such a point of view any sort of fair balance ina world state involves his making ‘‘sacrifices.’’ But those are bis payments for what he gets in return. We have seen throughout the book that it is impossible to get some- thing for nothing. Because consciousness is life, truistically the intelligent man wants to know he pays, and how much; and the highly intelligent man (as shown in §8164db, 169b, footnote 174¢) wants to initiate payment—pay first; sacrifice. We need an apparent digression:- that it is thus rigorously truistic that an indirect tax is wrong, immoral, and bad busi- ness (i. e., in a democracy; in an aristocracy it is an evil needed to compensate; cf. last of footnote 175e). 176d Those remarks on taxation, and the more explicit remarks in par. g below on tariffs, are true only in rigorous theory. As will im- plicitly appear, customary methods of indirect taxation more or less correct conventional errors in principles of taxation; and such prac- tical balancing is of course correct. The orthodox theory of taxation is that taxes are “‘a self-levied contribution which each man pays according to his ability’’ (Hadley, ‘‘Economics,’’ §498) so that it becomes an unsolved’ question “‘whether we should try to tax the strong man at a relatively higher rate than the weak man’’ (ibid, §517). Thus it appears that the orthodox theory is uncertain; but that there is a general view that in strict justice all men should pay an equal fraction of what they receive, although orthodoxly, in prac- tice perhaps it is better to tend towards having the poor or weak man UNIVERSE 942 Most of the people who agreed to our Constitution made sac- rifices, and were willing to do so (as is proved by the fact that they did). That is largely how it happened that the Constitution is so extraordinarily good:- it was consciously paid for by everybody, without any perceptible aristocratic privileges being given as bribes—no “‘log-rolling.’’ To form a world state, various nations would consciously have to pay for the organization at once and would not very perceptibly pay a smaller fraction (speaking in economic terms of concrete wealth). Both those general ideas of taxation (equal fractions; and the weak a smaller faction) are wrong (even with regard to un- earned wealth got in an aristocracy by inheritance or grabbing; then the correct principle is that all which is unearned should be repaid). The successful, ‘‘wealthy’’ man in a democracy, usually in just- ice ought to pay some smaller fraction of the concrete wealth (property; money) he gets, than does the less snecessful, ‘“‘poor’’ man. And it is a continually asserted quantitative fact, which prob- ably is true, that the successful man does thus “‘pay less than his share’’—which probably shows again that we act better than we say in our make believes. And the way we achieve that probably correct result, in the face of a wrong orthodox theory, and sometimes in the face of actual efforts to make the successful man pay a larger fraction becanse he is ‘‘able’’ to, is to levy indirect or secret taxes. They of course get passed on to the poor nearly entirely (in ways so simple and well known that the person who is not a fool or a self-blinded aristocratic grabber scarcely requires statistical proof of it, although that can be got from many stock-selling circulars); and that serves to restore a correct quantitative balance. The really correct thing to do glaringly is to state openly that an indirect tax is wrong (fit only for savage socialists and barbaric autocrats,and naturally tend- ing to make us similarly blind and partly dead when used on ns), and that we won’t use it but will directly tax everybody, taxing the successfnl some agreed-on smaller faction of their wealth (putting the aristocrats in jail, if such extreme measures are needed to stop their grabbing). The rigorous truism (footnote 175e) is that a man should return to society services equivalent to what he receives (that is the trnism that action equals reaction, which we have seen is universally true; the orthodox theory of taxation is wrong in that it expresses that truism only partially, as we shall see). Obvionsly the ‘successful’? man in a democracy (who is not always rich in concrete property, although he usually is nowadays) is one who of his own initiative or enterprise, or at least without being ‘‘watched”’ or sup- ervised by others at the expense of much of their lives, gives all the work or reaction that he can. The successful man gets useful things done: gives better products and methods, etc., that help us all indi- rectly. The unsuccessful or really poor man is one who fails to give much reaction to others, doesn’t like his job or care to do it well, or has to be watched by foremen, policemen, etc. So what he gives to society is meager and of poor quality; but he usually puts energy into demanding good pay, and consequently ordinarily receives much more than his fair share of conervete pay—of wealth. So as a rnle the successful man has already, before he comes to pay taxes, given pro- portionately more to society than the poor ones. So he ordinarily should pay a smaller fraction in taxes. It is a quantitative proposi- tion, of course with a few exceptions: the rigorous theory is that the man in a democracy who has deserved little should pay a larger frac- tion of concrete taxes if (as is usually practically unavoidably the case) he gets a larger fraction of concrete pay. —— And it is clear from the fundamental theory of taxation (the theory of That...x This...) that the best hope of achieving reasonably just taxation, which next to honest money is perhaps the most important economic balance wheel, lies in taxing people from several points of view. ]. e., no “‘single tax,’’ no solution of the infinite regress involved in taxing a single sort of unit of a man’s wealth is practically soluble very far out, and so it is better to try to average the important items of wealth. Any single thing, such as land, could theoretically furnish a just base ofall taxes. The practical difficulty with the land single tax is in determining just who owns or controls or uses a given bit of land (e. g., as one of thousands of equally difficult questions:- How much use does an aviation company make of the land it flies over; or may it drop monkey-wrenches anywhere free of charge?). That probable solution of this quantitative problem of the base of taxation is opposite that of the base of money (§168h); for it easy to deter- mine the actual controller of a given piece of actual money. And obviously, the foregoing general theory of taxation fits with the actual general practice in this country (except that we are a bit vague yet about putting a profiteer or financial aristocrat in jailif need be). So it would be intelligent, and save much money, to enunciate and practice those simple principles openly. 243 get repaid foratime. So obviously, any world state will have to be made largely on credit (J), by the able men who can work now for a benefit inthe future—just as most large busi- nesses are made. There would perhaps be an immediate **spiritual’’ return in some dropping of the tension of national distrust and refusal of credit (which distrust is concretely shown in expensive armaments); hunt many people are too defective nervously to see that (especially some armament niakers who are quite similar in every way to liquor dealers; §166h). And it is certain that some men will betray that trust: the aristocrat we have always with us. If a nation in the world state betrayed the trust we could not put it in jai] or an insane asylum; and the milder equivalent, ostra- cism or boycott, might not work; then we would have to kill it off more or less—perhaps a more unpleasant and expen- sive business than not having such a world-state obligation. e. As we have seen, democracy is a conscious effort to approach a balance, and truistically if successful prevents war—which is the social surgery needed to cure an unbalance which is bad (§149n)—the attempted cure for hell. When the pain of an unbalance becomes great, the nation with the weaker nervous system becomes maniacal first and starts the war, The nation that keeps on preparing for war more in- tensely than another nation openly admits its fear of the other; and such open indulgence in cowardice (footnote 170r) and babying of its “‘nerves’’ will truistically make it wear out its nervous systems, just as any coward who gives way to his fears gets panicky: relief from that pain of fearing—often becoming so crazy with that pain that it sincerely fancies the other nation at- tacked first. Obviously, any aristocracy, in consistence with its pseudo principle of repulsing the other nation and grab- bing from it “‘a place in the snn’’ and any other little thing, must keep piling up its *“preparedness’’ as much as it can (thus, by the unavoidable laws of nature as just seen, giving way to cowardice and destroying itself). A democracy tries to approach the balance, but it recognizes the inevitable nat- ural fact that always there must be a fringe of defective aristocrats at each end of society (8168 p); hence, demnc- racy forms a police force large enough to take care of the probable number of aristocrats who will go insane enough to need watching or become violent. But as that police force is an admission by the democracy that its educative efforts have inevitably failed of perfect success, it will truistically try to reduce the force. And that being in accord with natural law, all other advantages follow:- the democracy does not become cowardly, or panicky; it saves expense; etc. f. There are three sorts of extreme pacifists in theory (none in practice, as the theory is quite wrong and can’t work):- autocrats or militarists, socialists, and religious ob- jectors. (1) The theory of the autocrats or militarists is that they will prepare so thoroughly that they can or will lick the rest of the world, and thus there will be absolute peace. It doesn’t work, as we just saw, but it does superficially sound nice enough to delude those extremely pacific militarists. (Another pet delusion of those queer pacifists is that | pre- paredness’’ is national insurance. Insurance is distribution of arisk over Land 7. The risk of war is naturally distrib- uted over the wbole nation, so it is merely silly to talk of distributing it further. And as regards T distribution :- in- stead of storing up wealth, as insurance premiums, to pay for war when some other extreme pacifists become violent, they spend it on ‘‘preparedness,’”’ and then have to get more out of an impoverished nation. Buta police force is, intelli- gently, an admitted expense—what it costs a democracy for its failure to teach extreme pacifists to think.) (2) The so- cialists in theory are extreme pacifists in that they would UNIVERSE and it finally starts a war as a welcome. Three XIX §176g have everybody an official of a single world government, so that there would be absolute peace because there would be nobody to fight. Incidentally, they in practice will first wage a war of extermination on those who disagree. (3) The first two extreme pacifists claim they want absolute peace, and are willing to fight for it. The third sort is the religious objectors who are going to get absolute peace by refusing to fight. Obviously, their ‘religious, scruples’ amount to try- ing absolutely to confuse the One and the Many; also, they deny that anything can be intolerable and they thus practi- cally deny the One or religion (§169d), and force sane men to restrain them or kill them—which is war, merely under its zero name. So the difference between the aristocratic preparedness and the democratic preparedness is this:- the aristocrat has a fake panacea for war (in three guises) that actually produces or is an unbalance or disease for which war is one cure; so they consider it admirable to zxcrease their ‘““panacea’’ or armament: democratic preparedness recog- nizes that war is a last (or surgical) cure for a bad disease, a definite admission of democracy’s imperfection and hence an armament or police force that we want to keep as low as possible. The aristocrat boasts of his preparedness, and flaunts it in the face of the world: the democrat regrets the need of his preparedness, but tries to keep it adequate to deal with the probable number of rather crazy aristocrats. A genius with words can do the race an enormous ser- vice by inventing good distinctive names for the two things:- democratic preparedness and aristocratic preparedness. g. The next general quantitative result of a world state, or partial trial at one, is that it tends towards an economic balance, and so repudiates commercial exploiting or repul- sions. In short, as is definitely recognized in effect by the Constitution (Art. I, §X, 2), any tariffs or imposts, or duties on imports or exports, between the parts of a democracy tend to disrupt it and destroy life, and so are immoral and explic- itly forbidden. Asa truism there must be free trade (even though there is no formal world state) jf we are to be moral in our economic relations with other nations: the instinctive conclusion of mankind is glaringly to that effect, as is proved by the fact that at no time in history has appreciable mora] stigma attached to smuggling. A tariff for revenue only is an obvions logica] self-contradiction, and so spoils the brains of those who try to ‘believe’ it:- for it truistically by the infinite regress protects some industries. Also, a tar- iff that is merely thus largely for revenue is an indirect tax, and immoral on that ground. If “‘infant’’ industries need to be protected for a time (and they practically do, as will implicitly appear), a direct bounty is obviously the open, non-secret, moral] procedure. But that protection of infant industries is mora] only temporarily; it is immoral] and para- sitical for anyone to accept aid long, just as it is for a grown child to live on his parents—and as unlovely. (I have heard of “‘key’’ industries: any argument for continued pro- tection for such is merely the wailing of a spoiled baby lacking in resourcefulness and seli-reliance; for rigorously, no industry or part of the Many can be absolutely essential] or changeless.) In the long run, if you are unable to get better or-and more work delivered to you for a given price from me, than you can from any other laborer on earth, then truistically that laborer ought to do it for you:- for I am not of superior clay that you should take poorer work from me. You might today take my poorer work, 7f you thought that I would thus learn, and tomorrow give you so much better work than anybody else that you thus gained in the Jong run (that shows how a bounty for infant industry is right, just as it is economically right to support a child—and a volume of details on the two subjects is omitted:- e. g., the parents §176g XIX Three ordinarily get their money repayment for supporting a child directly from society at the time {not later from the child], the care of the child increasing their earning capacity). In the long run you are immorally wasting human life if you do not buy in the best market:- your life, the life of the better laborer, and that of the poorer by making him a privileged aristocratic parasite. So the intelligent, democratic way is obviously to stop putting up those immoral tariff barriers to the best market. We shall usually prefer to react with those closer to us if they actually prove themselves to be friends by giving us good work (they have the economic advantage under normal conditions of being at less expense for trans- portation, and our inspection of the goods). But if a ‘““heath- en’’ in the other hemisphere can prove himself the better man by overcoming that natural economic handicap, then he is a better friend than the slack, incompetent workman next door. The biological and other human ways in which poor workmen get the job in an aristocracy and then pay for their “‘privilege’’ are these:- They verbally tell the aristo- cratic, fiat ruler that they depend on his protecting them, and standing for their poor work; they thus acknowledge that the aristocrat is superior, and that they (al) tariff-protected business men who approve the tariff and all union-protected workmen who approve making the employer pay regular pay for poor work) are rather worthless, and they thus confirm the aristocrat in his power-madness at the expense of degrading themselves mentally—it is the road to uselessness. The aristo- crat is similarly debased by that self-abasing, incompetent, and lying adulation, and his business is always really in an unhealthy, running-down condition. The good business man obviously can not afford to be tariff-protected, as it makes him soft and flabby, and wastes his time running to Washing- ton with whines that not even a self-reliant baby would emit, and worst of all it costs him the publie’s good will. And in precisely the same way the labor unions can not afford their aristocratic game of protecting incompetents, h. The last general quantitative result of a world state, or partial one, which I shall consider explicitly is the racial one. Because of the comparative difficulty of transportation and communication in past ages, various races have stayed rather steadily in somewhat different environments (climates) and truistically have lived at different rates, and so are now biologically different in a way which can most intelligibly be expressed as different virtual ages. The difference is so slight as not to cause mutual sterility (mo doubt such sterility oc- curred in the past, and by the principles of periodicity nature promptly eliminated the weaker), and ta make it unprofitable to give specific comparison here of such ages. _Truistically intermarriage of those races produces a biological unbalance, just as the children of » couple of the same race wide apart in age are noticeably variable. Some of those half-breeds have little survival strength; a few are a mixture which is better than either parent stock (and of such half-breeds we spring). We have almost no knowledge of what crosses are good in the long run: it truistically clearly is silly to say that we imperatively must preserve racial ‘‘purity.’? And equally clearly and truistically one race is not essentially superior to another—mierely quantitatively different. Truistically, if we force races to refrain from intermarriage, that increases the difference, until inevitably the unbalance will precipitate a race war in which one race is exterminated—and the advo- cate of race purity has no real facts to show that it won’t be his race to go (I cheerfully agree that I have the usual human belief that it wouldn’t be my race; and that I like my racial qualities and wouldn’t care to take a chance on mixing them; but that is merely healthy emotion, and I retain, or have got, sense enough to know that I am ignorant of actual facts— UNIVERSE wlike nearly thoughtless rabbits. 244 and I have read Madison Grant’s ‘Passing of the Great Race,’’ and a lot of other such cheap, dualistic guesses. ) Sa a democratic state will, just as the Constitution does, take races as essentially equal but quautitatively unequal, and will let alone (§149m) the question of intermarriage until there are some more-definite facts. It will be grateful to the per- sons whose strength or foolhardiness or environment forces a crossing, for having furnished data. Jf we decide that we must not cross with a certain race, that means that we will exterminate them—or become hypocrites and be exterminated. i. Connected with that is the problem of birth control. The United States has over 35 inhabitants to the square mile —nearly 20 acres or ordinary city ““blocks’’ to each person. If present knowledge were intelligently and vigorously used our larid might be made to support 20 times that number. But practically, every increase of population causes some un- balancing which is often perceptible. Aristocrats hold that uunbalances should be increased, and consistently with that they often explicitly want the birth rate increased—ordinarily the more aristocratic, militaristic, and imperialistic a person is, the more he objects to what he calls race suicide. (That phrase “‘race suicide’’ is scarcely rational:- if I avoid getting fat I do not commit suicide, and a race that avoids over- growth does not; the phrase is stupidly used by aristocrats to beg the question as to actual facts.) The upper ten aris- tocrats of course want more people to lord it over and use as eannon fodder. And the submerged tenth aristocrats breed Neither have enough intel- ligence to understand democracy or temperance, but again in this case proceed on the pseudo principle that an unbalance is desirable—that if a little is good, more is better. Some few couples are geniuses at producing say as many as ten vigorous, useful children: but the ordinary family with five nowadays is a calamity to the state and early death to that parent who takes the responsibility seriously. In the old days large families were worse on both children and parents; but in those days people were so stupid that the majority blundered into an accidental death before thirty, so that quantity was then of more importance. Democracy requires a balanced degree of racial] increase. Perhaps we are up to the point in our history where the great and useful pioneering will be in quest of quality, to restore and if possible maintain the balance Quantity... < Quality.... That pioneering has already been begun as regards the race itself by the average person in this country—-which birth control is probably the most important symptom of our sound social health. Tbe pioneering in business ethics—the intelligent building-up and seeking of “good will’’—is perhaps the next. j. So it appears that a consciously formed world state will not necessarily end war. Any severe climatic variation is likely to cause war—and would, unless men were agile enough mentally to meet the change rapidly with appropriate balancing of Unselfishness... < Selfishness... A world democ- racy based on the sound principles of the Constitution will ordinarily prevent disturbances of much size—will ordinarily prevent a “‘war.’’ The chief danger will be the same as al- ways in the past:- a power-mad, selfish boss and citizens too unintelligent to size him up and to see where they will land if they follow him a little way on his primrose path to sudden glory and wealth. There is no automatic way to end war: it all depends on men in the end. Wars cure the worst un- balances by weeding out the worst aristocrats—and a new crop starts at once. A knowledge and use of democracy can keep the aristocrats from growing, by education if that is done well enough. And that is work. When we get out of balance with the environment there is in effect a “‘nat- ural’’ war called famine or-and pestilence. Democracy 24.5 involves keeping a tolerable balance with the environment (cf. footnote 175e). Part of that is called maintaining the standard of living; and roughly, in business the ‘standard of living’ is called overhead. The aristocrat dualistically fancies that such standard (including various heavy business expendi- tures for costly stationery and palatial furnishings, etc.) is a sacrosanct affair that must be maintained of itself. But an intelligent child can see that if that standard and over- head does not enable its possessor to react better, with both material and men, and thus do better than any “cheap foreign labor,’’ then that expense is in some degree a waste —a destructive evil instead of a good. 8177. a. Thus any democratic state involves us in quan- titative problems impossible of accurate solution, with grave perils on each side of the balance. That is what life is: we like it. Everything in the universe is engaged in the same sort of balancing, and in time wears out and changes into a different order structure, just as we all die—thus being a part of keeping the perfect balance of the whole. b. The race has for ages been increasing its life or hap- piness—extending its limits of conscious balance with the environment, and becoming more consciously God. Thus the race has grasped and enjoys the universe in a rough way, and has grasped the ““material’’ earth in a rather definite way; and has already substantially formed a more or less organized world state, thus also grasping its homan members in a rather definite way. Most of the race enjoy braving and balancing the dangers at those two limits or outer zones—and thrive on them, even though those dangers sound objectionable when explicitly described as in the last section. The spreading of the limits of consciousness into those dangers is an increase of the definiteness of relationship——of love. Because the race is as a verifiable fact now consciously related toa wide extent, UNIVERSE Appendix A we as a truism of that fact love the race unless we are de- fective. But there are a few of the race who get out into those danger zones and are so weakas to be damaged and be unable to get back to a balance, or see that they want to. They are the aristocrats—the submerged tenth on and as one dying fringe or breaking-up difference surface of the race, and the upper ten on the opposite fringe. Those fringes are where the consciousness of relationship or love begins to dim. But in a wide sense we see we love those failing and quitting aristocrats as being inevitable in the nature of things, and as interesting and entertaining horrible educative examples. ce. And that generally satisfactory condition of human affairs, with always some perceptible unbalances that are on the way to a balance if we take enough time into view, out- lines what we have seen in this book. The book is a de- scription of the universe, given chiefly in terms of humans because those are familiar and intelligible. It is a rigorous unification of the universe, because that infinite universe zs our ultimate selves—we being God in that religious aspect. That unification is expressed as the solution of the One and Many. The race for centuries has tacitly been using that solution or logic—knowing the principles and applying them to the objective world as science, and to ourselves as morality or democracy. d. The essentials may be briefly stated, although it re- quired a number of pages to make them positively evident :- The One is the Many. We grasp and are the One by working personally with the Many in a temperate or demo- cratic way. From the point of view of our feelings or sense of well-being that balanced rhythmie grasp of the One is happiness; from the point of view of our seeing or know- ing or intellect that balanced rhythmie grasp of the One is ineffable beauty. APPENDIX A ABBREVIATIONS No attempt is made to include ordinary abbreviations, or to in- clude those used in short passages wherein they are first explained (in several such cases abbreviations are used in a sense different from that listed below as their usual meaning). ‘“‘Ency. Brit.”? ‘“The Encyclopaedia Brittanica,’’ 11th ed. Daniell’s ‘‘Physics.’’? Alfred Daniell, ““A Text Book of the Principles of Physics,’’ 3rd ed. (1902). Marshall’s ‘‘Economics.’’ Alfred Marshall, ““Principles of Economics,’’ 6th ed. (1910). Watson’s ‘‘Physics.’’? W. Watson, ‘‘A Text-book of Phys- ies,”’ 5th impression (1904). Wood’s “‘Opties.”’ Robert W. Wood, ‘Physical Optics,’ Ist ed. (1904). ? eh Subscripts that are used in the text with several of the abbrevia- tions below, are given separately. A (1) a general symbol for any given thing; (2) chemical affinity, or intensive factor of dynamic molar energy. C variable numerical coefficient for molar or static masses. Ent entropy, or extensive factor in heat energy. Energy energy. F force. G variable numerical coefficient of ‘dynamic’ or gravitation masses; also sometimes used, as indicated by context, as the conventional gravity constant. H variable numerical coefficient for ‘dynamic’ heat; also used, as indicated by context, as orthodox heat constant. J variable numerical coefficient of ‘static’ heat: also used, as indicated by context, as constant Joule’s equivalent. K variable numerical coefficient of ‘static’ electricity; also used, as indicated by context, as the conventiona] con- stant specific inductive capacity. L length or space—one unit measure of length. M mass—specifically, one unit or part of the universe. P potential of electricity or intensive factor of elec. energy. Q quantity of electricity or extensive factor of elec. energy. Ra conventional constant used in heat. T time—one unit measure of time. Temp temperature, or intensive factor of heat energy. That that; anything, as compared with a This. This this; any given thing. U variable numerical coefficient of ‘dynamic’ electricity ; also used, as indicated by context, as the conventional constant permeability. V velocity. V, average velocity of light ina “‘vacunm’’ in our neigh- borhood. See §126b for other subscripts. W weight. e (1) current of electricity ; (2) see §82a. d ()) distance, same as L; (2) differential symbol. ConTINUED oN Next Pace e [subscript | zero or standard formal unit (S7Ib). r ’ Appendix A length, same as L. unit magnet pole. [subscript] dynamic. any number. pressure, UNIVERSE radius, same as LL, , [subscript] indicates a relationship word. ; [subscript] static. v volume. indicates infinite regress ($33g). APPENDIX B PERIODIC TABLE OF ELEMENTS 2 He 3-99 10 Ne | 20.2 | rr Na 23.00 19 K 39.10 24.32 WA 39.88 20 Ca 49.07 30 Zn 65.37 8 Cd ‘eas oa 54% \|55 Cs 112.40 |114.8 56 Ba |57 La 58Ce soPr 27.1 2t Sc 44.3 33 Ga | 32 Ge | 33 As 69.9 51 8b 120.2 50 Sa 49 In 118.7 130.2 | 132.81 137 .37|139-0 149.25140.6 144.3 67Ho 68 Er 69Tu 7o Yb 71Lu 72— 163.5 167.7'168.5 173.5 175.9 $27.5 60 Nd 63-62 5m 63 Eu 64 Gd 65 Tb 66 Ds 150.4 44 Ru 126.92 52 Te | 53 | | 157-3 159.2 162.5 760s 77 Ir 78 Pt 190.9 193.1 195.2 152 This periodie table of elements and their atomic numbers is adapted from Millikan’s, ‘‘The Eleetron,’’ published in 1917. The weights of elements not in the order of their atomic numbers are in italics. Hydrogen Helium Lithium Beryllium Boron Carbon Nitrogen Oxygen Fluorine Neon Sodium Magnesium Aluminium Silicon Phosphorus Sulphur Chlorine Argon Potassium Caleium Scandium Titanium Vanadium Chromium Manganese Tron Cobalt Nickel Copper Zine Gallium eM Ore WO SO RO ee ae Oo mM Oe mr oanrf WOH © 22 23 Q4 25 26 QT 28 29 30 31 32 Germanium 33 Arsenic 34 Selenium 35 Bromine 36 Krypton 37 Rubidium 38 Strontium 39 Yttrium 40 Zirconium 41 Niobium 42 Molybdenum 43 44. Rhuthenium 45 Rhodium 46 Palladium 47 Silver 48 Cadmium 49 Indium 50 Tin 51 Antimony 52 Tellurium 53 Todine 54 Xenon 55 Caesium 56 Barium 57 Lanthanum 58 Cerium 59 Praseodymium 60 Neodymium 61 62 Samarium 63 Europium 64 Gadolinium 65 Terbium 66 Dyprosium 67 Holmium 68 Erbium 69 Thulium 70 Ytterbium 71 Lutecium 12 73 Tantalum 74 Tungsten 15 — 76 Osmium 77 Iridium 78 Platinum 79 Gold 80 Mercury 81 Thallium 82 Lead 83 Bismuth 84 Polonium 85 86 Emanation 87 88 Radium 89 Aetinium 90 Thorium 91 Uranium X2 92 Uranium APPENDIX C GEOLOGIC TIME SCALE Prepared by H. F. Osborn and by C. A. Reeds after Schuchert. from Osborn’s Reproduced “Origin and Evolution of Life.’’ The times given are much too short MILLIONS Or YEARS 235 3Q MILLIONS YEARS 35 43 u - ROCKS GENERALLY METAMORPHOSED IGNEOUS PREOOMINANT ISNEOUS SECOMDARY ENTOMBED FOSSILS DIRECT EVIDENCE OF FORMER Lif ROCKS CHREFLY UNMETAMORPHOSCO SEQHMENTARY PREOOMINANT, RATIO 12, 18.000 000 YEARS SEDIMENTARY SECONDARY LIMESTONE IRON ORE, AND GRAPHITE INDIRECT EVIDENCE OF FORMER LIFE FOSSILS SCARCE 8 Cal RATIO 6, 9,000,000 YEARS “PRECAMBRIAN, RATIO 20. 30.000,000 YEARS ($112hi; XI}). | GUATERNARY TERTIARY UPPER CRE TACEO Us LOW! CRETACEOU {COMANCHEA AGE ! JURASSIC TRIASSIC g a a a Es _ v ent | 0 Ea — NS nermuee. | W = I | PERMIAN 8 PENNSYLVANIAN IUPPER 3 | cansonirencuss - 5 AGE OF AMPHIBIANS MISSISSIPPLAN wy . CAARTOMIFEROUS) SILURIAN PALAEOZOIC 3 + a 2 QF INVERTEGRATES ANIMIKIAN EVOLUTION OF HURONIAN INVERTEBRATES ALGOMIAN PROTEROZOIC SUDGURIAN LAURENTIAN EVOLUTION UNICELLULAR LIFE ARCHAEOZOIC (ARCHEAN) GRENVILLE (KEEWAWAI ICOUTCHICHING Q47 How to Use. ‘48b’ refers to section and paragraph; ‘f48b,’ to footnote; ‘Fb,’ to section and para- praphin Preface; ‘One,’ to Part One; ‘ii,’ to page ii in Introductions; ‘IX,’ to Chap. IX. This Index is not full. The names of per- sons are not always the actual legal names; the names of subjects are not always the act- ual names used in the text. The Index is a compromise, with no special consistency ex- cept in an attempted ready usefulness. It is not satisfactory to me, except in that it is the best I could do in a reasonable time. In theory it should be less so to the reader. aberration, 127, 17c; see Jight. absolute, 28b; see perfect. — zero, 80e, 114g, 134), 141f. abstract, 28f, 59. action at distance, f77b, 88a. —-reaction, 86e, 98b, 167; see balance. Adam and Eve, 100c. Adami, G. 145e. Adums, H. ete. f48b, 1355c, 156e, 157c. = War Sul loa. Ade, George, f167b. affinity (chem.) 74e, 134hj; see sol. sys. age, 146k-n; ages (geologic) App. C; see astronomy. agnosticism, 5, 22h, 23, 32, 35d, 40g, 88d, Ac, iv. Albertus Magnus, f48b. **Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland”’ (**Carroll’’) 23a, 99a, 167d. Ampere, A. M. 76, 74b, 77, 83f, 94g. analysis, 21b. Ananias (Biblical) 166q. Angell, James R. 155c. Angstrom, A. J. 121c. anthropocentricism, 73h, 100cd. applied or used, 85e. a priori and a posteriori, 163). Aquinas, Thomas, 24c, 46d, f48b, 151b. aristocrat, v, 7j, 14d, 37e, 48d, 85c, 88), 89i, 100c, 105d, 139a, 141h, 145e, 147e, 149r, 158g, 159f-n, 162di, 163f-h, 166q, 167h, 168-9, 171jkm, 173-4. Aristotle, 26g, f48b. armaments, 176d-f; see war. Arrhenius, 8S. A. 107a, 108b. art, 171; artistic temperament, 159g, 166pq, 168e. assimilation, 120h; see growth. assumption, 22, 88b, 97a. astral planes, 100g. astronomy, XII; ages, 111¢; velocities, 111; unified witb electricity, 135d; see solar system, ete. asymmetry, 98; see incommens., balan. Atherton, Gertrude, 155b, 1660q, 170k. athletics, 166f. atom, 74e, 15j, 89, 90, 119a; no con- stant —, 101j, 128e, f132a; getting energy out, 141; see Richards, etc. UNIVERSE INDEX attraction, repulsion, 13493; see gravity. authority, 162b, f167b. autocracy, 174; see aristocrat. Avogadro, Amedes, 89g. axis (filiar, and main) 98n. balance, 1l4c, 146s, 7j, 163, 177; temperance, genius, democracy. Balmer’s formula, 128de, 130f. banking, f168h. Bastian, H. Charlton, 144cd. Bateson, Wm. 147c. batteries, storage, f135c. behavioristie psychology, 490; Dewey. Being, 22, 98, 95e, 161b; assumption. Bergson, H. f165b, 20a, 64c. Berkeley, George, lc. Bernoulli’s theorem, 95, 98hi, 100d, 101g, 102, 114b, 126a; see fluid theo. Bible, 85c, 99a, 160d, 161b, 1635b, 170b, Ty biologists, British, 147, f100c. biology, XVI; definition, 142-3; organ, Jordan, Darwin, life, ete. birth, 144ij, 96d, 8m; control, 176i. Bjerknes, V. F. K. 94, 95d, 113b, 114b, 194f, 184k, 84e. *“blood and iron’’ 145, 163b. Bode’s Jaw, 117g, 128de. Bok, Edward, f167b. books, 491. boundary, 47, 55c, Two; see Vy. Boyden, U. A. 127k. Bradley, F. H. iv, v. Bragg, W. H. and son, 101j, 138h. breeding, 159}. brevity, 30g, 50h, 138f, Db. brokers (stock) 163h. Brooks, Wm. K. 147d. Brownian movement, 137cf. Bryce, James, 173h. Buckle, H. T. 490, 87b. Buddha, Buddhism, 39a, 157e; see Nirvana. business, 163gh, Fe, vi, vii, 173e; see labor, sizing up men, money, etc. ““business is business’’ 163g. butters-in, 167). see see see ether, see 49, 59eg, Cabot, Richard C. 149i0, 167b. ealeulus, 30b-f, 104h. Campbell], W. W. 171m. eancer, 149). capital, see Jabor, wealth, property. Carlyle, Thomas, 162d, 166p. Carnegie, Andrew, 94g, 168m. Carnegie Institution, F. Carnot, M. F. Sadi, 104. Carrel, Alexis, 146k. Carrington, Hereward, 101k. Index Cycl Castle, Wm. E. 147f. catastrophies, 100). Catholics, 24c, 46d, f48b, f49a, 86d, 149q, 174c. cause and effect, 86; caution, f 40g. Cavendish, Henry, 89}. cell (bielogic) 120h, 143d; (ether) 97d, Two; (nerve) 152c. center (of reference) 40f, 88], 100c. Chamberlin, T. C. le, 113ced, 117be, 118d, 122g-i, 144¢c. chemistry, 138g-i; see atom, etc. ehicken and egg, problem of, 109. Chinese, 17¢, 168h. chivalry, 170]-n. Christ, 6, 19¢, 24c, 29, 39h, 47i, 48b, 49, 891, 153fh, 155c, 159In, 160d, 162, 165, 167h, 168), 170bm. Christianity, see Christ, religion. Christian Science, 149q, 49a, 155. circular reasoning, 22, 35f; see logic. civilization, 166c, 171; see progress. classes (by legislation) 162i, 163f, 167h; (of men) XVIII, XIX, 178fi. classic Jogic, 23a; see logic. Clausius, R. J. E. le, 80-2, 100). climate, 99d, 112g-m, 122, 166c. coefficients, 71, IX, 68, 77d, 83f. cohesion, 47}; see friction, force. cold, astronomical bodies cold inside, see planets. cold light, 132. combustion, 141. comets, 120; see solar system. commensurability, 50; see incommens. commonsense, v, 2f, 39, 491t. competition, 1700; see balance, democ. Conklin, Edwin G. 147d. “Conrad, Joseph’’ 155b. conservation (of resources) 167k; of en- ergy) see energy, religion. constants, 50d, 82, 89k, 100c. 123d. Constitution of U.S. 173, 7j, 37d, 169h. continuity, 26, 86; see relationship, in- fmity, unification. contradiction, 26-7, 28e, 51; and Many. Cooke, Morris Lilewellyn, vi-vii, Gb, 114c, f167b, 163). cooperation, vii, 167; see balance. Copernicus, 40f. Coriat, I. H. 154c. courage, 170r, Fe, Gb, 150h, 176e. credit, 167k, 168h. Crehore, A. C. 134k. criterion of molar bodies, 105; see /j. culture, 166c, 171; see progress. cure, 148h. ““eurved’’ color, 128g; see Euclid. eycles, 50e, 101f, 144i, 149c, 164e, 166m. see relationship. see Que — space, 60; Cyni Index cynicism, 21b. Darwin, C. 87b, 89i, 144ch, 145, 147d. = G. Tl isd. death, 80m, 114g, 144i}, 1461, 163g. deism, 47i. democrat, XIX, 173-4, 167-70, 7j, 48¢, 49ru, 105d, 149r, 162. Democritus, 89c. Descartes, 24c, 46d, 134k, 151b. description, 85a. devil, 49f; see God. Dewey, John, iii-v, Cc, Gb, 15b, 17d, Qla, 22f, 23a, 35d, 87b, 490p, 1282, 1491, 151b, 154b, 161b, f£167b, 1744. difference surface, 98n, 47g, 80m. dimensions (of space) 59, 62, 63h, 78a; languages of different — 62; theory, 68; dimensional equations, f38c, 68. directions, 99b-d, 32b, 43f, 50e, 88k, 101i, 104j, 130b, 134d, 135c, 145¢, 146e, 1703; in light, 125a; elec. 134d. division of labor, 1700-q. divorce, 166no. dogmatism, 5, 39f, 44g, 48d, 85c. Doppler effect, 127g. Drude, P. K. L. 180b. dualist, 5b, 19, 21, 49, 89k, 104b; see materialist, aristocrat. Dunne, F. P. (““Mr. Dooley’’) f167b. dynaniic, 73, 77b, 98], IX; see static. Eastman, George, 168m. economics, 156d, 1700, XVIII, XIX; see Marshall, A., money, taxes, etc. Eddington, A. S. 74a, 107e, 112i. Eddy, Mary Baker Glover, 149q. Edison, Thomas A. 152f, f167b, 168m. education, 174fg, 163b; see learning. Ehrlich, Panl, 149¢. HKinstein, A. 66, vii, 36b, 42b, 57b, 100c), 125b, 127g-k, 128g, 134), 135c, f168v. elasticity, 97d, XI, 74f. electricity, XIV, 75-7, 15}; static, 134, mag. 185; see electron, Ampere, etc. electron, 89bf, 98y, 120h, 137bg. element, 101j, 118e, App. B; see har- monic periodicity, atom, etc. Ellis, Havelock, 155a. emotions, 153, 17d, 20d, 30g, f 94g. ‘*Rnevclopaedia Brittanica’’17a. energy, 15i, 1X, 39g, 100); getting — 139-41. entropy, 7lh, 77-82; 140de, 174a. equality, no quantitative, 105d; One and Many, quantitative. equation, 39a; see mathematics. error, man can not make, 25b. Erwin, M. 94, 84c, 96d, 98i, 101), 124, 126c, 128d, 134k. ether, 93-4, Two, 66a, 125d; see Being. ethics, 160, 170, XVIII. Euclid, Euclidian space and time, 60-2, 330, £38a, 57, 66, 87b, 104e. evil, 85e; see good. evolution, 145, 98p; see progress. increase of, 80, see UNIVERSE exact, no exact science, 40-2, 50, 66, 95d, 26g, 35fg, 36g, 52b, 82b, 85d, 881, 98], 100cl, 137e, 143c, 147g, 148b; see infinite regress. exaggeration, 43k. executives, {94g, 157c, 170p. expediency, 40k. experiments, 1, 84b, 85e, 88f), 158a; excessive, 137c-g; see proof. explanation, 40h, 85a. factors, 7le-gi, IX, Two. faculties, 154be, 159a. fairy tales, 167d. faith, 5, 40). fame, 168, 166f; see power-madness. Faraday, M. 87b, 89dj, 98i, 99); 130e. fear, 158g; see courage. feminism, 166o0-r, 170k. field, 98n; see tube of force, fluid theo. fighting, 145, 175e; see war. filament, 98n, Two. Filene, A. L. and E. A. 168g. Fisher, Dorothy Canfield, 155f, 166r, 167b, 170k, 171f, Ce. — Irving, f{168h; and Fiske, E. L. 146n. Fiske, John, 166). Fizeau, A. H. L. 124¢. Flournev, Theodore, 101k. fluid theories, 94, XIII. force, IX-XI; all forces known, 139; fields of, 89; residing, 73f; of words, 52e; see gravity, elec., love, etc. Ford, Henry, 47j, 159j, f167b, 168m. Foster, James H. f98g, £167b. fourth dimension, 62, 66g, 128¢. Franklin Institute, 127a. freedom, 169e; of speech, 169f-b, 173¢; of will, 157e-g. Frend, 154d-f, 156e. friction, 97h, 15f, 98c; see force. galaxy, 107-9, XII; gambling, f163h. Gantt, H. L. f£167b. Gautier, 134k. genius, 159e-n, f166d, 169h, 170ik. geocentricism, 100c; see center. geology, 122g¢-i. Germans, pre-war, Ic, 19a, 49, 147e, 164d, f 172c. Gibbons, James, Cardinal, f 49a. Gilbreth, F. B. and Lillian M. 163}. Gilman, Charlotte Perkins Stetson, 170q. glacial ages, 112g-m. glad game, see make believe. God, 2led, 25b, 29, 46-7, 98m, 104b, 123e, 140d, 153f, 158i, 159e-n, 161, 166m; see Trinity. Golden Age, 87b. Golden Rule, 162ei)j. Goldthwait, Joel E. 149ir. good, Good and Evil, XVIII, 160-1, 135¢c, 100). government, see Constitution, democrat, aristocrat; —~ ownership, 168i, 1700. Grace, Eugene G. f167b. spectrum, 128h-k. 948 grain theory, see Reynolds. grammar, 27e, f30b. gravity, 74, 134jk, 64d, 70, 75d, 75e, 83f, 91f, 103, 108, 120i, 158e, 146h; see solar system, Newton. Gresham’s law, f168h. growth, 980-q, Two, 76d, 80fm, 100m, 109, 120h, 146. guessing, 106; see quantitative. gyroscope theory, 96d. Haeckel, Ernest H. v. Hamilton, Alexander, 173h. — Sir Wm. R. 2g. Hale, George E. lc, 122e. *“Hall, Holworthy’’ 155b. hallucinations, f 166d. happiness, 163, XVIII. harmonie periodicity, harmonic propor- tions, 801], 83g, 84a, 100bj, 101j, 110a, 118e, 120f, 128d, 156c, 163), 170p, 176b. Hathaway, H. K. 168). lieat, 78-82, 188c-e; see entropy, ete. heaven, 123. hedonism, 160a, 161b. Hegel, G. W. F. iii, v. Heraclitus, 42b, 66h. heredity, 147. Hergesheimer, J. 155b. Hering, Carl, 53b. high cost of living, £168h, 176), 176g. Hinks, A. R. 107a. history, 165b, f 170d; Hobbes, Thomas, 167b. Homer, 171). Hoover, Herbert, f167b, 168m. Hopkins, E. M. 49r. housekeeping, 170p; see mother. Howe, E. W. 159i, f£167b. Hughes, Charles E. f173b. human nature changing, 147h. humanity, law of, 164d. humor, f 162a, 34b, 43k, 50h, 153f. Hurst, Fannie, 1355b. Huygens’s principle, 124d, 125b, 126, 128a, 158f. hypocrisy, see make helieve, aristocrat. hypotheses, 159b. Hyslop, J. H. 101k. hysteria, 37e, 101k, 154e, 166pq. [bsen; 1706, 171). idealism, v, 20, 49r, 160a, 161b, 163i; lit- erary idealism, 171f. identity, 28; see One and Many, logic. idolatry, 14d, 49q, 52c, 85e, 173b. ignorance, 5, 164c; see agnosticism. immortality, 152d-f, 101k, 123e, 144), 146k. implicit, implication, v, 52. incommensurability, 50, 125a, 126a, Two. increase of entropy, see entropy. individualism, 1711, vii; see democracy hysteria, power-madness, balance. industrial democracy, 170p. ineffable, iv, v, 34, 40k, f51h, 162c; see infinite regress. length of, 112m. 3 249 inertia, 88; see motion. infinite regress, 36gn, V, 20d, 24d, 42c, Sle, 52b, 53e, 6la, 72e, 76d, 77d, 96d, 100g, 101i, 135e, 141h, 1531, 173c. infinity, 43, 50g,24c; see number. Inquisition, 161b. insanity, 155ab, 159fg. intellect, 153, XVII]; see reason. intentions, good, 155f. interest (psychological) 159c. intuition, see intellect, Bergson. inverse square law, 76d, 73, 77cf, 80), 832, 94e, 156b; see structure. ion, 135; see atom. irrationalism, see agnosticism. James, Henry, f169h, 171f. — William, v, vi, 15b, 49p, 113d, 153hf, 155d, 156e, f165b. Job (Biblical) £165d, 166r. job, any religious, 166f; men. Jordan, David Starr, v-vi, Ce, Gb, le, Q3a, 84ce, 87b, £942, f100c, 143¢c, 145abe, 147d, 1356e, 167b. Joule, J. P. 79. judgment, 42d, 31a, iv. Judgment Day, 86d. judiciary, 174h. *“just and unjust’’ 1121. K, 75-7, 68c, 66f, 136. Kaiser, 25c, 50e, 85c, 88}, 137d. Kant, I. 4b, 19a, 104b, 108e, 113b, 161b. Kellogg, Vernon, vii, 147d. Kelvin (Wm. Thomson) 2g, 3b, 7e, 96df, 980, 101j, 112i, 148b. Keyser, Cassius J. 60c. Kidd, Benjamin, 166c. kinetic, 77h; theories, 89, X-XI, Iwo, 15}, 104. Klyce, Laura Kent, Ce. —§. Sa, 7i, f34c, 49t, 99d, 138g, 144), 152f, 153f, 158e, 159d, 162b, f 166d, 170m, £170r, 1711m, £172. Knight, Austin M. 129c. Kultur, 163gh, 171i. see sizing up labor, labor leaders, 174be, vii, 163h, 167k, 170p, 176g. lag, 101f, 132a, 138¢, 146g. laissez faire, 149mr. Lamarck, chevalier de, 147d. Landolt, H. 143c. Langmuir, Irving, 101). language, One; model of, VIII; of dif- ferent dimens. 62; see One and Many. Laplace, marquis de, 118e, 113c, 114c. Larmor, Sir Joseph, 79a, 80c. lawyers, lawyers’ law, vii, 163fg, 173. Leacock, Stephen, f167b. learning, way of, 158g, 159b. least action, 98m, 104fg. Le Bon, G. f132a, 134k. Lecky, W. E. H. f48b. Lee, Gerald Stanley, Cc, 159}, 162h, 165d, f167b, 171f. UNIVERSE Leibnitz, G. W. 30f. lever, 15f, 100m. life, 143-4, 5c, 112m, whole book; maximum, 166-7. light, XIII, 15j, 101k; formation of, 124-8; bending of, 125b, 127g; color, 126d; corpuscular, 130d; dispersion, 128-9; polarization, 130; reflection, 131; refraction, 1281; veloc. 36b, 127. — year, 107d. Lincoln, A. 34b, f94¢, 153f, 156e, 159n, 168}, £173b, 173h. line organization, 37f, 167h, 174c. literature, 99a, f169h, 171f. Little, Arthur D. £167b. “living, world owes a’’ 168p. Loeb, J. 146or. logic, One, 1V, VI, 4; Christ’s, 153h; necessity in, 34-5; rule, 43h-k, 44; users of valid, f167f; woman’s, 170b. logistics, 4a, 44h. Lorentz, H. A. 66, 1273. Lorimer, George H. f167b. love, 47b, 162, XVIII; see force. Luther, Martin, f 166d. machine, 15f, 21b, 47j, 50e, 86f, 98), 100m, 165d; language, 63i. magnetism, see elec.; personal, 101k. make believe, 155, 48d, 149i, f168hvii. Maine, Sir Henry J. S. f173bb. majority, 171k-m, 173¢. man, 46-7, Three; average, 6b, 171k-m; compared with woman, 170; great men, f167b; measurement of, 148, 140e; part of machines, 140de; theo- retical, 40k; see classes, sizing up m. Many, 14b, 65; see One and Many. marriage, 166)-r. Marshall, A. 84c, 156d, 163), f163h. = Jobn, ¢ 178b,-178h: Marx, Karl, 174. mass, IX, 96b; varies with velocity, 41, 66, 72e, Two. materialism, materialist, 49h, 80, 46de, 7, 51h, 66i, 88j, 98m, 100c, 137d, 145, 146e. mathematics, Be, 3, 9, 30, 36k, 39a, 48-4, 49p, 58, 60-2, 104k. inatter, IX, Two, 98m. Maxwell, J. C. 2g, 15d, 46c, 74f, 80f, 89, 90b, 95d, 98cijy, 104, 105, 134d, 135c, 140e. Mayo, W. J. and C. H. 149ir. measures, measurement, 2, 32, 36i, 491, 67, 84a, 101), 148. mechanics, 86f, VIII, 98, Two, 9, vi; gravity, f74b and see gravity. medicine, 149. memory, 158, 36f. Mendelism, 145e, 147g. Merriam, John C. Fd. Metchnikoff, E. 144), 146n. meteor, meteorite, 120jk. method, 86, One; see trick of words. Michelson-Morley experiment, 66ag, 1272). Inodex Paci middleman, 1700, Fi. militarist, f170r, 176f, 52c; see aristocrat. Mill, J. S. 490. millennium, 123. Miller, Eugene, 84c, 113d. Millikan, R. A. 41¢c, 89h, 128e, 137cf. mind, 153, XVII; and matter, 150fg. Mitchell, S. Weir, 101k, 149i. modesty, 5b, f94g, 156e. inolecule, see atom, structure. money, 168. monism, 49, 17c, v. Montaigne, M. de, f167b. Moore, Benjamin, 144ce. Moseley’s law, 12Sek, 130f. Moses, 173b. motion, 36], 72a, 73h, f98d; 87-8, lig. mother, 159i. Muensterberg, H. 151b, f165b. music, 101f; see harmonic periodicity. mvstery, 4c, 40}, 1001. mystic, 20, iv, 34, 49, 7la, 73b, 88c, 90d, 100h, 130d, 158e. laws of, name, 35e, 48, 49r, 76d, 90; Napoleon I, f 94g. nebula, 107, XII; nebulosity, 121. negative (— form easier) 41, 88cd, 173b. neighbor, 162; see ethics. Newcomb, Simon, 128d. newspapers, 158g, 173h. Newton, I. 74, 87-8, 2a, 15g, 30f, 49p, 64d, 66b, 75a, 77i, 83f, 89i, 93, 97e, 98m, 100In, ll4c, 117g, 127), 134jk, 136d, 163}. New York, 99b, 101k, 123a, 159n. Nietzsche, F. W. 49ei, 145a, 162h, 163h. Nirvana, 43e, 88], 163b; see Buddha. non-Euclidian space, see Euclid. Nordmann, C. 197f. Norris, Kathleen, 155b. Northrup, E. F. 102, 117f, 194f. nova, 117d. number, 43, 26, 36h, 44, 50, 55, 58. see logic. nebular theory, 113. observation, 22i. Ohm’s law, 136, 73a, 77i. One, One and Many, 14-16, 28, 49, 157, One, whole book. Onnes, H. K. 141f. ontology, sce Being, ether. opportunity, 138d, 166f, 40k. optimism, 149f. oratory, f 28h. orders of structure, see structure. organism, XVI, 15f, 86df; see struct- ure; organs, 146hi. Osborn, H. F. 112h-j, 147h, App. C. Ostwald, W. 137e, 147e. overeating, 146n. *‘overhead’’ 176}. overrunning, 101f; see incommensurab. pXv, 82-3, 71i. pacifists, 176f. Pain Index pain, 163; see good. panacea, 149¢. panic, business, f168h, Fe. pantheism, 47i. parallels, 60. paranoia, 37e, 158g. parasite, 149f, 155c, 1660p; see aristoc. Paton, Stewart, 171m. patience, 176r. Patten, Wm. lc, 84c, 145abe, 147d. Paul, Paulineism, 6c, 89bi, 161b, 165b, 1660, 167gh, 171f; see Christ. payment, 168, 89k. Pearson, Karl, 49p. Pepper, George Wharton, f173b. perfect, 101i, 104b; gas, 82; see ex- act, One and Many. periodicity, see harmonic periodicity. periodic table, 80], 100}, 119, 144d, App. B. permeability, see U. Perrin, M. Jean, 137cf. personality, person, 42d, 47ij, 86d, 101k, 152ef. pessimism, 149f. phenomenon, 980, 139b. philosophy, 39, iii, 7d, 52h, 66h, 88f, 89c. phlogiston, 15). physicians, 149. physics, physical science, 67a, 68e-i, IX, Two. planetesimal, 113, 115, 126k. planets, 117f (see solar system); cold inside, 119a, 122]; direc. of revo. 112c. Plato, le, f48b. play, 167c-m; see democracy. Plotinus, 15c. pluralism, 17b; poetry, f165d. Poincare, J. H. 3c, 30b. **Pollyanna’’ 149f, f 168hbvii. pope, see aristocrat, theologian, Porter, Eleanor H. 1409f. Portier, Panl, 146i. possible, 101k; see quantitative. potential, 73h, 76, 134b, 146e; — en- ergy, 801; infinite, zero, 80, 99b-d; of man, 140e. power, 73h (see energy): human, 166df, 168k], 173h; see rebirth, power-mad. power-madness, 168], 173e, 174b, 176, 85c, 139a. pragmatism, 49p, 156e. prayer, 167d. prediction, 85d. Prince, Morton, 154c. principle, 147e, 169; see qualitative. printing, typography, E, F, f34c, 40g. privilege, 48d; see aristocrat. problem, see solution, One and Many. progress, 98p, 147k, 170k. prohibition, 166h. proof, 35, 22, 49h, 50e, 53e, 88). property (physics) 56, 88bd, 119c, 128ef; (wealth) £175c. prophet, prophecy, 85d. see materialist, logic. UNIVERSE prosperity, 164b; see power-madness. protection (tariff) 170k, 176dg. psychic phenomena, 161k, 152f. psychology, XVII; modern, 154c; see will, mind, ete. Ptolemaic astronomy, 100c, 127i. punishment, penology, 168q. Puritan, 135c, 149e, 156e. purpose, 5, 42d, 100), 101f, 144h. qualitative, 40, iii, 5, 66, 148, 162i; see One. quantitative, 40, iii, 4e, 37, 66, 148, 162i; see Many. quitters, 2lb, 159. race, f170j, Three; end of, 1121; puri- ty and war, 176h. radioactivity, 119a, 141g. Ramsey, Sir Wm. 138h. realism, 20; literary, 171f. reality, 49g, 100c, iii; see truth. reason, reasoning, 25a, 153be; induc- tive and deductive, 163j; see logic. rebirth, 162, 153f-h, 28h, 46h, 48e, 85b, 98m, 149q, 166dfh, 168], 17Ic. Reeve, S. A. 84c, 89be, 92, 93e, 97, 100c, 113c, 1700. regress, see infinite regress. reincarnation, 158e. relationship, 28fgh, 44ef, 47h, 57, 583. relativity, 66; of color, 128g; see Ein- stein. religion, 39, 6, 85b, 160cd; any job re- ligious, 166f; see rebirth, ethics, One, Trinity, Christ, theologian. responsibility, 164e, XVITI. rest, 36] (see static); 167m (see democ. ). reverse, reversal, 32b, 50e, 98k, 104), 135c. Reynolds, Osborne, 91, 49g, 84c, 87b, 89be, 93e, 95d, 97, 100c, 104j, 126c, 134k, 145c, 147c. rhetoric, 52gh. rhythm, see balance. Richards, T. W. 81-3, Ce, le, 23a, S4b, 89, 90c, 92b, I3f, 100c, 119d, 138h, 156b. riddle of universe, 14de, 40hj, 49k. Riley, Woodbridge, 15b. ring, single surface, VIII. Ritter, Wm. E. 84c, 145abe, 147d. ritual, 167d, 171j, 97b. Rockefeller, John D. 159j, 168m. rotary engine, 62i. Rowland, H. A. 135a. Russell, Bertrand, 3c, lic, 44d, 62f. Rutherford, E. 138h. Ryan, J. A. f48b, 166d. salvation, see rebirth. sanctions, 173be. Saturn, 113, 118-9. Schwab, Charles M. £167b, 168m. science, 39, 85ce, iv, vi, vii, 2,10, 28a, 165b, whole book. scientific management, 168}; see Taylor. 250 *‘serap of paper’’ 35c, f48b, 147e. secondaries, 98w; see structure. Sedgwick, Ellery, f167b. selfish, see aristocrat. self-preservation, law of, 164d, f175e. sentence, 31-3, 37. separation, 26; see dualism. sex, 146, 98p, 154df, 166)-], 170. Shakespeare, 155b. sharp distinctions, ete. 52. Shaw, James B. 2g, 3c. Sidgwick, Alfred, 49p. sin, 164c, 163. Singer, I. 161b, 167h. single surface ring, VIII. simple, 71h. sizing up men, Fe, 52c, 148, 157c, 162i, 167], 170, 176a; see measures. snobs, 135c. socialism, 175, 149}; see aristocrat. sociology, 169, XVIII, XIX; social en- vironment, 166c. Socrates, 166p, 167k. Soddy, F. 138h. solar system, 110-22; birth, 111; end, 112f, 120a; gravity in, 1138, 114¢c; retrograde motions, 118d; _ see plan- etesimal, planets, sun, etc. Sollas, W. J. 11h. solution of any problem, 159, 33g, 40k. soul, 152d, 153k, 46; woman’s, 170h. sovereignty, 47h, 173bh. space, V, 32g, 36, One; space and time inseparable, 64, 150; see time. specialist, vii, 188g, 149k, 1'700-q. spectrum, 128, 156c; of smells, 138d; see harmonic periodicity. Spencer, Herbert, 36b, 144h. Stallo, J. B. 49p. standard universe, 28b; see nniverse. static, static and dynamic, 73, f 74h, f7G6a, 77b, 98}, 108d, 133, 135c, 138f, 150g. Stefan’s law, 79c. Steinmetz, C. P. 148c. Storey, M. 163g. storms, 120e, 122c. structure, 15f, 86f, 76d, 83g, 100ej, 101i, 105, 110e, 128ef, 144c, 158c; see per- son, machine. subconscious, 153b, 15+. subjectivism, iv, v. submerged tenth, 168p; subscripts, 71b. Substance, 77i; see matter, Being. sun, see solar system; heat of, 115; spots, 120e, 122de. Sunday, Wm. A. 166h. Sundman, 83c. superman, 145c. surgery, 149rn, 176e. swearing, 43k. Swedenborg, E. 98m, f 166d. symbol, 30, 53e. systems, Ab, 20b, 47h. ee Taft, Wm. H. 163g, 173b, £167b. see aristocrat. 251 tariff, 170k, 176dg. Tarkington, Booth, f167b. tautology, 34, dle. Taylor, Frederick W. 168), Cc, f 94g, f167b, 162hi, 163), 174¢. taxes, 168in, 175e, f 176d. teleology, 42d; see purpose. telepathy, 101k, 146h, 152f. temperance, 149e, 50f, f£166d; see bal- ance. temperature, 77-82, 71b, 110, 153d; see heat, entropy. theologian, theology, vii, 6, 39g, 48b, 49, 107h, 1443, 160d, 171lc; see aris- tocrat, Christ, Trinity, rebirth. theory, see qualitative; physical theo- ries, X; defects of orthodox, 96. Theresa, St. 20d, 170m. thermodynamics, see heat, entropy. Thompson, J. Arthur, 147c. — Sanford FE. 163). Thomson, Sir J. J. Ce, 15), 66b, 77b, 89h, 90c, 98ij, 100c, 118e, 137b, 138h. three bodies, problem of, 83. Tikhoff, 127f. time, time and space, 36, 33g, V, 150-1, 158; economy of, 165; see space. tips, 168¢. titles, 167h, 1680. toleration, 169. Tolstoy, 162h, 167gi. transcendentalist, iv, 36k. ‘Transcript, Boston Evening’’ 14d. trick of words, iii, 2f, 9, 12, 20a, 98m. Trinity, 24c, 27-9, 43h, 48-9, 62, 71, 88, 134aj, 151b, 157, 171be. tropism, 158e, 146e. truism, 35f, 12; see logic, identity. UNIVERSE truth, 28f, 47h, 49ist, 581; tube of force, 98i. Tunzlemann, G. W. de, 74af, 135d. Turner, 122e. two bodies, problem of, 83, 98e. see reality. U, 75-7, 136; see electricity, unifica- tion, inverse square. unification, 74f, IX, iii, A, 9, 66dh, 74d, 77g, 136, 138¢. unit, 40c, 69b; see measurement, time, space, etc. universals, 20c. universe, 25b; infinite ‘“‘number’’ of, 100g; outside of, 47fg, 100e (see boundary); see One and Many, ete. unknown, unknowable, 4c, 36b, 40); see agnosticism. upper ten, 168p; see aristocrat. Utopias, 123. ? vacuum tube phenomena, 135, 1l4lg. value, 168; see payment, money. Vance, 163g. vibrations, see fluid theories, light. V;, 100cf, 74d, 105a, 152a; see light. volcano, 120e, 122i. Vorse, Mary Heaton (Mrs. O’Brien), 166r, f167b, 170k. vortex whirls, 90d, XI, Two. Waals, J. D. Van der, 81-2, 84b, 89d, 104, 145e. Walsh, J. J. f48b, 48d, 167d. Wanamaker, John, f167b, 168m. war, 176, 173abd, 174e, 35d; see mili- tarist, aristocrat, ““blood and iron.”’ Ward, James, 150c, 151b, f165b. Index Zoro Warren, Maude Radford, 166r, f167b, 170k. waves, 98y, XIII; see fluid theories. wealth, inheritance of, 167h, 168m-o, 173i, f175e. weight, 70-1; see atom. Weismann, A. 147. Wells, H. G. 29c, 49a. whirls, XI, Two; experimental, 101-2. White, A. D. 48d. Whitehead, A. N. 62f. Whitman, Walt, 169h, I71fj. Wilde, Oscar, 158g. will, 157. Wilson, Edmund B. 147d. — Harry Leon, f167b. — Woodrow, 159d, 164bd, 167g)k, 171f, f172c, 173e, 174be. woman, see feminism, man. Wood, R. W. 130b. Woodward, R. S. F, 171m. words, iv, 27-8; cheap, 168i; inflection of, f30b; have force, 52e; see logic, sentence. work, 167c-m; see democracy. world state, 176-7. worry, 156e, 170r. worship, 167d. conservation of, 137c-g; objectionable, f£174c; X-rays, 101jk, 128ek. Zeeman effect, 130e. Zeno, 15g, 94d; see One and Many. zero, 43; see infinity, number. zodiacal light, 121. Zoroaster, 32b. : } at = 8 © = spas» a s UJ ‘ al = = - " Vives _ -_ _s — A - ' - . i 8 “. J ; n 4 s A - ne 7 A ae . a ie i A,